JCll I III Class and Nation, A    Historically and in

V llil the Current Crisis

Class and Nation

Historically and in the Current Crisis

by Samir Amin

Translated by Susan Kaplow


r

London Heinemann Ibadan Nairobi


Heinemann Educational Books Ltd 22 Bedford Square, London WC1B 3HH P.M.B. 5205, Ibadan P.O. Box45314, Nairobi

EDINBURGH MELBOURNE AUCKLAND HONG KONG SINGAPORE KUALA LUMPUR NEW DELHI KINGSTON PORT OF SPAIN

0 435 96050 4 (cased)

0 435 96051 2 (paper)

First published 1980 © Monthly Review Press 1980

1


| DORSET SSSSTWE OF j KI8HEB iON LEARk>#& iSOJfi >2

141488


S x

Printed in the United States of America

Contents

Introduction vii Chapter 1

Classes, Nations, and the State in Historical Materialism 1

Chapter 2

Communal Formations    36

Chapter 3

Tributary Formations 46 Chapter 4

Unequal Development in the Capitalist Transition and in the Bourgeois Revolution 71

Chapter 5

104


Unequal Development in the Capitalist Centers Chapter 6

Center and Periphery in the Capitalist System:

The N ational Question T oday    131

Chapter 7

National Liberation and the Socialist Transition:

Is the Bourgeoisie Still a Rising Class? 182

vi Contents Chapter 8

The Theory of Imperialism

and the Contemporary Crisis 225

Conclusion

Revolution or Decadence? Thoughts on the Transition from One Mode of Production to Another 249

References Index 283

Introduction

A reader once remarked that my works deal with three sets of problems: (a) concrete analyses of the situation of third world countries (Egypt, the Maghreb, West Africa, the Congo), (b) a theory of capitalist accumulation on a world scale, and (c) an interpretation of historical materialism. Indeed, this classification also corresponds to the sequence of my work. Doubtless, concrete analysis of a situation is never neutral; it always implicitly entails a theory. The first of my analyses (Nassarian Egypt, West Africa, the neocolonial Congo and Maghreb, and allegedly socialist attempts to break with imperialist domination) were in large part based on a theoretical interpretation of imperialism. This interpretation, formulated between 1954 and 1957, was questionable, due to the inadequacies of the Marxism which prevailed in the 1950s, inadequacies which marked my own intellectual and political formation.

The theory in question enabled me to criticize bourgeois theoretical explanations of underdevelopment but did not enjoin a practical political elaboration of substituting national liberation movements for bourgeois nationalist politics. I produced my first works, concerning the Arab and African countries indicated, between 1960 and 1967; they suffered from this limitation. This unsatisfactory state of affairs obliged me to reexamine the theory of imperialism, which in turn brought me to rewrite (Unequal Development) and to further explore (Unequal Exchange and the Law of Value) the theory of accumulation in the years 1968-1973.

This was also the time of the clear failure of revisionist Marxism and, with the cultural revolution in China, of the elaboration of a global alternative. These favorable conditions led me to reconsider the most basic questions of historical materialism. Imperialism and Unequal Development, The Arab Nation, The Law of Value and Historical Materialism, written, as was this work, between 1973 and 1978, contain my interpretations of historical materialism. They also reexamine, in light of these interpretations, the concrete situations which most interest me: those of the third world in general and of Africa and the Arab world in particular.

If I were to summarize what seems essential to me in this study, I would emphasize the following points.

From the beginning, there have been two competing interpretations of historical materialism. The first virtually reduces the method to a linear economic determinism: the development of the productive forces automatically brings about the necessary adjustment in the relations of production by means of social revolutions, the makers of which lay bare historical necessity. Then the political and ideological superstructure is transformed to meet the requirements of the reproduction of the relations of production. The other interpretation emphasizes the double dialectic of forces and relations of production on the one hand and of these latter and the superstructure on the other.

The first interpretation assimilates laws of social evolution to laws of nature. From Engels’ attempt at a Dialectics of Nature to the positivist interpretation of Kautsky, from Bolshevism itself to the Soviet dia-mat (dialectical materialism), this interpretation pursues the philosophical work of the Enlightenment and constitutes the radical bourgeois interpretation of Marxism. The second interpretation contrasts the objective character of natural laws with the combined objective-subjective character of social laws.

The first interpretation either fails to deal with alienation or extends it to all of human history. Alienation thus becomes the product of a human nature which transcends the history of social systems; it has its roots in anthropology, that is, in the permanent relation between humanity and nature. History develops by “the force of circumstance.” The idea which people (or classes) have that they make history is naive: the scope of their apparent freedom is narrow because the determinism of technical progress weighs so heavily. The second interpretation leads us to distinguish two levels of alienation: (1) that which results from the permanence of the humanity-nature relation, a relation which transcends social modes, defines human nature in its permanent dimension but does not have a direct role in the evolution of social history; i.e., anthropological alienation, and (2) that which comprises the ideological superstructure of societies, or social alienation.

Attempts to detail the successive contents of this social alienation led to the conclusion that all precapitalist social class systems had the same type of social alienation, which I consider to be alienation in nature. Its characteristics derive, on the one hand, from the transparency of the economic relations of exploitations and, on the other hand, from the limited degree of mastery over nature at the corresponding levels of development of the productive forces. This social alienation necessarily had an absolute, religious character, due to the dominant place of ideology in social reproduction. In contrast, social alienation under capitalism is produced in part by the growing opacity of economic relations due to the generalization of commodity relations and in part by the qualitatively higher degree of mastery over nature. Commodity alienation thus replaces nature, with the economy as the external force which determines social evolution. The struggle for the abolition of exploitation and of classes entails liberation from economic determinism. Communism must put an end to social alienation, although it cannot abolish anthropological alienation.

This interpretation reasserts the unity of universal history. This unity is not to be found in an overly detailed succession of modes of production. The classic line of development—slavery-feudalism-capitalism—is not only peculiar but is also largely mythical. The opposition between a European and a so-called Asian line belongs to a family of Eurocentric philosophies of history. Unity is recreated by the necessary succession of three families of modes of production: the family of communal modes, that of tributary modes, and the capitalist mode, the first to have universal characteristics. The unity of the family of tributary modes is expressed in the universal character of social alienation in nature, in contrast to the social commodity alienation of capitalism.

The peculiarity of Western history in this perspective resides exclusively in the incomplete character of its specific form of the tributary mode, the feudal mode, which was produced by its combination with communal modes.

My intention in developing these general reflections on history is to propose a number of conclusions of a general and theoretical nature concerning the relations among class struggles—classes being defined in the framework of the economic formations which control the major, successive social systems and within which the dialectic of class struggle operates. This framework seems to be defined primarily by the state, the reality of which may cross-cut other realities depending on circumstances, either those of the nation or those of the ethnic group.

Current political preoccupations furnish inspiration. Recent developments in our world everywhere underline the importance of the nation and of the state: the class struggle is the motive force of history but it occurs within a state-national framework which sets its scope, its modalities, and its outcomes.

This book first presents a system of theoretical concepts concerning these questions, then a series of accounts which follow the historical sequence of evolution. This is the reverse of the order in which I did research, as I began with reflections and observations about the contemporary world (imperialism, national liberation, socialist construction) and went back to the theoretical analysis of capitalism (and particularly of the dialectic between class struggle and economic laws in the capitalist mode) and then to the history of its gradual establishment (the mercantilist and then the preimperialist periods during which the laws of unequal development operated in the then forming state-national framework). The lessons derived from this twofold series of experiences (the transition to socialism and the transition to capitalism) have suggested certain theses which seem to throw new light on earlier periods, those of precapitalist societies and those of transitions to class societies. This second test of principles in the light of facts enables me to further elaborate them.

The first chapter presents the system of concepts and the relations among state, nation, and economy. The rest analyzes unequal development: Chapters 2 and 3 as it occurred in precapitalist formations, Chapters 4 and 5 as it took place in the bourgeois revolution and the capitalist centers, and Chapters 6, 7, and 8 as it takes place in the imperialist system and the socialist transition.

Chapter 1

Classes, Nations, and the State in Historical Materialism

History is a weapon in the ideological battle between those who want to change society (a society in a given sense) and those who want to maintain its basic features. I do not believe the pronouncements of those who claim to be above the fray, because people make history, albeit within objectively determined conditions. In fact, social laws do not operate like natural laws. And I do not believe in a single cosmogony embracing nature and society— even when it goes under the name of a materialist dialectic.

On the contrary, those who want to change society necessarily have ideas of a higher quality than those who wish to keep it from changing. This is because society changes. Those who want to stop its motion must therefore ignore the evidence. To do this, they encumber thought with so much detail as to justify their refusal to abstract and generalize, although these are part of any scientific attitude. They rely instead on moral reflection—Platonic or Con-fucian. But those who want to change society are not gods living outside of it: there is a wide margin between the goals that they think they are adopting, those that they really (often implicitly) adopt, and the results obtained.

I will try here to make an inventory of what history teaches us. This will be provisional, modest, but dangerous in that it invites all manner of criticism. It is based on the presupposition that only the present gives meaning to the past. I share the viewpoint of those who want a classless society. Further, I contend that the struggle for social liberation from class exploitation is indissolubly linked to the national liberation struggle of the people of Asia and Africa.

The inventory can be presented in the form of seven theses, which will be elaborated in this book. The theses and their theoretical conclusions can be summarized as follows:

First thesis: universal history can be understood. The best narrative history, using an eclectic, empirical method, can offer only immediate explanations: it invokes multiple, direct, causal connections operating on different planes (a certain ideology accounts for a particular behavior, a given economic fact causes a certain development, etc.). It is possible to go beyond this level by basing an analysis on a universally applicable set of concepts, those of historical materialism. These concepts are not given a priori but are deduced from history itself. In the evolution of all human societies we can identify several major universal tendencies resulting from the same basic dialectic, namely, that between productive forces and relations of production.

Second thesis: universal history is always the history of unequal development. Unequal development is universal, although its character, sphere of operation, and form are not merely infinite rearrangements of a few simple laws. A periodization of history must be based on the dialectic between general tendencies and the unequal development expressing these tendencies.

Third thesis: history is, in the final analysis, the history of class struggle. Class relations dialectically define the modes of production which constitute successive social formations, corresponding to different levels in the development of the productive forces. But these classes are contained in a specific society, bounded by the borders of the state and, sometimes, of the nation.

Fourth thesis: societies constitute a system of social formations when they are so closely interrelated that their class oppositions and alliances can no longer validly be analyzed at the societal level but must be studied at the global level of the system. In particular, the contemporary world is a system, that of imperialism.

Fifth thesis: the social reproduction of capitalist society cannot be understood by looking only at the internal economic workings of the nation-states of the capitalist world system. To be understood, social reproduction involves the interference at the level of the state in the economic regulation and application of the class struggle-economic laws dialectic not to each nation-state but to the system as a whole.

Sixth thesis: the existence of nations raises the national question, and the process of unequal development makes this question particularly acute in the development of class struggles. Thus it is important to distinguish between bourgeois and proletarian tendencies with regard to how the national question is posed and resolved.

Seventh thesis: although the tendency to homogenization which characterizes the capitalist system operates by contradiction (homogenization and inequality), it has powerful ideological effects. The ideology of “universal culture” thus needs constant reexamination as it evolves through successive forms and phases.

I. The particular and the universal in history

1. The fundamental concepts of historical materialism have scientific value only to the extent that they possess universal analytical applicability. It follows that these concepts must be abstracted from universal history, and not from a particular segment of it. The concepts of mode of production, social formation, infrastructure, superstructure, social classes, and so on have this universal validity. On the other hand, the feudal mode of production is not necessarily valid universally, because it is abstracted from one part of history, that of Europe. To state in advance that feudalism is a universal category and to try to force the reality of other societies into this predefined mold is to turn one’s back on the scientific spirit. The failure to use the whole of human history from which to derive universal concepts leads to talk of “the irreducibility of civilizations, ” talk which is irrational and, finally, racist.

From this perspective, the great lesson of history is the universality of the basic laws that govern human societies, European and others. Here Marx gave us only the first elements, although the basic ones, of historical materialism. The level of knowledge during his lifetime and the prevailing ignorance about the nonEuropean world limited Marx’s ability to develop these elements. He was also limited by his own experience of social struggles, struggles which only became really widespread after his death. I stress this in the belief that the major source of knowledge is action: any other position leads to rigid dogmatism and practical impotence.

Thus the participation of the peoples of Asia and Africa in capitalist and socialist history has enriched historical materialism. The struggle against narrow interpretations of Marxism, against West-centered reductionism, is part of the struggle for social and national liberation, of the struggle against ideological imperialism.

2.    Historical materialism requires us to accept (1) that the development of the productive forces controls, in the final analysis, the relations of production, although it needs to be made clear whether we are talking about the actual development of existing productive forces or their potential development; and (2) that all human societies have gone through and will go through stages that, despite their diversity of form, are basically similar. The problem is correctly to identify these stages, on the basis of human history as a whole.

I propose the following schema: (1) All human societies have gone through three consecutive stages: (a) primitive communism, (b) the tributary mode of production, and (c) capitalism. They will all reach a fourth stage: communism. (2) Each of these three phases is separated from the one following it by a period of transition: (a) the period of communal modes of production, (b) the period of the transition to capitalism. And all societies are going through or will go through a third period (called socialist) of transition to communism. (3) Capitalism, like communism, is not an accident or an exception but an objective and necessary rule.

3.    Primitive communism, as Guy Dhoquois has defined it, is the “negation of necessary origin” (82-7).* It is impossible to conceive of the transition from animal to human without this stage. During this transition certain decisive transformations took place, the effects of which still remain and perhaps always will remain (that is, independently of social systems in that humans, as a species distinct from animals, transcend social systems). This means simply that certain of these characteristics may survive into communism. What are these characteristics? We know almost nothing about them, and anthropology has little to teach us on the subject because this stage is irrevocably lost. At best, certain recognizable elements in a handful of paleolithic societies may inspire philosophical and imaginative psychological speculation. But the danger of scientism is very strong here because we are and will remain unsure about the most elementary data.

4. The discussion of the stage I have called tributary is far more conclusive. If it is useful to compartmentalize by academic areas, this stage belongs to the historians and not the anthropologists. In it, we are dealing with the history of all civilizations based manifestly and indisputably on (1) considerable development of the productive forces—settled agriculture beyond the subsistence stage, a substantial and guaranteed surplus, and significant, rich, and varied nonagricultural activities (crafts) employing a range of technical knowledge and tools, although not machines; (2) nonproductive activities on a level corresponding to the size of the surplus;

(3) division into social classes on this economic base; and (4) a developed state (city, kingdom, or empire) that transcends village reality.

A number of things can be said about this stage. First, it takes a wide variety of forms, all of which have common characteristics in that the extraction of surplus labor is controlled by the dominance of the superstructure within a society based on use value. Second, the basic mode of this stage is the tributary one, whereas the feudal mode is a variant thereof, and the so-called slave mode is an

‘‘Figures in parentheses refer to listings in the References.

exception, usually located within another mode. Third, the complexity of formations at this stage (which explains its variety) implies that beyond the immediate relations of production, relations of both internal and external exchange are generating market relations. Fourth, this stage is not static but, on the contrary, is characterized by a considerable development of the productive forces based on tributary relations of production operating within complex formations. At this level of necessary abstraction and within this framework, Europe is no more “exceptional” than China, India, or Egypt, for example.

5. Capitalism is a necessary stage not only because it already exists, and exists worldwide. In fact, all tributary societies had to transform the relations of production underlying their development and to invent capitalist relations, which alone could enable the productive forces to further develop. Capitalism was not destined to be invented in Europe: it might also have been invented by the Chinese, Arabs, or others. The only reason it was not invented in Asia or Africa is that its prior development in Europe led to its impeding the other continents’ normal evolution. Their subjugation did not begin with imperialism: it started with the birth of capitalism itself.

Many, including a number of Marxists, have attempted to prove that capitalism could have arisen only by chance and in the European context, which provided an exception to the static situation of the other continents. All these attempts betray the fundamental principles of historical materialism. They exemplify the West-centered perspective, which is the ideology of capitalism and imperialism.

The capitalist system, then, will always be divided into a center and a periphery. This is an inherent contradiction. Center and periphery have changed their form and function from the mer-cantalist to the imperialist era. They have evolved from one phase of imperialism to the other, but they always stand opposed, like the two poles of a contradictory whole.

We may note in passing that the level of the productive forces during the capitalist era and the laws that govern their development involve a homogenizing tendency. This is because the capitalist mode is based on exchange value, while the tributary mode is based on use value. Nevertheless, the homogenization remains partial. It does not occur everywhere, but only in the centers; the central capitalist formations become increasingly similar. This homogenizaton contrasts with the variety of formations remaining from the previous era. Thus we need deal with only one problem related to the capitalist phase: Why did capitalism appear earlier in Europe? The answer is that Europe was less advanced, was peripheral. This is the first major manifestation of the unequal development of societies.

6. The communist stage is also necessary. But is it the only possible necessary stage? Capitalist relations stop the development of the productive forces well short of their clear potential level. In particular, capitalism cannot resolve its inherent center-periphery contradiction. Must classes be abolished in order for the productive forces to develop? I am not completely sure that this is the case. The transition which begins with the overthrow of capitalist relations does not lead automatically to communism. This transition may lead instead to a new stage which would then appear as necessary, a stage characterized by a new social class structure. This stage, which I refer to as the Soviet mode of production (or state collectivist mode or, more simply, statist mode of production) can already be seen as a possible one. Things might evolve in this direction, both in the periphery and in the center. Were they to do so, state centralization of capital and the resolution of the center-periphery contradiction would make possible considerable development of the productive forces. For this reason, such a stage cannot simply be called capitalist.

Should such evolution occur, communism would remain the necessary subsequent stage, because the existence of classes would limit the development of the productive forces. But, clearly, the whole problem of the struggle for communism—the problem of the transition—would take on different dimensions.

7.    Periods of transition are different from necessary stages because in the former elements of change prevail over elements of reproduction, while in the latter elements of reproduction are more prominent. This is not to say that during necessary stages reproduction eliminates contradiction, for without contradiction we could not understand change, that is, the reason why a necessary stage is not eternal. It simply means that during necessary stages class struggle tends to be integrated into reproduction, to become part of it. For instance, under capitalism, the class struggle tends—at least in the center—to be reduced to its economic dimension and to contribute to the functioning of the system rather than to its destruction. On the other hand, during periods of transition the class struggle really takes center stage. It becomes the motive force of history.

All necessary stages thus give the impression of being eternal and unchanging. In this respect, there is no difference between Europe and Asia, or even between the past and the present. All societies at the second, tributary, stage give this same impression of stagnation: what Marx said about Asia applies to European feudal society also, as Paul Sweezy has noted (50-2). In contrast to societies at this second stage, capitalism appears to be constantly changing, due to its basic economic law. But the permanent revolutionizing of the productive forces causes a no less permanent adaptation in the relations of production. This creates the impression that the system cannot be changed, an impression fostered by bourgeois ideology.

8.    Each period of transition has its own very particular features. Each concrete situation gives rise to a specific articulation of all the contradictions. However, these contradictions ultimately are resolved by the creation of stable systems, corresponding to the necessary stages. Despite their variety, these systems do not have many concrete differences of the same type but rather share certain basic common characteristics. As Perry Anderson has argued, “the genesis of a mode of production must be distinguished from its structure” (40-1).

9.    The first transitional period is from primitive, classless society to tributary society. In the academic division of labor, this is the province of anthropology, the contribution of which is discussed below. The rise of social classes, the rise of the state, and the development of relations of domination and exploitation combine in as many concrete ways as there are cases, i.e., societies, however small. An appropriate expression for these situations is “communal modes of production,” which emphasizes the fact that the formation of classes and the state is still incomplete and that forms of property are still collective.

10.    The second transitional period is from tributary society to capitalism, and takes one of two basically different forms. The first is the transition to capitalism in the center, i.e., transitions (in the plural) in Europe and Japan. This is the area where West-centered views are at their strongest, even among many Marxists. The second is the transition to peripheral capitalism. Because of its initial domination by external capitalism—still external in certain respects—peripheral capitalism developed in a very distinctive way. In general, the societies subjected to external capitalist domination were tributary societies, some of which were highly developed. But certain minor societies have been integrated into the capitalist system while still in the communal stage, albeit rarely.

11.    The third transitional period is the socialist experience. Up to the present, socialism has been introduced in peripheral areas (East Asia, Cuba) and semiperipheral areas (USSR, Yugoslavia, Albania, and countries of the European Soviet bloc). The Paris Commune provides an important exception to this generalization.

12.    There is a big difference between studying past transitions, to the tributary mode and to the capitalist mode in the center, and studying present-day transitions, to the capitalist mode in the periphery and socialist transitions. We can understand the past only through the scientific investigations of anthropologists and historians. We understand the present primarily through action: this is the superior means to knowledge.

Of course, anthropologists and historians can try to adopt the perspective of the revolutionary classes within the history they study, but this is different from actually becoming a revolutionary. For this reason, we can understand the past better by beginning with present-day struggles than by the reverse procedure. Anthropology and history must therefore take a back seat to the lessons learned by activists in the anti-imperialist struggle (operating in the framework of the transition to peripheral capitalism) and in the process of socialist construction (operating in a transitional period the outcome of which is in doubt so long as the statist mode is not firmly installed).

13. The above argument can be summarized as follows:

First necessary stage: primitive communism. Negation of necessary origin. Almost no knowledge about the transition from animality to humanity, although it is essential. Uniformity or variety?

First transitional phase: communal societies. Domain of anthropology. Incomplete class and state formation. Great concrete variety.

Second necessary stage: tributary societies. Tributary form dominant and variety characteristic of an economy based on use value. Slow but significant development of productive forces and impression of stagnation. Dominance of the base by the superstructure and forms of reproduction controlled by this dominance. Problems of particular situations (slavery) and of nondominant exchange relations.

Second transitional phase: the transition to capitalism. The transition to capitalism in the center: diversity of concrete situations related to the dominance of the elements of change over the elements of reproduction. Area where West-centered thinking is at its strongest. First manifestation of unequal development. The transition to peripheral capitalism: the basic lessons of antiimperialist activity.

Third necessary stage: capitalism. Tremendous development of productive forces: permanent renewal of these and permanent adaptation of the relations of production. Elements of reproduction dominant and tendency to reduce the class struggle to its economic dimension. Economy based on exchange value and dominance of the economic factor. Inherent center-periphery

contradiction and tendency to homogenization in the center only.

Third transitional phase: socialism. Second manifestation of unequal development. Diversity of historical experiences of this transition, always starting within peripheral or semiperipheral capitalism. Dominance of the class struggle and uncertainty about its outcome.

Fourth necessary stage. First possibility: the statist mode of production. Resolution of the center-periphery contradiction. Uniformity in that exchange value dominates the economy. Dominance of the superstructure (state centralization of capital). New contradictions and new conditions for the second transition, which will ultimately occur.

Second possibility: communism. Variety: reestablishment of use value. All else unknown (return to the original problems?).

14. The schema detailed here clearly raises basic questions about the method of historical materialism. At issue is whether one chooses Marx, Weber, or utopian socialism.

Although it is generally conceded that a mode of production consists of a particular combination of relations and forces of production, there has been a tendency to degrade the concept of mode of production by confusing it with the status of the producer (for instance, slave, serf, or wage laborer). Yet wage labor predates capitalism by several thousand years and capitalism is more than wage labor made universal. The capitalist mode combines wage labor with a certain level of development of the productive forces. Similarly, the existence of productive slaves is insufficient to constitute a slave mode of production: the fact of their existence means nothing, except in combination with a particular state of the productive forces. If the concept of mode of production is for certain people synonymous with the status of the producer, the misunderstanding is firstly a semantic one.

If we try to draw up a complete list of these statuses in the history of class societies, we cannot stop with the three modes of dependent labor: slavery, serfdom, and wage labor. Having a priori limited the list to these three types, West-centered Marxists have been forced to invent a fourth status, that of the producer in a so-called community (“asiatic”) dominated by a state (“generalized slavery”). Unfortunately, this fourth mode does not exist. What does exist, however, and what furthermore is far more common than slavery or serfdom, is the labor of the petty peasant producer. This is neither completely free and commodified nor is it totally within the confines of communal property. Rather, it is subject to tribute. We need a name for this most historically common status and can find no other than the one I have proposed, the tributary mode.

Some people regard this mode as a useless oversimplification and insist on the need to locate in time and space the specific features of each precapitalist society. This is an example of how difficult dialogue is between historians, concerned to apprehend history in all its concrete details, and nonhistorians. The latter are perhaps too often in a hurry to generalize, to formulate so-called theories and laws. But the former suffer from empiricism and lack of perspective. What kind of progress can we make toward understanding social laws if we insist on defining one hundred, two hundred, five hundred modes of production? It is better to run the risk of finding diversity, which is real, elsewhere: in the articulation of a limited number of abstract elements, including modes of production, relations of production, productive forces, producers’ statuses, degree of commercialization of the economy, base-superstructure relations, and so on. This is in keeping with the spirit of Marx’s method: the concept is concrete because it synthesizes a number of determinations that articulate abstract elements.

We should not abandon theory simply because certain generalizations, such as the five stages or “two ways” (Asian and European), are incorrect. The strength of the formulation I propose is that it focuses on the deep similarities that characterize all precapitalist class societies. Many historians perceive only the differences among them. But the similarities are just as striking: Why were there corporations in Florence, Paris, Baghdad, Cairo, Fez, Canton, and Calicut? Why does the French Sun King remind us of the Chinese emperor? Why was interest on loans prohibited in various places? Doesn’t this prove that the contradictions characterizing all these societies are of the same type? Only concrete analysis of specific cases enables us to understand why some went through the necessary transition to capitalism more quickly than others. We must therefore categorically refuse to reject the term “precapitalist” (which assumes the necessity of capitalism) in favor of the allegedly more neutral term “antecapitalist” (which assumes that capitalism was the product of mere chance).

The latter position breaks the connection between relations and forces of production. It substitutes Weber for Marx and the search for “ideal types” through a method of generalization based on outward appearances for the search for general laws of motion. We must uncover the basic characteristics of the historical dynamic connecting the development of the productive forces to several major, successive stages in the evolution of the relations of production. Only within the framework of research inspired by Marx’s method can we avoid the ahistoricism of the structuralist alternative and the dogmatism of vulgar Marxism (the five stages and the “two ways”).

I believe we can avoid the pitfalls of the major philosophy of history, economism, by correctly treating the connection between forces and relations of production. I have said that given relations of production always lead to a particular kind of development of the productive forces, whose orientation they shape. However, only superior relations (capitalist relations are superior to tributary ones and these latter to communal ones) can clear the way for progress beyond the level of development attained on the basis of the old relations of production. The abolition of classes is thus a logical necessity and not a preference for one value system over another. This is the difference between Marx and the utopian socialism that preceded him.

Is the motive force of history the class struggle or the development of the productive forces? My thesis is that the class struggle determines the direction and the pace of development of the productive forces and that this development is therefore not neutral. The distinction between the development of the productive forces on the basis of given relations of production and their potential further development on the basis of new and superior relations suggests this non-neutrality.

In Imperialism and Unequal Development and in The Law of Value and Historical Materialism I pointed out that the schemas of Volume II of Capital demonstrate that different dynamic equilibria are possible. Different combinations of technical coefficients, rates of surplus value, real wages, and rates of profit correspond to these different equilibria. The flexibility of the schemas of Volume II reminds us that class struggle directs technical progress. For the precapitalist era, I have shown how the class struggle between peasants and their tributary exploiters determined a form of development which involved eventual penetration by capitalism. I stated that the same determination was occurring in all developed precapitalist societies, in Europe as well as the Arab world and China before their subjugation by European capitalism. On this is based my reassertion of the necessity of capitalism. Moreover, while the class struggle is certainly in the final analysis the motive force of history, it is useful to distinguish between two types of class struggle. The first takes place within a system of relations of production (the economist struggle under capitalism, for example) which directs the development of the productive forces on the basis of the relations of production in question. The second type of class struggle, the goal of which is to overturn old relations and establish new ones, is the condition for unparalleled subsequent potential development. This struggle characterizes revolutionary and transitional periods.

Starting from this position, we can see how the thesis of unequal development becomes obligatory. In the system’s center, where the relations of production are most firmly established, the development of the productive forces as directed by these relations reinforces the system’s cohesion. However, in the periphery, insufficient development of the productive forces results in greater flexibility; this explains why revolutions occur sooner in the periphery.

The thesis of unequal development is certainly not economistic. However, those who have challenged the prevailing revisionist position, which is truly economistic, have tended toward anarchism and utopianism, particularly since 1968. In their somewhat facile antieconomism they forget that the economic base is ultimately determinant. This kind of antieconomism leads logically to structuralism and idealism: concepts of reason, progress, or imagination become the motive forces of history.

15. In conclusion, four points should be stressed from this discussion about the universal and the particular in history. First, the fundamental analytical concepts of historical materialism have universal validity. Second, the same basic forces in the form of the universal productive forces-relations of production dialectic have been and still are at work in all societies. These forces impel universal history to pass through three major, necessary stages. Third, this obligatory development has assumed a great variety of forms and types. Fourth, evolution works by qualitative leaps from one mode to the other. It works unequally and goes through concrete transitions which have particular features in each case.

II. Universality and particularities of unequal development

1. Universal history teaches us that development is always unequal. The regions that have the most advanced productive forces and relations of production at a given moment, are never or almost never the ones to move the most rapidly and radically to a more advanced stage. Unequal development has appeared with particular force twice in history: in our own time, during which the transition to socialism began in countries like Russia and China and not in Great Britain or the United States; and in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, when capitalism developed in feudal Europe and not in the older, more flourishing oriental civilizations which had been more advanced for centuries or even millenia.

Within Europe itself, the transition to capitalism was uneven, as Italy, Spain, and England successively outpaced one another. Later in the development of capitalism, the United States surpassed Great Britain, Germany, and France. Today, in terms of the socialist transition, the USSR is retreating while China moves forward.

Is it possible to deduce a general law of unequal development from the fact of its universality? We must be careful not to confuse historical with natural law. In the natural sciences, a law is a discovery implying statistical repetition of the same cause-effect relationship. But this discussion is limited to two stages—capitalist and socialist—and two cases of unequal development, each having its own specific causes.

2. Yet the same pairs of terms—“center-periphery,” “complete-incomplete,” “advanced-backward”—recur through the whole of this analysis of unequal development in history. These terms will be explained in detail in subsequent chapters, particularly Chapters 3,4, 5, and 6. The use of the same terms is not meant to imply that history “eternally repeats itself’ and that a single, simple explanation therefore covers the whole of it. Rather, it is meant to suggest certain historical lessons, but these have meaning only if we grasp the originality of each of the two processes of unequal development in question.

Although the terms “center,” “complete,” and “advanced” are synonymous, as are the terms “periphery,” “incomplete,” and “backward,” the area in which the development in question takes place is different for the two major stages, tributary and capitalist. It should be emphasized that in the capitalist mode the economy is dominant, while in the tributary mode, ideology (the superstructure) is dominant. Complete and incomplete are thus adjectives that apply in the former case to the economy and in the latter to the superstructure.

In the system of capitalist imperialism, the centers are economically dominant, the peripheries are dominated. The capitalist system, furthermore, is the first global economic system. The central-dominant economies are autocentered, that is, complete; the peripheral-dominated economies are extraverted, incomplete and hence backward. Economic domination blocks them, stops them from catching up. In this sense, the cause of backwardness is external, although it is internalized through the class alliances that reproduce it.

This is not at all the case with precapitalist modes, whether central or peripheral, complete or incomplete. The complete tributary mode (China, Egypt) is complete at the superstructural level, with a dominant class-state, state centralization of the tributary surplus, and corresponding forms of state and ideology. The feudal mode is an incomplete tributary mode because it is incomplete with regard to state centralization of the tributary surplus. But complete tributary societies did not impose external domination on incomplete ones. Egypt did not dominate Rome (rather, it was the opposite) or still less feudal Europe (which did not belong to the same system of formations nor to the same era), and China did not dominate Japan. Consequently, external domination was not responsbile for blocking development in these cases. If feudalism, an incomplete and peripheral form of the tributary mode, was more suitable to the development of capitalism than the complete, central tributary mode this was not because tributary societies dominated feudal societies. There is no analogy with the correspondence between national liberation and socialism of our era. Obviously, we must seek the explanation elsewhere in the analysis.

Similarly, the European transition to feudalism resulted from a particular synthesis of the disintegration of the ancient, slaveholding Roman world and the development of the communal barbarian world. This barbarian world was backward compared to Roman society. In this sense, it was peripheral; it was in the process of transformation from a primitive classless society to a class society, while Roman society was a clearly recognizable class society. Among the barbarians, class society was embryonic, incomplete; in Rome, it was complete. That the less advanced sector initiated the synthesis accounts for the incomplete character of the resulting tributary mode (the feudal mode). Similarly, too, when we analyze unequal development in the European feudal system and in the transition to (mercantilist) capitalism, we see center-periphery relations inverted, although not necessarily by external causes. Thus we must avoid transposing the meaning of the terms “center” and “periphery” from one historical period to another.

I have expounded a theory of unequal development in terms of center and periphery, complete and incomplete. Is it possible to substitute for this theory a “general theory of the weak link”? Probably not. An analysis in terms of the weak link is appropriate to the capitalist system: the link is weak because the local alliance of revolutionary classes can prevail over the reactionary alliance, which is only one gear in the interlocking dominant alliances composing the imperialist system. The weak link assumes the dominance of the economic base. It would be pointless to generalize this particular analysis to all of history because the capitalist and the precapitalist weak links are different.

3. Thus there are no laws of transition. There are only lessons that reveal general and particular laws specific to each different mode of production and certain features particular to the conjunctures which produce unequal development.

Periodization of a system enables us to grasp the moments of transition in their specific configurations in relation to the characteristics of the mode of production which govern them. Of course, since the capitalist system is the first global system, we can speak of a general, world periodization based on the characteristics and tendencies of the system on a world scale. But there is no world periodization for past eras. History texts that equate the European, Arab, and Chinese middle ages are in error.

The periodization of European history, from the Roman and barbarian world to capitalism, is important because of the specific features of the feudal mode which dominated precapitalist Europe and of the birth of capitalism from this feudal society. There are three major divisions in this periodization: (1) ancient world (Roman) and barbarian world (German), (2) feudalism/mercantilist and absolutist feudalism, and (3) competitive capitalism/monopoly capitalism. Since the division separating the ancient and barbarian world from feudalism and that separating mercantilism from capitalism represent transitions to new modes of production, each phase preceding the division can be considered a transitional one: transition to feudalism (first to eighth centuries), (mercantilist) transition to capitalism (seventeenth to eighteenth centuries). But does the current phase of monopoly capitalism represent a transition to socialism? The question calls for expanded analysis below (Chapter 7).

We can also see that the form a transition takes may account for subsequent long-range developments. For instance, the form of the transition to feudalism can explain the form of the bourgeois revolution (the peasant element in the bourgeois revolution, discussed in Chapter 4). Is this strong determinism, wherein the ancient past weighs heavily on the present, very different from the weak determinism of revolutionary periods? Can we therefore contrast evolutions (reformist) where the objective (synchronic) conditions predominate with revolutions where the subjective (or so-called subjective) conditions prevail by reducing the weight of the past?

4. Because the discussion of unequal development in Chapters 3-6 encompasses ethnic groups or nations at unequal levels of advancement, the national question will always be associated with it.

III. The concept of nation

1. I propose a concept of nation in contrast to that of ethnic group. The two share one extremely important characteristic, a common language. The distinction between them is based on the presence or absence of state centralization (on the state level and through state intervention) of the surplus product.

Thus, although state and nation are not identical, the national phenomenon cannot be separated from the analysis of the state. On this basis, I propose a systematic survey of the nation throughout history. In particular, the nation clearly appears in (1) complete tributary societies (China, Egypt) where the tribute was centralized by the state and the tributary class was a state class, in contrast to incomplete tributary societies (like European feudal societies) where tribute collection was not centralized, and (2) capitalism, where the competition among capitals (with the resulting equalization of profits) and the mobility of labor are controlled by the state through legislation, the monetary system, and state economic policy. I explained that the European situation—the absence of nations during the feudal era, the concurrent birth of the nation and of capitalism—accounts for the West-centered distortion of the concept of nation. This distortion appears not only in the works of Stalin but also in those of Marx, Engels, and Lenin. The question of the Arab “nation” should be studied from this perspective.

2.    Class conflicts and alliances take place within social formations bounded by states, which may or may not be nations. This is because conflicts and alliances imply active interference on the political and thus the state level.

3.    Thus the concept of nation clearly appears in complete societies, whether they are tributary (China, Egypt) or capitalist (European nations of the capitalist center). On the other hand, in peripheral, incomplete modes of production, ethnic identification is too weak to constitute a nation. This is the case for feudal Europe, because the feudal mode was only an incomplete tributary mode. It is also the case for contemporary capitalist peripheries. Similarly, the society-nation equation does not still hold during transitional periods. Thus in contemporary Europe (assuming we are in an ambiguous transition either to socialism or to a state class mode) new national problems are surfacing. For instance, French regions, France, and Europe are three levels of a rapidly changing reality. These questions will be taken up in the following chapters, especially Chapters 4-6.

IV. The concept of a system of social formations

I propose using the concept of a system of social formations when the class conflicts and alliances in one area (in one state) have a significant effect on the conflicts and alliances in the other. When this is not the case, the formations are autonomous, even if they maintain exchange relations between them.

The imperialist system is the model par excellence of a system of social formations. The alliances and conflicts among its different partners are interdependent: social-democratic alliances in the center, national liberation alliances in the periphery. This articulation of alliances and conflicts, wherein classes can be completely defined only in relation to their place in the system as a whole, indicates that value is being distributed systemwide. Value has a collective origin at the level of the system rather than the level of each (state) formation; value is a world and not a national category (globalization of the productive process); its distribution results, in the final analysis, from class struggles and alliances on a world and not a national scale.

V. State, nation, and economy in capitalist reproduction

1. The state instance is essential to an understanding of the way in which social formations operate. The latter are not simply modes of production, nor are modes of production merely infrastructural economic bases (relations and forces of production). This is because the state has been established as a tool of the exploiting classes.

Specifically, in capitalist formations the role of the state is essential for the reproduction of the concrete conditions of accumulations (including class alliances necessary to this reproduction, economic policies favoring them, etc.). Politics is the arena wherein the alliances of the hegemonic bloc form and dissolve. The same is true of the world system of capitalist formations. The

conditions for the reproduction of the world hierarchy are determined at the state level: international division of labor, class alliances on a world scale, and so on. To separate the economy from the state is to accept the artificial division between “pure economics” and “political science” by which bourgeois scholarship attempts to refute historical materialism.

2. A good way to approach the problem of the relationship between the state and the economy (national and global) is to begin with the original outline for Capital. Marx proposed to treat six groups of questions in the following order: (1) capital, (2) real property, (3) wage labor, (4) the state, the nation, political democracy, parties, and the class struggle, (5) crises, and (6) international trade and the world market (82-9).

The four volumes of Capital (Volume I published during Marx’s lifetime, Volumes II and III by Engels, and Volume IV, concerning theories of surplus value, by Kautsky) treat questions 1, 2, and 3. The other questions are dealt with only tangentially and unsystematically in the Grundrisse and in Capital.

I have elsewhere presented my interpretation of the place of Capital in historical materialism in Imperialism and Unequal Development, The Law of Value and Historical Materialism, and will not repeat it here. Volumes I, II, and III consist partially of a theory of the “pure” capitalist mode of production (two classes, the bourgeoisie and the proletariat), and deals with fundamentals: the law of value, accumulation and dynamic equilibrium, competition among capitals, and the equalization of profit. The rest of Volume III begins to discuss the transition of the capitalist mode to a standard capitalist formation with three classes: it deals with capitalist ground rent. These volumes constitute Marxist political economy, understood as a critique of political economy. They define the boundaries which may not be transgressed without sacrificing the scientific character of Marxism. These volumes cover the first three questions.

By critique of political economy I mean the demystification of the objective economic “laws” that certain political economists claim to have discovered. Economic reality is not the sole determining factor but rather acts in dialectical relation with class struggles. The economy is only the immediate appearance; the deeper reality is located on the level of historical materialism. Thus economics is “the bourgeoisie’s discussion of its own practice” (10-13). The bourgeois “scientific” formulations (of Ricardo or of neo-Ricardians such as Sraffa) correctly describe the manifest interrelations of price, wages, and profits, that is, questions 1, 2, and 3 of the outline for Capital.

But from such a limited perspective we cannot correctly understand the class struggle, which seems to be no more than the economic struggle between the bourgeoisie and the proletariat. If we want to understand the real dynamic of class struggles we must raise the questions contained in group 4 (state, nation, politics). It is the method of historical materialism, however, and not that of so-called economics, which raises these questions. What we need is a concrete analysis of a concrete situation, of the global (economic and political) history of a formation, of its blocs of class alliances as they function within a given political framework, with particular ideological mediations, and so on. On this level, state mediation is obviously required.

But this is not all. Bourgeois political economy claims to be able to answer questions 5 and 6 (crises and international economic relations) in economic terms. It proposes explanatory models for conjuncture and crisis, on the one hand, and for international exchange on the other; both models use the economic abstractions of price, wages, and profits. Can we criticize these theories in their own terms, replacing bourgeois models with Marxist models? Is this what Marx would have done had he written two more volumes in answer to these questions? Some think so and have tried to complete Marxist political economy along these lines. But I believe that these questions must first be answered in historical materialist terms; answers on a more basic level must precede answers in economic terms. I have stated that Marx did not write an “economics of crisis” and an “international economics” not because he lacked the time but because the scientific analysis of economic forms demanded prior advances in historical materialist thought.

3. Take the questions of group 5 (cycle and crisis), for instance. It is not difficult to propose a model of cyclical accumulation similar to the model of regular linear accumulation in Volume II of Capital. It can be discussed in Marxist terms (value, variation in the rate of surplus value) or in pragmatic Ricardian-Sraffan terms (prices, wages, profit). This is precisely what I did in Unequal Development. But this model has only descriptive value. To really explain things we must consider crisis as a means to regulate accumulation, that is, as the strategy of the bourgeois class.

In pre-monopoly capitalism, state control of money is the first means of regulation. I have emphasized the point that money is not a veil but is an active instrument in the accumulation process. State control of money and credit is thus the economic policy of the bourgeoisie as a class. Capitalism cannot function without the state, without centralized money and credit. It cannot be analyzed by looking only at the competition among capitals. The changes in the interest rate which implement this economic policy have two goals. First, they speed up accumulation and then “restore order” by means of a crisis; this is a time of heightened competition favoring big business and of organized pressure on the proletariat. Second, they manage external relations, that is, they maintain or improve the national position vis-a-vis competing centers in the international division of labor. (For a discussion, see The Law of Value and Historical Materialism.)

Thus, during the pre-monopoly capitalism era, accumulation is regulated by state management of two areas: management of money on the one hand and of the labor force on the other (by the changes it introduces in the unemployment rate). The two are linked through the management of crisis.

Of course, we must go further than this. The social formation contains other classes: real proprietors, peasants, small producers (crafts workers, merchants), and so on. The historical circumstances of the bourgeois revolution and the kind of state which resulted from it created a certain type of hegemonic bloc. Regulation must either reproduce the conditions that maintain these alliances (for instance, the antiworker peasant alliance), or create the circumstances to dissolve or transform them, to substitute a new bloc for the old one, and so forth.

Overall, during the pre-monopoly capitalism period, state regulation in the advanced centers took place within a political framework that was at best a parliamentary democracy (England, France under Louis Philippe) restrictive of the working class and at times an authoritarian bourgeois monarchy sympathetic to bourgeois interests (Bonapartism). During that period, the working class was largely excluded from political life, its organizations were not legal, suffrage was restricted, and so on. This limited bourgeois democracy was in fact more open to participation by the peasantry and the petty bourgoisie.

4. Before seeing how this system of regulating the workforce changed in the imperialist era, we must try to answer Marx’s questions. Let us take up the group of questions relating to international economics. These raise two types of problems, those relating to competition among centers and those relating to the center-periphery division of labor. These problems are different for the preimperialist stage and for our own imperialist era.

During the preimperialist era competition among centers was also subject to state regulation. Laissez-faire was never other than ideological. The state, expressing the collective interests of the bourgeoisie, had two major means of regulating competition: the control of money and the control of customs duties. In the control of money, the effects of state economic policy related to internal accumulation and to external competition are closely linked. (See The Law of Value and Historical Materialism.) In its infinite variations, the conflict between free trade and protection has always been a political question of the greatest importance and has had a decisive impact on internal class alliances. There are numerous examples: the abolition of the Com Laws and the abandonment of the English aristocratic alliance; French and Italian protectionism and peasant interests; the protection of American farmers and American food aid policies, to name a few.

During the imperialist era, the automatisms which previously connected changes in the interest rate with short-term movements of international capital and of the balance of payments have been replaced by more complex mechanisms. Nevertheless, monetary policy still has a clear international dimension. It can be implemented by control of exchange and movements of capital in certain phases and always by state interference in money markets. The abandonment of the gold standard in favor of the Bretton Woods system and current monetary arrangements like the Smithsonian agreement indicate active intervention between national monetary policy and the conditions of international competition. Neoliberal policies such as the General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade (GATT) and the European Common Market and neoprotectionist policies, which are reappearing everywhere due to the current crisis, are still very important means of controlling international competition.

But with the advent of imperialism, whether in the form of imperial preserves or of a world ostensibly open to all, the international division of labor between centers and peripheries takes on a new dimension. My basic thesis is that this new division of labor ushers in the era of the social-democratic alliance in the imperialist centers. This alliance takes the place of old alliances based on dying classes, such as the peasantry and the old petty bourgeoisie. The alliance is often strengthened by the division of the working class into two sectors. The first is national and relatively privileged; it is the base of social democracy. The other is almost completely excluded from the system of privileges; it consists of immigrants, minorities subject to discrimination (blacks and Hispanic minorities in the United States, for example), young people, and women (especially temporary workers). There is also an attempt, which has met with varying degrees of success, to integrate the higher levels of the new petty bourgeoisie (including managers and technicians).

The natural complement to the social-democratic alliance in the center is the external alliance of the imperialist bourgeoisie with the exploiting classes of the periphery, either feudal and comprador classes or the dependent industrial bourgeoisie, depending on the era. On a world scale, this hegemonic bloc clashes with the bloc of national liberation forces, the composition of which varies with the class structure of each peripheral country.

The reproduction of this international structure involves imperialist ideological hegemony. It also involves the material corruption made possible by the superexploitation and looting of the periphery and by the economic impact this has on the center (full employment and combined growth of wages and productivity). This ideological hegemony makes it possible to extend electoral democracy to the working class, which had been impossible in the preimperialist stage. Nationalism, in its former national chauvinist guise or in its current panoccidentalist form, sustains this hegemony.

During the imperialist era, regulation by crisis and changes in the unemployment rate are no longer the main means of regulating accumulation. The substitution of the controlled conjuncture for the previous cycle expresses this change. Two main strategies, dictated by the international division of labor, are used to control the workforce: the reproduction of a growing reserve army in the periphery, and the division of the working class in the center, as explained above. National and international monetary and credit policies (such as those of the International Monetary Fund) reinforce this dual control over the labor force and the international division of labor. Control is exercised by states via political methods, not by the multinationals via their own independent actions, as some deviationist economists have claimed (71b).

Obviously, this control does not bring about harmony, contrary to the pretensions of economistic ideology (a two-pronged ideology of efficiency in the center and of development in the periphery, for which we must note the role of the World Bank in the production of its “third world action” component). It is fraught with class contradictions. But these contradictions are different from those of the past. The primary contradiction throughout the entire imperialist epoch is that between the imperialist bloc, including partners in the social democratic alliance and dependent alliances in the periphery, and the national liberation bloc. Thus the current crisis can be seen as a crisis of imperialism, i.e., a crisis of these blocs (for a fuller discussion, see Chapter 5 of Imperialism and Unequal Development).

Only by substituting historical materialism for political economy can we really understand problems of so-called international economics and fully criticize economism. It is not “comparative advantages” which determine the international division of labor, but the converse. And the international division of labor itself is determined by the reproduction of the class alliances underlying it.

By using historical materialism we can also analyze the economic operation of the system. We can see it as a system for determining the division of value created on a world scale through unequal rates of extraction of surplus labor and as a system based on the globalization of the previously national categories of the commodity form and of value.

5. In conclusion, it should be emphasized that accumulation, both on a world scale and on the scale of central and peripheral states, is a consequence of class alliances and oppositions within states and across state boundaries. Thus the state has essential functions: this level is decisive. But the state is not necessarily the nation. The two are basically the same in the center, where the nation-state was finally imposed by a twofold process of assimilation within the nation and destruction of multinational forms. But this is not generally the case in the periphery.

VI. The bourgeois and proletarian lines on the national question: ideology and material base

1. The bourgeois line, the line of all exploiting classes, recognizes the existence of every kind of social group (nations, ethno-linguistic groups, races, tribes, religious groups, not to mention age, sex, and other groups) except classes. Thus, using a simple empirical definition derived from the observation of immediate appearances, sociology claims that there are only socioeconomic categories, derived from occupations. These are defined by the type of work and the sector of activity and are neither more nor less important than noneconomic social categories. Sociology seeks to establish possible correlations between different apparent social phenomena. It considers class distinctions based on an analysis of the mode of production to be “metaphysical,” “vague,” and “unidentifiable.” This is similar to vulgar bourgeois economics, which deals only with price and considers the “metaphysical” category of value to be a pointless “detour. ”

Confronted with the various practical problems created by the existence of all these different categories, the bourgeois line takes one of two positions. The reactionary position denies the importance of rights and freedoms specific to the needs of each category. It believes that formal and individual liberty (“all men are equal”) suffices. The democratic position recognizes the necessity for particular rights and freedoms, for instance, the right of nations to self-determination, the right of women to real equality with men, the right of minorities to use their own language, and so on.

2. The proletarian line, the line of all exploited classes, recognizes class division as more basic than national, religious, sexual, or other immediately observable distinctions. Class division is based on the mode of production. It results in conflicts between the exploited classes, which are forced to furnish surplus labor, and the exploiting classes, which appropriate this surplus labor. The proletarian line also recognizes that price is the phenomenal form of value.

Since in all societies the exploiting classes have ideological hegemony (the ideology of the dominant class is the dominant ideology of the society) we must distinguish between a class-in-itself and a class-for-itself. For, if social class is an objective reality, it only becomes a full and complete political reality to the degree

that the ideological hegemony of the exploiting class is challenged by a clear and well-developed class consciousness. This consciousness develops through participation in the class struggle and through the recognition that other categories, although they also exist objectively, are less important than class exploitation.

Confronted with the problems which these various objective realities pose for the class struggle, the proletarian line also takes one of two positions, reactionary or revolutionary. The reactionary, or bureaucratic, formal position simply denies realities other than class. It denies the importance of sex, nations, religions, or other categories, regarding them not as realities but as phenomena artificially manipulated by the exploiting classes. This position results, moreover, in tactical concessions with regard to these realities. Indeed, it leads to practical failure in the class struggle because these realities are tenacious and subtly undermine the development of the class-for-itself.

The revolutionary position recognizes that all categorical differences have material bases and tries to understand how they interface with class differences. The revolutionary attitude does not distinguish between two worlds, the world of classes materially based on exploitation and the world of other categories based not on material reality but purely on circumstances and/or ideology. It recognizes only one world, wherein everything has a material basis which, in the final analysis, is class exploitation.

The revolutionary position thus always attempts to understand the dialectical interaction of all the elements of social life. It does not put all of these aspects on the same plane but always seeks out ultimate determinations and the ways in which these are expressed. On this basis, it develops a strategy and tactic of effective, revolutionary class alliances.

VII. The ideology of universal culture

1. Major debates, such as those about the state and the nation, lead us naturally to the formulation of conclusions about the direction of humanity’s cultural evolution—toward homogenization or not—and to the choice of a position with regard to this direction—active support for it or not. To do this we must understand how the productive forces develop and the impact of this development on the capitalist system.

2. My first thesis is that the tendency to homogenization, which underlies capitalist development, is blocked by the very conditions of unequal accumulation.

The material basis of the tendency to homogenization is the continual extension of markets, both in breadth and in depth. The commodity market extends progressively from one region to the country as a whole and then to the entire world. It also gradually envelops all aspects of social life. Capital markets, which were localized so long as capital could not be separated from the capitalist, tend to become global with the centralization of capital during the monopoly stage. The workforce itself, whose geographical mobility had been limited for so long by social, linguistic, legal, and other factors, tends to acquire greater—and even international—mobility.

Cultural life is not some mysterious, unfathomable domain, but is rather the way in which the utilization of use values is organized. Therefore, the homogenization of these use values through their domination by generalized exchange value must tend to homogenize culture itself. Nevertheless, this tendency is held in check by the effects of unequal accumulation.

First and most importantly at present, rapid accumulation in the center conflicts with curbed, biased accumulation on the periphery of the imperialist system. In the center, the tendency has been and is toward the disintegration of precapitalist modes and the integration of a proletarian labor force from which surplus value is directly extracted during the work process itself (real domination). In the periphery, the historical conditions under which capitalism attained a world scale have instead entailed a tremendous development of formal means of subjugation. This explains the survival of precapitalist forms, the superexploitation of labor in the periphery through the transfer of value, and the attendant distortion in the mode of accumulation. This fundamental inequality of imperialist development accelerates real homogenization in the center while blocking it in the periphery, where only a minority of the people can become modern consumers.

Second, accumulation is unequal in the centers themselves. This inequality was a major obstacle to the formation of these centers and to the acquisition of a unified national character by most of them. It continues to exist, surfacing again and again in the form of regionalism.

3. My second thesis is that this tendency to homogenization is not a necessary consequence of the development of the productive forces per se, but of the capitalist content of this development. The growth of the productive forces in precapitalist societies did not involve the domination of use value by exchange value. Thus, their development was not homogeneous but took a diversity of forms and methods.

The capitalist mode, which was historically necessary to the further growth of the productive forces, involved the dominance of exchange value and thus homogenization. But the capitalist mode is no more eternal than preceding modes. It has become an obstacle to the further development of the productive forces on a world scale because of the distorted mode of accumulation which it imposes on the periphery and which precludes the possibility of the periphery catching up. This is the major reason why capitalism is objectively obsolete on a world scale.

Can socialism, in its turn an historical necessity, overcome the legacy of the past and present by adopting models of accumulation similar enough to those of capitalism to succeed where capitalism has failed in homogenizing the world? Or must it operate differently? While socialism might bring about homogenization, the socialism in question in that case would be a new class mode, the statist mode. Since the nonstate path is equally “possible,” i.e., based on real tendencies in the struggle, there is no obligation to regard the first possibility as being historically necessary.

The key to a scientific analyisis of these problems is a correct understanding of the question of technology. My view is that technology is not neutral in its effects on the relations of production, making it impossible to represent the productive techniques of a classless society by simple extrapolation from capitalist techniques. Under capitalism, technical development supports a division of labor separating conception from execution and thereby reproduces the material base of class division. And if classless society is founded on the abolition of exchange value and the reestablished primacy of use value there is no reason to think that the current tendency to homogenization would continue. It should, on the contrary, reverse itself, because communism implies variety.

4.    The tendency to homogenization under capitalism is stronger in some areas than in others. In the area of industrial production techniques, in the realm of modes of consumption, “lifestyles,” and so on, its force is virtually irresistible. It is somewhat weaker in the domain of ideology and politics. And when it comes to the use of language, its impact is very weak.

During a long period, the linguistic unification of newly forming nations took place by force of circumstance (including force pure and simple) rather than by systematic design. For this reason spoken popular languages and official administrative languages continued to coexist. The spread of schools, corresponding to the practical demands of a considerably more integrated market, has only really succeeded in establishing national languages within the modern era. Each time the authorities tried to use the schools to impose a foreign language on a newly forming nation, they met with generally successful resistance. Many nineteenth-century socialists had hopes of rapid assimilation (see Kautsky’s predictions for the Austrian empire, or Strasser’s about the Czech language) but these have proved false.

5.    How should we evaluate this tendency toward homogenization? Obviously, it is pointless to cry over what has already taken place and is historically irreversible: the Gallicization of the Languedoc, the widespread adoption of private automobile transportation in the West, or of Coca-Cola by the Cubans, to take random examples of unequal importance. All emotion of this sort is foreign to Marxism, which does not believe in the immutability of societies in any area.

But the real question concerns the future. Should we celebrate this capitalist tendency toward homogenization, as we would celebrate the growth of the productive forces? Should we support it and view opposition to it as being as reactionary as smashing machines? Should we only regret that its class character limits its effectiveness? Or should we conclude that socialism will lead in the same direction, though more rapidly and less painfully?

Two tendencies have always coexisted within Marxism with regard to this question. Marx himself, at least in the first part of his active life, always spoke admiringly of the growth of the productive forces, the achievements of the bourgeoisie, and the tendency toward homogenization which freed people from the narrow confines of village life. But he gradually came to have doubts about this and in his later writings substituted a more nuanced perspective for his original onesided view.

However, the dominant tendency of the workers’ movement evolved in the opposite direction. Praise for “universal civilization” and a naive belief in the blending of cultures (and even of languages) were dominant in the Second International: we have only to think of Esperanto. Belied by the First World War, this naive cosmopolitanism reappeared after the Second World War, when Americanization emerged as a synonym for progress, or at least for inevitable modernization.

In fact, the tendency toward homogenization renders the superstructure more suitable to the needs of the capitalist infrastructure. It weakens the contradictions in this area and is therefore reactionary. The spontaneous resistance of people to this homogenization must be encouraged and strengthened with a view to overturning the underlying relations of exploitation. Homo consumens is not an inescapable necessity but only a necessity of capitalism. Indeed, the ideology of universal culture is a bourgeois ideology, child of the enlightenment ideology which held that the growth of the productive forces mechanically and automatically determines the growth of civilization, the progress of liberty and equality, and so on. This ideology obscures the class contradictions whereby the productive forces develop.

6. Whatever the case, has the tendency toward homogenization had important repercussions in the political arena, i.e., an impact on the class struggle in the contemporary world? Certainly, Until the wars of 1914-1918 and 1939-1945, the tendency toward homogenization seemed to be at work only in the nations of the center and especially in the great nation-states. It developed simultaneously with the constitution of monopoly capital on this national basis. It reinforced the deep chauvinist tendencies which served the interests of fiercely competing national imperialisms.

But things seem to have changed since 1945. Imperialist countries have been too unequal to escape the dominance of American imperialism and have relegated contradictions among themselves to the background. Fear of the USSR and of a widespread colonial revolt have reinforced this tendency. At the same time, the imperialist economic sphere became globalized and the construction of a European community began. The nature of this construction is ambivalent: will it result in a Europe united against the United States or in a Europe integrated into the Atlantic community via German mediation? Now, with the end of Gaullist illusions, a Germano-American Europe seems the more likely. And, as it has already done in America, economic growth has begun to homogenize European social life.

Under these circumstances, we must ask if the old type of nationalism is not about to disappear, to be replaced not by internationalism, but only by a pan-European neonationalism (panoccidentalism) with racist overtones and defining itself primarily by opposition to Asia and Africa. Its counterpart, tolerated and regenerated, would be microregionalisms without political significance.

Chapter 2

Communal Formations

1. If we accept the view that anthropology is the study of societies in the process of class formation, what can we learn from it? Anthropology, like all the specialized disciplines of social science, artificially divides social reality. It also has a twofold ideological objective: (1) to create a realm outside the fundamental laws of historical materialism (determination in the last instance by the economic base); and (2) to distinguish between “primitive peoples without a history,” especially those of Africa, and “peoples with a history, ” or even “with a great history” (Europeans), and thereby to provide a moral justification for imperialism. Given these circumstances, it is obvious that the work of anthropology generally has not been scientific, even though the evidence gathered by its best researchers can be used, following critical inventory, to enrich historical materialism. Thus the plethora of resources available to Anglo-Saxon anthropology, which rejects Marxism, has not made up for the inadequacy of its theoretical bases. It is worth noting that amidst this ethnographic jumble the most interesting contributions of non-Marxist anthropology have been made by researchers sympathetic to Marxism (cf. 10-9).

This oppressive legacy enhances the importance and value of the contribution of the Marxist minority in France that over the past fifteen years has rediscovered historical materialism. How can we forget that Engels’ The Origin of the Family, Private Property, and the State, a work of genius given the level of knowledge during

36

his time, failed to inspire a tradition of inquiry and remained a sort of intellectual curiosity, a decorative luxury object for the workers’ movement? This deplorable situation may be changing.

2.    Marxist anthropology already has to its credit the clarification of the problem of the dominance of kinship in societies in the process of class formation. It has shown that the low level of development of the productive forces necessitates forms of cooperation within the village collective and between villages, forms which are the material key to understanding the function of family, lineage, clan, and tribal organizations. It has thus effected a radical and salutary return to the best of Engels.

By demonstrating that the economic base is determinant in the last instance, some Marxist anthropologists have dispelled the confusion created by their structuralist colleagues, notably Maurice Godelier (10-14), in their attempt to treat kinship as part of the infrastructure and of the superstructure at the same time. Important in this regard are the contributions of various French Marxist anthropologists, particularly the distinction therein proposed between dominance and determination in the last instance (10-5, 10-6, 10-7).

3.    I do not conclude from this that economic anthropology has thereby taught us how the dominance of the noneconomic realm functions in societies in the process of class formation, based on what Alain Marie calls “the ideology of the family (or of kinship)” (10-4). Indeed, if we want to see this dominance at work, tributary societies provide material which is not only richer but also more directly related to the questions raised by the struggle against capitalism and for the construction of socialism. For in these far more advanced societies, the dominant ideology is no longer that of kinship, to which our modern world is rather indifferent, but is one conveyed and imposed by the major absolute institutions, whether religious or civil. Consideration of the role of the Christian church in feudal Europe, the ideology of absolute monarchy in mercantile Europe, of Islam in the Arab world, of Confucianism in China, and so on, seems much more useful to an understanding of the exact place of ideology in historical materialism.

In fact, the role of ideology has been obscured by the economistic reduction of Marxism. This reduction is evidence of the reintegration of the dominant Marxist tendency into the tradition of bourgeois philosophy, the philosophy of the Enlightenment, itself the ideological expression of the dominance of the economic instance in the capitalist mode. But it was not anthropological discoveries that led to the reexamination of this economistic reduction and of the theory of ideology-reflection which it inspired. Rather, it was prompted by political thinking about Soviet society and the construction of socialism, which in turn, promoted the growth of better anthropological thinking.

This fact underlines the primacy of the contribution of militant action over the best academic contribution, especially since it was not intellectual analysis of socialist problems but rather the enormous practical and theoretical movement brought about by the struggles in China that inspired the best anthropology. Maoism, not anthropology, has enabled us to reestablish historical materialism in every area. As a summary formulation I suggest that the centralization of capital in the statist mode ends the dominance of the economy (based on the transformation of surplus value into profit, Volume III of Capital) and reestablished the dominance of ideology (here, statist, consumismo nationalism). It is for this reason that the statist mode does not seem to me to be simply a form of capitalism but a new term in the necessary alternative required for the transcendence of capitalism.

4. However, progress always involves the risk of subsequent regression. For the resolution of certain problems creates new ones. Thus anthropology, having clarified the question of kinship, today faces a new and still unanswered question, namely, how male-female relations and the social relations of domination (which are on the level of superstructural instances) interrelate with exploitation (that is, the extraction of surplus labor). Particularly striking is the power of Alain Marie’s substitution of the term “women” for that of “commodities” in Marx’s text (10-4). This seems to be the best possible description of women’s status through the ages—not that of an exploited producer but of a commodity.

The particular nature of this problem stems from perhaps the fact that the question of the relations between the sexes and the dominated status of women dates in part from primitive communism, the transition from animal to human, and in part from the subsequent phase of early class formation. We may know how family organization interrelates with different modes of production. But we cannot conclude from this that women are a social class (exploited by men) except if we both confuse relations of domination with relations of exploitation of the one hand and on the other reduce to a single category the extraction of surplus labor from women throughout the ages (thereby denying the particularity of the interrelation between the family and the mode of production in different modes of production).

This formulation of the woman question results from an econo-mistic interpretation of historical materialism. Or, worse, it comes from extending the domain of historical materialism to an area outside its purview: that of anthropology in the literal sense, the definition of the human being in relation to the animal species. Such a formulation opens the door to psychologistic and biologistic follies based on the “myths of origin” that sustain certain feminist tendencies to the detriment of the struggle for the real liberation of women (11-3).

Here once again it is not intellectual speculation (anthropological or otherwise) but the eruption of women’s movements that has raised these issues. The fact that these movements have at times been quite remote from Marxism, as in the United States and northern Europe, and at others very close to it, as in the period just after the Russian and Chinese revolutions, neither adds to nor detracts from their relevance and importance.

Is it useful to reformulate these problems in terms of a so-called domestic mode of production, interfacing with other modes of production (11-1, 11-2)? I do not think so. In trying to prove that the source of the profits monopolies extract from immigrant workers is to be found in domestic exploitation, one clouds the specific effects of monopoly domination over the peasant societies from which these migrant workers come (cf. 11-2). The correct way to analyze this problem is, it seems to me, to look at the domination of the capitalist mode over peasant modes. This line of inquiry was probably opened by Marx himself, in his brief consideration of the effects of the integration of the Russian peasantry into the capitalist system, followed by Lenin, Kautsky, and even Chayanov (10-10). Once again, it was the peasant movement, especially in France, and anti-imperialist peasant struggles that gave rise to these ideas (cf. 73b).

Marx never posited that the value of labor power was that of the worker taken in isolation, but insisted it must take account of the cost of reproduction under the conditions characterizing any given society. These social conditions are familiar to us: they include the organization of the family, the sexual hierarchy, the sexual division of labor, and the assignment of domestic labor to women. This is why it is important to rediscover the true meaning of the value of labor power in the capitalist mode and the implications of this for the oppression of women. The fact that in the West the women’s revolt occurred first in the United States and in Northern Europe has not been without its effect. The widespread ignorance of Marxism in these regions has led to some ahistorical formulations, feminist versions of the feminine mystique (11-3).

We have to see the problem in a new light. I have argued that the notion of a domestic mode of production is confusing, since a mode of production cannot be transhistorical, accounting for everything in all times and places. With regard to the household division of labor an older phrase, “the oppression of women,” is clearer. The confusion stems from reducing all relations of domination and exploitation to a single category, that of relations of extraction of the surplus. The correct way to formulate the question of the interrelationship between women’s oppression and capitalist exploitation is this: women’s subjection enables capital to reduce the value of labor power; men dominate women, but they are exploited together. Bruno Lautier was, as far as I know, the first to develop systematically the idea of the interrelationship between formal and real forms of subjection and to reject the concept of a “chain” of exploitation, i. e., exploitation of women by man and of man by capital (73-3).

Doubtless the “historic defeat of the female sex,” to use Engels’ expression, is so ancient that the oppression of women has been a permanent feature of history. But in that case it cannot be analyzed as a mode of production. As Alain Lipietz has noted, this oppression never exists in an isolated manner, which proves that it does not have the status of a mode of production in the true meaning of the term (82-10).

5. Oriented toward the past (the transition to class society), anthropology is poorly placed to profit from the experience of class struggle, and may end up in a number of blind allies. The first of these comes from the tendency to forget that it is about the transition to class society. It is worth remembering that the societies it studies are necessarily societies wherein the level of development of the productive forces is very low. The lineage, clan, and tribal organizations are themselves obstacles to the further development of these forces, obstacles which cannot be overcome except through state tributary organization.

Of course, in order for class formation to begin, an initial development of the productive forces is necessary. This corresponds to the transition to settled agriculture. Contrary to the neoclassical economic theory which stupidly equates earth and nature, agronomists have known for a long time that agricultural land is a means of labor and not an object of labor. But other branches of the social sciences have not read agronomists because they are supposedly too earthy and empiricist. Economists, historians, and anthropologists have thus thought they were discovering what they were in fact only rediscovering. As to the myth which confuses the development of the productive forces with gains in the productivity of labor, Ester Boserup, although not a Marxist, dispelled it in a work published in 1965 (10-11). She argued that the transition to intensive agriculture under the impact of demographic pressure brought about greater per capita production (and thus ultimately a more dependable surplus) thanks to the greater annual quantity of labor and not to the higher daily productivity of labor.

Every time we encounter the dominance of kinship, this is an infallible sign that we are still at the first stage of a long evolution, an embryonic stage in the process of class formation. And on this particular point, the criticism that Meillassoux pays too little attention to the level of the productive forces seems justified (11-4). Africanists too easily forget that the sub-Saharan societies they study had neither the plow nor a written language (except in Ethiopia and the Sudan). This conjunction is not accidental. The development of the productive forces, a necessary condition for the constitution of a surplus large enough to lead to irreversible state formation, occurs through the transition from human energy (hoe agriculture) to animal energy. Similarly, it is hard to imagine a state without the use of writing for census taking, dispensing information, and transmitting orders. The imperial Ethiopian state and the Mahdist state in the Sudan were forming at the same time that the use of the plow and of writing were becoming widespread.

Analysis of the productive forces implies analysis of the technical process of production, but the latter obviously cannot be separated from the superstructure. Frangois Pouillon emphasizes this point, reminding us that the category of abstract labor is a category of the capitalist mode (10-4). When classes are forming, the relations of domination and the embryonic relations of exploitation are still inextricably bound together. To disentangle them, it is necessary to make a radical distinction between them. As Marie suggests, “exploitation is not a necessary correlary of domination, ” although the two are linked: the birth of the state parallels the birth of classes (10-4). Because Meillassoux refused to make this distinction, he confuses the peasant mode of production and the domestic mode of production. Based on his study of the Guro, in West Africa,

Meillassoux states that neither control of a surplus product nor control of the means of production exists and that the control of labor power (but why?) operates via that of the reproducers (the women). Here he is confusing relations of cooperation and domination, already established to a certain extent (sufficiently to enable the gerontocracy to organize cooperation within the village and between villages), but not yet completely (no state, no power at its disposal), with relations of exploitation not yet established at all. For if there is no state, it is because there is no need for one. There is general acceptance of the gerontocracy because it brings about the necessary cooperation. The lack of social classes does not necessarily mean that a society is idyllic.

And if there are no classes, the modes of production of this transition must be characterized as communal modes. I use the plural because at this stage of human evolution, ecological, demographic, and other conditions bring into being a great variety of organizations. Nevertheless, this variety is created not by the level of the productive forces (which is everywhere very low) but by the relations of production and juridical and political relations.

The task of historical materialism, therefore, is to find the common denominator in all this variety. This is the communal ownership of the primary means of production, the land. Communal ownership is organized in a great variety of specific ways, in which individual, family, lineage, and other uses are combined. If we emphasize specific details, we run the risk of forgetting the basic common characteristic, that of collective ownership. We may confuse the plane of the economic base with the plane of political organization (prestate), emphasizing the gerontocracy (relation of dominance) and attributing to it effects of a mode of extraction of surplus value which it is not.

6. The second blind alley into which anthropology may stray intensifies the negative effects of dogmatic rigidity. Given the circumstances under which academic anthropology has developed, this once again opens the way to the aberrations of West-centeredness.

The persistent search for a “slave mode of production” seems to be a deviation of this sort, one which recalls the “five stages” of the Stalinist vulgate. Among the extreme variety of forms taken by the transition from communal to tributary modes of production, slavery seems to be neither obligatory, nor even widespread. And the persistence of the search is due exclusively to the importance of Greek and Roman antiquity in the development of the West.

The confusion between the status of persons and that of producers is a case in point. West-centeredness reaches caricature proportion on this subject: fifty words from fifty different languages describing different situations in different areas are translated by the same term, “slavery.” Then a way out of this impasse is sought. In fact if these words have different connotations, it is because they describe different realities. Slavery constitutes a particular and rather exceptional labor status, which becomes really widespread only in highly mercantilized situations, which are clearly the situations just preceding the completion of the capitalist mode.

7.    The third blind alley has serious consequences. If under the pretext of the primacy of the relations of production, it excludes the analysis of circulation from the realm of historical materialism, circulation will be treated as having no effect in its turn on the relations of production. Is this a dialectical vision?

Elsewhere I have argued about the importance of Volumes II and III of Capital and the danger of reducing Marx to Volume I alone. Here I will merely state that the refusal to consider circulation is rather suspect, and acts as a blind for imperialism. It is precisely this obstinate refusal to even consider the existence of commodity circulation and the exclusive concentration on the relations of production, thus reduced to the immediate labor process, which has led to considering slavery as a necessary and general state in the succession of modes of production.

8.    Questions about the transition from antiquity to European feudalism belong to the intersection of history and anthropology. I will return to this point to emphasize the importance of the interpenetration of barbarian communal modes with the class modes of antiquity in the establishment of feudalism as a special and peripheral form of the tributary mode.

Marx and Engels created a Marxist anthropology based on questions about the history of Greek and Roman antiquity and about the establishment of Christian feudalism. Marx thought this particular development of the state and classes was different from that of “Asia” (in the Grundrisse). Engels, on the other hand, in The Origin of the Family, emphasized the universal characteristics of evolution, by analogy with the Greek gens and thatofthe Iroquois.

Marxist exegesis having replaced Marxism, the Grundrisse has inspired a literature which is prolific but lacking in scientific spirit. I will return to this debate in the following chapter. As Meillassoux notes, we must study reality in all its variety if we wish to make progress (10-5). Without doubt, it is on the basis of concrete anthropological studies, particularly those about Africa, that progress has been made toward a better understanding of communal societies.

Chapter 3

Tributary Formations

1. The period between the definitive establishment of social classes and the state in a given society and the entrance of that society into the central (complete) or peripheral (dominated) capitalist era varies in length. At times it is long (five thousand years for Egypt, three thousand for Greece), at others short (fifteen centuries for Europe). Occasionally, imperialist integration does away with this period entirely (for several African and Oceanic societies). Clearly, even a superficial view reveals the immense variety of social organizations that characterize this period. Given this situation, is it scientific to try to find a common denominator?

Marxist tradition in this area is contradictory. Academic Marxism has insisted on emphasizing the particularity of each case. At times, it has even become empiricist and refused to use the same terms for societies belonging to different cultural areas; for instance, it has reserved the term “feudal” for Europe (with, as always, the Japanese exception) and refused to use it for Asia. On the other hand, the militant Marxist tradition has always used a global terminology, using the term feudal, for instance, for all great precapitalist societies: China, India, the Arab world, and even clearly less developed societies (in Africa, for instance).

If we approach this question with Marxology rather than Marxism, we can attribute either tradition to Marx. As Rodney Hilton states, Marx certainly gave the term “feudal” a general and broad connotation which was completely understood by his contemporaries (50-2). He used it to cover all of European history at least from the barbarian invasions to the English and French bourgeois revolutions. His view of feudalism was not that of later bourgeois historians who, by restricting it, have narrowed the area of its sway to the region between the Loire and the Rhine during four centuries. But Marx also invented the phrase “asiatic mode of production,” and—in his erstwhile unpublished writings, including the Grundisse—adopted certain theses of Montesquieu and Bernier that contrast Asian “stagnation” with the eventful and dynamic history of Europe.

These two tendencies have consistently generated controversies which have always passionately interested activists. Overall the dominant tendency in the Euro-American academic world has stressed the diversity and exceptional character of European history. Elsewhere, the prevailing tendency has attempted to play down the particularities.

In the course of this discussion there have been slack times, for instance from the end of the nineteenth century to 1917, followed by the period of apparent unanimity imposed by the theory of the “five universal stages. ” There have also been moments when the stylish view prevailed, as with the asiatic mode of production. The flagrant West-centeredness of the end of the last century or the gospel of the five stages led to conclusions which seem absurd to us today. But it is probably equally erroneous to try to find the “asiatic” mode everywhere, in protohistory, among tribes around the world, and in the “great historical” empires. Ultimately, what purpose is served by generalizations based on a feeling of vague similarity imposed by a unitary conception of a generalized mode of production, be it feudal, asiatic, or tributary? How can we avoid being blinded by the many details of immediate reality (slavery here and not there; a highly monetized economy in one place and an almost natural one elsewhere; nonexistent or complete urbanization, etc)? How can we use the same concept of mode of production to analyze societies at so many different levels of development of the productive forces? It is well for those who wish to defend the unitary viewpoint to spell out the field of unity in order to avoid serious misunderstandings. Two observations seem relevant here.

2. First, the search for an ultimate unity beyond diversity applies only to societies wherein the level of development of the productive forces is the same. Of course, this does not mean exactly the same: the level is not the same in France and in the United States, but we can nonetheless agree that both are capitalist countries. It is necessary to consider three steps in the development of the productive forces and three corresponding sets of relations of production. If we do not try to link the essential content of the relations of production with the level of development of the productive forces, we are rejecting the very essence of historical materialism, which is the determination in the last instance by the economic base.

On the first step of the development of productive forces, the surplus is too small to permit more than the beginnings of class and state formation. This is why it seems absurd and non-Marxist to use the same term (asiatic or other) for lineage, clan, or tribal and state formations. Still, this is what the Hungarian scholar Ferenc Tokei, whose theses are better known in the West through Godelier’s interpretation of them (30-3, 30-4), tries to do. Tokei locates the “asiatic” mode (which he uses to characterize the great civilizations of the Orient) in the transition to class society. How can China, which in the eleventh century produced as much iron as Europe in the eighteenth and had five cities of more than one million inhabitants, be classed as being at the beginning of class society, and Europe, which was at the same level of development of the productive forces, be classed as being on the brink of industrial revolution?

It seems obvious that on this first step the low level of development is inextricably linked with lineage, clan, and tribal relations. It is these relations that enable the productive forces to begin developing beyond the phase of primitive communism (the transition to settled agriculture) and at the same time block their development beyond a certain point. Thus, wherever we find these relations, the level of the productive forces is necessarily low, and where we do not find them, it is necessarily high. The existence of these relations is furthermore the expression of the dominance of kinship (and the absence of the state). The forms of property that accompany this first step always—and necessarily—have basic traits in common: property is always communal and its use is regulated by the systems of kinship that control the dominant instance.

The second step corresponds to a level of development of the productive forces which makes the growth of the state both possible and necessary. That is, it necessitates the end of the dominance of kinship (which can continue to exist but only as a vestige dominated by another rationality). The forms of property corresponding to this second step are those which enable the dominant class to control access to the land and by means of this to extract tribute from the peasant producers. The extraction of this tribute is controlled by the dominance of ideology, which always takes the same form: state religion or quasi religion.

The high level of the productive forces under capitalism corresponds to the third step. This level involves capitalist property. That is, at one end, monopoly control by the bourgeoisie of the means of production, which are no longer mainly land but machines, equipment, and factories; and at the other end, free wage labor, the extraction of the surplus (here, surplus value) by means of economic exchange (the sale of labor power). Concretely, the development of agriculture beyond a certain point necessitated machines and fertilizers, i.e., industry and therefore capitalism. Born in the agriculture of the transition, capitalism thus had to expand elsewhere before returning to agriculture. This point is essential to an understanding of the particular features of peripheral capitalism (90-2).

Thus we have very general and abstract definitions of three forms of property—communal (of the land); tributary (of the land); capitalist (of means of production other than land). These stress the content of property understood as social control, rather than its juridical and ideological forms. The same conceptual framework will be used to investigate the problem of transcending capitalism. Each form of property necessarily corresponds to one step in the development of the productive forces. On the first step, organization of production remains at the lineage and village level. On the second, the organization of production is, at least in part (in fact, in its decisive part, not quantitatively but qualitatively) determined at the level of a state society, which is more or less extensive but always much bigger than the village. The circulation of the surplus (not necessarily in the form of commodities) accounts for the importance of specialized crafts, nonproductive functions, the state, the cities, commerce, and so on. A higher level of development necessitates a general market, a capitalist market.

On this level of abstraction, each step is universally necessary. Not to look for unity at this level is to reject the abc’s of Marxism. If we do this, history becomes not necessity but chance, and its explanation can be only idealist, structuralist, or psychologistic: the “genius of peoples,” and the like. West-centeredness involves this kind of explanation (the “destiny” of Europe) and therefore must negate the unifying principle.

3.    The second observation relevant to this inquiry is that the unifying principle of each step should be sought on the level of the basic mode of production rather than the social formation. Theorists like Perry Anderson (40-1) and others who refuse to make this conceptual distinction, use the argument of the variety of formations to negate the unifying principle (of the mode of production). To the extent that I emphasize this conceptual distinction, I am rejecting the argument based on the variety of immediate reality (90-1).

4.    What then are the basic, common characteristics of the mode of production (in the singular) of this second step of development of the productive forces? The first is that the surplus product is extracted by noneconomic means. This characteristic differentiates this first class mode from the communal mode preceding it. There the surplus product—which already exists—is not appropriated by an exploiting class. It is centralized by a ruling group for collective use and redistributed according to the needs of reproduction. The confusion between relations of cooperation and dominance (functions that oppose the governing and the governed, even without a state) and relations of exploitation underlies the failure to distinguish between the surplus product used collectively and the surplus product appropriated by an exploiting class. The confusion stems from the desire to reject those naive simplifications equating the communal mode with idyllic primitive communism. The extraction of the surplus product is thus like tribute to the profit of the exploiting class. This is why I propose to call this basic mode of the second step the tributary mode.

5. The second characteristic of the tributary mode is that the essential organization of production is based on use value and not on exchange value. The product kept by the producer is itself directly a use value meant for consumption, in general, for the producer’s own consumption. But the product extracted by the exploiting class is also directly a use value for this class. The essence of this tributary mode then is a natural economy, without exchange but not without transfers (tribute is one) and redistributions (50-2).

Still, there is in tributary formations what seems to be commodity exchange, which is sometimes nonmonetary (barter) but more often monetary. How can this be reconciled with the statement that use value is dominant? Here I will merely note that exchange, even monetary exchange, in these formations is not always nor even primarily commodity exchange; that is, it is not based on exchange value (the law of value) but on use value (comparative advantage). Maurice Dobb, followed by Kohachiro Takahashi, Rodney Hilton, and many others, because they forget this difference, have not arrived at an acceptable conceptual definition of the tributary mode (or of its feudal variation) (50-2).

For this is what is needed. The argument in favor of variety and particularity rests on the confusion between mode of production and social formation and the subsequent rejection of the abstract character of the concept of the mode of production. And yet this is what Marx taught us (reduction to two classes defined as two poles of a contradiction, absence of noncapitalist property, especially of land, etc.). No capitalist formation, however advanced and complete, can be reduced to this mode. The existence of landed property and of a third class of landed proprietors having a third kind of income (rent) proves this point. Exchange in tributary formations is subject to the fundmental law of the tributary mode just as land ownership is subject to the fundmental law of the capitalist mode in capitalist formations.

6. The third characteristic of the tributary mode is thus the dominance of the superstructure. Although there is general agreement on this point, a few comments are in order.

T ribute can never be extracted solely by means of violence: some social consensus is necessary. This is what Marx meant when he said that “the ideology of the dominant class is the dominant ideology of society. ” In the tributary mode this ideology takes the form of great religions: Christianity, Islam, Hinduism, Buddhism, Confucianism, and so forth. It is worth recalling that this domination aids in the extraction of the surplus, while the ideology of kinship in the communal mode, where ideology is also dominant, aids in the reproduction of relations of cooperation and domination but not of exploitation. Furthermore, local religions correspond to the communal modes and the dominance of kinship, in contrast to the state religions of the tributary mode. This is why it is not anthropology but the history of great precapitalist societies which has the most to teach us about the dominance of the superstructure. For in the communal mode there is no class struggle (except an embryonic one), while in the tributary mode the class struggle takes center stage. In addition, the fact that this struggle is connected in the precapitalist peripheral formations of our own time with the struggle for socialism explains the deep reasons for the contribution of Maoism.

In fact, the dominance of the superstructure is the first consequence of the dominance of use value in the economic base. The functioning of this dominance of class ideology has an impact on the class struggle in the tributary mode. The exploited class does not generally struggle for the total elimination of exploitation but only for its maintenance within the “reasonable” limits necessary for the reproduction of economic life at a level of development of the productive forces where the surplus product is collectively used. The theme of the emperor who can lose a heavenly mandate if exploitation exceeds these limits supports this. In the West, an alliance of the absolute monarchy against the feudal lords and in favor of the peasants had the same import.

Of course, this characterization of the class struggle in the tributary mode excludes neither class struggle nor steps toward the total abolition of exploitation: we find peasant communism everywhere, in Europe, the Arab world, and in China, as P.-P. Rey (10-6) and Jean Chesneaux (31-6) have pointed out. Generally, the class struggle in these circumstances took the form of challenging ideology on its own grounds: the Christianity of the state churches was challenged by Albigensian and Protestant heresies; Sunnite Islam was challenged by Shiism and Qarmat communism; and Confucianism was challenged by Taoism.

7. The fourth characteristic of the tributary mode is its appearance of stability and even of stagnation, the second consequence of the dominance of use value. This is a characteristic common to all tributary formations, including European feudalism, and not unique to the mythical “Asia” of Montesquieu, Bernier, and the anthropologists who want to revive the asiatic mode. This characteristic, which is highly relative, is a false appearance deriving from the contrast with capitalism. Based on exchange value, the basic internal law of capitalism functions on the level of the economic base: competition among capitalists necessitates accumulation, that is, a permanent revolution in the productive forces. This is an additional reason why I hesitate to equate the capitalist mode with the statist mode (a possible development), characterized by the centralization of capital and control over it. The tributary mode, based on use value, has no similar internal exigency on the level of its economic base.

And yet tributary societies are not stagnant. The very idea of nonmovement is foreign to Marxism. In fact, all tributary societies, whether in Egypt, China, Japan, India and South Asia, the Arabian and Persian East, North Africa and the Sudan, or Mediterranean or feudal Europe, have made great progress in the development of their productive forces. But progress does not imply qualitative change in the tributary relations of production. In the same way the United States of 1970 and England in 1780 represent two extreme moments in the development of the productive forces on the basis of the same capitalist relations. New relations of production grow up to overcome the block imposed by the resistance of old relations and, in their turn, bring about further development of the potential inherent in the new relations. However, the dynamic underlying the mechanism of development of the productive forces in the tributary mode lies in an area that simultaneously involves the base and the superstructure (which here is dominant).

8. How then is the class struggle carried out in the tributary mode and how does it necessarily lead to capitalism? The class struggle between peasant producers and their tributary exploiters spans the entire history of tributary formations, in Asia and Africa as well as in Europe. There is, however, an essential difference between this struggle and the struggle between proletarians and bourgeois under capitalism. The second can end in the victory of the proletariat and the establishment of a classless society. The first cannot end in a peasant victory. Each victory won by the peasants in these circumstances weakens the exploiting tributary class in favor of a third, nascent class, the bourgeoisie, and thus opens the way to capitalism.

This bourgeoisie grows up partly alongside the peasantry, on the basis of commerce and merchant capital, and partly within the peasantry which when even partially liberated becomes internally differentiated along the lines described below. This difference, which prevents us from schematizing and mechanically transposing the functions and perspectives of the class struggle from the capitalist to the tributary mode, is closely related to economic vs. ideological dominance.

Nonetheless, the class struggle in the tributary mode is also the motive force of history because it is the contradiction that leads to the transcendence of this mode in accord with the objective necessities of the development of the productive forces. Along these same lines, we should examine the class struggle under capitalism to see if it can lead to the displacing of capitalism by a statist mode which would bring about the new development of the productive forces and also operate to the benefit of a “new class. ”

Thus it is also class struggle which accounts for the changing character of the tributary mode and which impels the development of the productive forces within it. The search by the tributary class for a greater surplus is certainly not an inherent economic law analogous to the pursuit of capitalist profit. But it is the search for increased tribute—or even for the maintenance of tribute—which compels the tributary class, under the impetus of the peasant struggle, to improve production methods. For this reason I have tried to refute, since 1957, the then current thesis of external technical progress. in precapitalist formations by analyzing the dynamic of rent in peripheral capitalism.

Finally, class struggle within the tributary mode explains, at least in part, the external policy of the tributary class. This class seeks to compensate for what it loses inside the society it exploits by an expansionist policy aimed at subjugating other peoples and replacing their exploiting classes. This is the motivation behind all tributary wars, including feudal wars. At times the tributary class has even been able to mobilize the people for this type of venture. This may be compared with the dependence of external policy on internal class struggle under capitalism, even though the capitalist law of accumulation is of a different type. And it can also be compared with the alliance of the bourgeoisie and the proletariat of an externally oriented country under imperialism, following the prediction of Marx and Engels for England and the plan of action drawn up by Cecil Rhodes.

9.    These characteristics are common to all precapitalist class formations. They are sufficiently defining to merit a common designation, for which I propose the concept of tributary. The particular features—those of feudalism, among others—follow on the recognition of these common characteristics. But in order to approach the question of the particular features of different tributary formations correctly, it is necessary first to elucidate a series of theoretical questions concerning the relations of exchange and of circulation.

10.    In the concrete, there is virtually no such thing as autonomous, “simple petty commodity production.” The conceptual definition of this mode, which involves no exploiting class but only small, specialized producers owning their means of production and exchanging their products (in their entirety, in principle) according to the law of value, indicates its particular epistemological status relative to other modes.

Marx pointed to the conditions necessary for exchange to take place according to the law of value: exchange must be not occasional but systematic, not monopolistic but competitive, not marginal but of sufficient quantity to permit adjustments in supply and demand. These conditions do not usually obtain in the societies studied by anthropology (10-4). In 19571 made a similar statement about tributary formations, which are characterized by the absence of a generalized market in the means of production (land and labor power) and by the importance of self-subsistence. From this I concluded that in these formations exchange generally operates— and paradoxically, to all appearances—in accordance with neoclassical value theory (comparative advantage) rather than with the law of value which applies to a different form, to capitalism. This reflects the dominance of use values in precapitalist modes.

There is much confusion and ambiguity in the controversy about whether exchange in precapitalist societies has a “dissolving” effect. Perhaps this is because of the too frequent failure to recognize that exchange, which involves only a fraction of the surplus, is dominated by the law of the tributary mode. Under these circumstances, historical discussions about the relative and comparative importance of exchange flows, market organization, urban agglomeration, and so forth are not pointless but do not address the essential questions. The fact that no tributary economy has ever been “natural” proves nothing in favor of or against the notion of the dissolving power of commodity relations.

I do not underestimate the importance of commodity relations. I have stressed their role in Arab formations and shown that they had in their turn a decisive impact on the tributary mode by assuring its expansion: for instance, in Iraq during the great Abbasid epoch. And I have gone so far as to account for certain civilizations by the importance of these relations. The existence of these relations makes it necessary to examine the dynamic of relations between tributary societies. As a parallel, we would similarly be unable to examine central and peripheral capitalist formations in isolation from each other. Here we need to analyze the dialectical relations between internal and external forces in the dynamic of tributary socities and particularly in the transitions to capitalism.

Paul Sweezy notes, for instance, that the disintegration of feudal relations in Europe (the reasons for which will be examined below) ushered in a transitional period of precapitalist commodity production governed by the law of value, before the expansion of capitalism (50-2). He shows that this disintegration was produced by the transformation of payment in kind into monetary payment under the combined impact of the internal class struggle and the effects of large-scale commerce.

In 1957 I noted the even more striking case of New England, model par excellence of the precapitalist commodity mode. This is incomprehensible as an isolated case but completely understandable when its functions in the world system of the time are considered. Ignoring this aspect of reality is always a mistake. In the change from feudalism to central capitalism in Japan can we eliminate external forces and their interaction with internal forces? Is this interaction not decisive for the establishment of peripheral capitalism? And even more generally, beyond strict economic interactions, should we ignore those which operate on the superstructural level? Can we explain the particular forms of feudalism in Eastern Europe (“second serfdom”) without invoking both commercial relations with the West and the transfer of political and ideological structures: the borrowing, for instance, of the form of absolute monarchy from the West? As to the periphery of the capitalist system, can we exclude from our analysis ideological and cultural domination, borrowing in the areas of models of consumption, and technical and political organization?

11. Another problem which it is probably useful to examine before discussing the particular features of feudalism is the question of slavery. In my view the Greco-Roman exception is the source of a series of major confusions. I have already commented on the methodological questions raised by works that look for slavery on all continents and in all centuries, and in the doubtful nature of the supposed “slave mode of production.”

My first observation is that the publication of the Grundrisse led to an explosion of Marxology, which grew increasingly distant from Marxism as erudition took on the subject. Tokei’s exegesis, carried further by his students, always comes down to the same thing (30-2). With the emergence from the primitive community, two paths were open. The first was that taken by Asia: communities continued to exist and a despotic state superimposed itself on them. The communities remained the owners of the land, over which the producers, organized in families, had only a tenuous hold. This path was a dead end which blocked the development of the productive forces and reduced the history of Asia to an unchanging repetition of one superficial scenario.

The other path entailed the dissolution of the community and the assertion of individual private property in land. First, it engendered an initial, radical class division, fostering the reduction to slavery of those who had lost their agrarian property. From this came the Greek miracle, followed by its extension to the Roman empire. Then came the transformation of slavery into serfdom and the unique composition of feudalism. Seigneurial property, always private, fostered the development of the contradictions (autonomy of the cities, struggle of the peasants for peasant private property, etc.) which engendered capitalism. This is the path of constant change, of incessant progress. This was Europe’s path, which originated in Greek antiquity. In this unique path, slavery had a decisive role from the outset.

This theory is false from beginning to end and is based on nothing other than nineteenth-century Europe’s almost total lack of information about and strong prejudices with regard to a mythical “Asia. ” There has been no communal, collective ownership of the land in Egypt (for the past five thousand years at least) nor in China (at least since the Han), nor probably in India (with some qualifications). These societies have long had private property in land in the same way as had feudal Europe. They have never had slavery on a large scale and rarely serfdom in the European sense. Were the majority of caliphs and of Chinese emperors any more despotic than the absolute monarchs of Spain, France, or England? And everybody knows today that the development of the productive forces in Asia was on the.same level as and at least as rapid as that which took place in the West over the centuries from Homer to the Industrial Revolution.

And so? The theory reflects a West-centered teleology, inspired a posteriori by the capitalist development of Europe, which implies that no other society could develop capitalism on its own. If all this were true, we would have to conclude that the laws of historical materialism apply only to the West, that Western history is the incarnation of reason. This so-called Marxism is similar to the cultural nationalism of ideologues in the contemporary third world who reject Marxism because “it does not apply to our particular societies. ” At one end, West-centeredness produced by imperialist ideology and posing as Marxism; at the other end, cultural nationalism: these are true twin brothers.

12. The only interest this Marxology holds is as a curiosity of West-centeredness. Suffice it to say that slavery was exceptional because of the small number of societies it affected. Moreover, it coexisted with very different levels of development of the productive forces: from the city of Athens and from Roman Sicily to Lower Iraq under the Abbasids, to the plantations of America and, for all intents and purposes, to the mines of South Africa. Can relations of production be totally independent of the productive forces, as this suggests?

On the contrary, slavery always yields a commodity (a marketable product): in Classical antiquity, in Lower Iraq, in America. But commodity production was the exception in the precapitalist world. Thus the areas where slavery prevailed cannot be understood by themselves: they were only dependent parts of a much greater whole. Athenian slavery can be understood only by considering the Greek cities as part of the whole area with which they traded. For their specialization extended to an area which included the Orient—where slavery did not penetrate. In the Roman west slavery was limited to the coastal zones, the product of which could be commercialized. In Gaul and Spain the cost of transport stopped its extension, proof that slavery is linked with commerce. And America had no existence of its own; it was the periphery of mercantilist Europe.

Yet another characteristic makes slavery a necessarily exceptional mode: it barely reproduces the labor force. It thus almost always entails—and that quite early on—external raiding and dies when the source dries up. This is illustrated by the examples, farflung in time and place, of Roman raids among the barbarians and European raids in Africa. Of course, we must not confuse this kind of slavery with other forms which go by the same name. In reality the latter are a different phenomenon, and involve the reduction of the status of persons within diverse types of societies: for example, communal (without exploitation), or tributary (where the so-called slaves are domestics and state servants).

13. The feudal mode has all the characteristics of the general tributary mode as set out above. But it has the following additional characteristics outlined by Sweezy: (1) the organization of production within the framework of the domain, involving payment in labor; and (2) the exercise by the lord of political and jurisdictional prerogatives, which implies political decentralization. At least this was the case in the beginning (50-2). These characteristics are a precise reflection of the origin of the feudal formation in the barbarian invasions, invasions by peoples still in the stage of class formation as they were taking over a more advanced society. Thus the feudal mode is simply a primitive, incomplete tributary mode.

Feudalism did not grow out of slavery. The temporal succession is here perhaps an illusion. It reproduced the general law for the transition of a society without classes to a class society: after the communal stage comes the tributary stage (without the passage through slavery). The history of the West is no different from that of the East in this regard. And myths about asiatic communal property and so on can quite as easily and incorrectly be applied to the West. In addition, Japanese feudalism also left the communal stage without going through slavery.

It is a well-known fact that the barbarians were at the communal stage. Are the variations among these communities—Slavic, German, or Indian—of a different sort than the innumerable other variations discovered since then: Inca, Aztec, Mayan, Malagasy, pre-Islamic Arabian, plus a good thousand African varieties? Is it also an accident that, passing from this stage to the tributary stage, the Germans abandoned their local religions to adopt an imperial religion, Christianity? Is it an accident that the same thing happened in Africa with Islamization?

Feudal property is not radically different from tributary property. Rather, it is a primitive form of tributary property, a form resulting from the weak and decentralized character of political power. To contrast “eminent state ownership of the land” in Asia with seigneurial private property is to mix truth and falsehood. For the eminent ownership of the state functioned on the superstructural level—to justify taxes—but not on that of the technical organization of production. In European feudalism, eminent ownership by the Christian God functioned in the same way (the land must be worked, the peasants have a right to use it), in a weaker version corresponding to the rudimentary character of the state. Thus, with the development of the productive forces original political decentralization gave way to centralization. And the absolute European monarchies became very similar to complete tributary forms.

Those who espouse the asiatic mode of production try to reconcile things which are irreconcilable: the primitive character of the asiatic mode (chronologically the first, corresponding to the transition to classes) and the development of the productive forces in Asia, which development has finally been acknowledged. Thus they hypothesize an evolution from the tributary to the feudal mode (despite the survival of the state!). I believe exactly the opposite occurred: the primitive feudal mode evolved toward the tributary mode; the tributary mode is not the exception but the general rule and the feudal mode is a particular and exceptional variant of the tributary set.

Some think they can save the theory of the “Western miracle” (and of its counterpart, Asiatic desolation) by inventing a Chinese feudalism, assumed to have followed the asiatic mode. Would this Chinese feudalism be different from (and inferior to) Western feudalism because it followed not slavery but the asiatic mode, in conformity with Tokei’s schemas? But Western feudalism came out of the barbarian invasions and the Germans also went from the community to protofedualism, then to feudalism, without going through the intermediary stage of slavery. Godelier then tries the ultimate explanation: oriental feudalism did not engender capitalism because it was not “accompanied by a great development of commodity production and of money” (due to the tenaciousness of “peasant communities”) (10-14). But the survival of these communities exists only in the minds of those who talk about it. As to the development of a market, facts support the contrary position, that it was much more advanced in the East (Arab, Indian, and Chinese, among others) than in the feudal West. The reason for the early appearance of capitalism in the West lies elsewhere: by the time European feudalism attained the tributary stage under an absolute monarchy, it was too late.

Precisely because of its poor origins, European society traversed the tributary period more quickly. This is the thesis of unequal development: European society was more flexible because it was peripheral. It thus resolved its contradictions more quickly. These were the same as in other tributary societies and had necessarily to be resolved in the same way: by capitalism. But elsewhere these contradictions were better controlled and therefore developed less quickly. This is the general framework in which to place the history of the transition to capitalism.

Before analyzing this transition, it is useful to review these controversies about the uniqueness of feudalism and the asiatic mode. Those who deny that the primitive and undeveloped character of European feudalism was responsible for its more rapid transition to capitalism do so for ideological reasons. Refusing to accept the thesis of unequal development, they are forced to construct an alternative: hence the asiatic mode. But the notion is not based on reality. What is the difference between peasant communities in the Orient and the West? We know that the Western serf, like the Eastern peasant, had the right to use the land, that during the feudal period he could not be ejected by his lord. Although according to Tokei it was only in the asiatic mode that the individual needed to go through the community in order to get land, in fact this was also true of feudalism. As to eminent ownership by the Eastern state, the feudal lord also had this. And under absolute monarchy, when the king became the lord of all lords, his eminent property was very similar to that of the pharoah of Egypt or the emperor of China.

But, if Tokei’s schemas are without scientific value, I agree with Chesneaux that they have a clear ideological import (30-4). Godelier expresses this when he claims to have proven that “European feudalism was the only one to have made capitalism possible. ” Not the only one: just the first one.

14. The history of the transition to capitalism underscores the practical importance of the primitive, peripheral character of original feudalism. The first series of controversial questions concerns

the feudal cities, their importance, and their autonomy. There is no doubt that the cities, like the countryside, were less controlled by the central power. But arguments must go beyond immediate appearances, which are contradictory to begin with. Max Weber has been accused of exaggerating the autonomy of European cities and Rodney Hilton correctly observes that the most important city of the West, Paris, was tightly controlled by the monarch (50-2). John Merrington observes that cities became “refeudalized” when their bourgeoisies invested in landed property as in Italy, or allied with the feudal lords against the peasant revolts, as in France in the seventeenth century (50-2). He adds that the new capitalism rose outside the cities and to escape the guilds put its factories in the countryside, in Manchester and Birmingham. It was only very late, in the ninteenth century, that triumphant capitalism “ruralized” the countryside by destroying its craft production and limiting it to farm production alone.

Furthermore, the urban phenomenon is older than European feudalism. Classical antiquity was urban par excellence. Were its cities autonomous? Less than it seems: on the one hand, they were cities of landed proprietors and on the other, as they grew under the direct and indirect effects of large-scale commerce (onto which slave craft production was grafted) their domination over the distinct and foreign rural areas which they indirectly exploited remained precarious because it only operated through commercial flows and uncertain alliances.

Arab cities were in a generally analogous situation. As to Chinese cities, which were very important, they were contained, within a complete and very advanced tributary mode and reflected the complexity of its rich, secondary distributions of the surplus (flourishing crafts and manufactures). But like the Arab cities, Chinese cities were under the effective supervision of the central tributary power. This was the case throughout Chinese history. In the Arab world, when the tributary power weakened, the cities proliferated. By contrast, Japanese cities were important and autonomous for the same reason as in the West, namely, the weakness of the central feudal power. But they proliferated because the lack of external expansion, from which European cities benefited, obliged the Japanese merchant class to look toward the countryside and to invest in land purchase and usury.

Thus we can see the common thread running through this multiplicity of forms. The exceptional, accelerating role of feudal cities whether old (dominated by guilds strong in relation to the central power) or new (having neither guilds nor central power) stemmed from the weakness of the central power. When this latter asserted itself with the absolute monarchies, feudal relations already had more than begun to disintegrate even in the countryside.

15.    The early disintegration of feudal relations in the countryside was due also to the fragmentation of feudal power. This fragmentation allowed the class struggle rapidly to transcend the manorial economy, to impose petty exploitation through payment in kind and then in money. This transformation lightened the weight of tribute, accelerated peasant accumulation, and initiated differentiation within the peasantry. By the time the feudal class reacted, via the absolute monarchy they constructed to stop the liberation of the peasantry, it was too late (40-1). Serfdom had disappeared, the peasantry was differentiated, and the market had begun to grow.

The dialectic of the two paths of capitalist progression rests on this essential foundation. At one end was the establishment of manufactures and the putting out system, organized by merchant'capital grafted onto long-distance trade. At the other end was the establishment of small industrial enterprises based on the kulak peasantry. Between these two paths have been contradictions, doubtless secondary but nonetheless important, particularly when the big bourgeoisie won over the feudal monarchy, obtained protections in exchange, and profited from these to fight against competition from the dispersed bourgeoisie of the towns and countryside.

16.    It is not my intention to go into more detail about the transition, which took a great variety of concrete forms. There are no general laws of transition, only concrete, specific conjunctions of all the contradictions of the mode which is beginning to disappear and their interaction with external forces. The same is equally true for the socialist transition.

This is why “causes” may seem here to be “effect. ” As Anderson has emphasized, Italy suffered from the too early appearance of embryonic capitalist relations, Spain from its too early and disproportionate domination over America. In the West (France and England), the absolutist feudal state was established to compensate for the end of serfdom and was strengthened by advanced urbanization. In the East, absolutism found an urban void and was the means of establishing a serfdom required by the low level of the productive forces and by unoccupied land (40-1). Andre Gunder Frank (50-10), Oliver Cox (50-11), and Immanuel Wallerstein (50-4) complement more than they contradict this analysis based on the formation of absolutism with their own based on the formation of the world system and the dialectic of center-periphery relations. Finally, the study of the Japanese case is always instructive, first because the genesis of feudalism was different there and also because Japan did not benefit from a periphery as did mercantilist Europe.

Generally, all transitions are very instructive; this includes belated transitions, that is, those which have led today to dependent, peripheral capitalism. Subsequent history often depends on the form taken by this essential transition to capitalism. I agree with Anderson that in the West the absolute monarchy was toppled by the bourgeois revolution, that in central Europe the monarchy carried out this revolution from the top down, that in the East— already a semiperipheral situation—the monarchy was ousted by the proletarian revolution. I should add that from this time on this is the only possible path for the periphery: a “bourgeois revolution” is no longer possible. Thus we see the second manifestation of unequal development operating within the transition to socialism.

17. If feudalism had its particular features, so did each one of the other great tributary civilizations. I have discussed the particularities of Arab civilization in my recent book The Arab Nation (76b-6) and elsewhere those of the Ottoman Empire, in which the Balkan area yields striking parallels (76b-7).

Controversies about so-called asiatic societies, when they have gotten beyond Marxology to a Marxist analysis of reality, have contributed precious data of the dynamics of change through the comparative study of China, India, Africa, Malagasy, South Asia, and other areas. For there is no doubt that a Marxist must try to identify the forces and mechanisms that govern the movement of each of these cases, a movement which is irresistible. Those who try to identify in these areas so-called mechanisms of immutability are not doing scientific work. They are doing idealist and West-centered ideological work, like the bourgeois economists who analyze the “immutable” laws of “pure economy.”

Every tributary society looks different. But all of them can be analyzed by using the concepts of tributary mode of production and the class opposition between tributary exploiters and exploited (peasant) producers. The Indian caste system is a case in point. This false concept is a passive reflection of Hindu ideology (which here functions precisely in the same way as state ideology exercises its absolutist dominance, like Confucianism in China, for instance) and masks social reality: this can be seen in tributary appropriation of the land by the exploiters (Kshatriya warriors and the sacred Brahmin class), the exploitation of the Sudra, the redistribution of tribute among the clients of exploiting classes (the jajmani system). The remarkable work of Louis Dumont and Meillassoux’ subtle and pertinent critique of it (31-9) show that Indian castes had scarcely any existence except ideologically. In reality, what was at work was a system of tributary exploitation (here Meillassoux sometimes uses the word “seignorial,” so strong is the analogy with feudalism; at others he uses the more debatable term “slavery”).

The Chinese gentry type of exploitation and the Confucian ideology which accompanied it certainly had their particularities. But on the basic level of the class struggle between exploiters and exploited and the dynamic between them, the analogy is very great. The analogy is also very close with the Muslim Arab and Ottoman East, to the point where the interrelation between basic tributary relations and market relations functioned there in the same way: formation of merchant-usurer classes and private appropriation of the land, for example.

Bourgeois historiography about precapitalist societies has little to offer in the way of analysis. We have only to look at how the arbitrary definition of feudalism given by the authors of Feudalism in History (50-18) (feudalism is a method of government, not an economic system) allows them to skip from the Hittites to Sumer, from Shang and Chou China to the Parthians, from the Rajputs to Byzantium, and so on, thanks to a method which consists of looking for certain facts regardless of context. And yet in this abundant literature we can find much useful material if we are willing to rearrange it.

18. If slavery is recognized as exceptional and the communal modes are relegated to the distant past, only four formulations about the great class societies remain: (1) the “two ways” (European feudalism and the asiatic mode), (2) generalized feudalism, (3) the generalized tributary mode, and (4) the particularity of each society. The fourth position simply evades the theoretical problem and the first is false. The old formulation of generalized feudalism is not fundamentally wrong. In fact, my formulation of the tributary mode is nothing more than an improvement on it. But it emphasizes the incomplete character of the feudal variant of the tributary set. Its incomplete, peripheral character is due to the effects of the barbarian invasions and seems to explain better than any other theory the early development of capitalism in the West.

I have learned from an article published in La Pensee (no. 122, 1965) that the Japanese Marxist Jiro Hoyakawa proposed the term “triYmtary mode of production” in 1934.1 do not know the exact content of the Japanese controversy, except through several brief book reviews published in Western languages. In the 1950s I began to make a distinction between “feudalism in its general form” and in its “European type” and I substituted “tributary” and “feudal” for these unwieldy expressions for the first time in 1957. In another issue of La Pensee (no. 132, 1967) I learned that the Rumanian Ion Banu also uses the term “tributary. ” But he and I use this word in very different ways. For me, the tributary mode is the general form of precapitalist class society, of which feudalism is a particular type. Banu discusses the ideology of oriental philosophers from a perspective which seems to me close to that of the European revisionists who believe in the asiatic mode (Tokei, Godelier, etc.), that is, who are above all concerned to stem the Maoist tide.

I have attributed the incomplete character of the feudal mode to the lack of centralization of the surplus and to the fragmentation of power. Based on this, I stated that the European feudal mode evolved toward the tributary mode, with the establishment of absolute monarchies. This general direction did not preclude effective regressions, which took place here and there, from advanced tributary modes back toward feudal fragmentation. The centralization of the surplus implies both the real preeminence of the central power and a relatively advanced mercantilization of this surplus. Circumstances have made one or the other of these recede, and they have often done so in correlation. The feudaliza-tion of Arab formations is an example. This occurred, furthermore, in conjunction with the progressive domination of incipient European capitalism over the whole of the mercantilist world system and illustrates my thesis that the potential appearance of Arab capitalism was forestalled by that of Europe. In a certain way, the feudal mode is thus also a decadent tributary mode.

The opposition between the central, complete tributary mode and the incomplete character of the feudal peripheral mode is not on the same level as that between center and periphery in the capitalist system. In tributary formations, ideology is dominant and thus it is on this level that the complete or incomplete character of the mode underlying these formations is to be identified. An example is complete, tributary China: Chinese national unity was expressed in the common use of the written Mandarin language (linked to the state, which centralized the surplus), whereas diverse regional languages continued to be spoken in everyday use, and this linguistic unity went along with Confucian state ideology. This is why I speak of a nation only with regard to complete tributary formations.

Chapter 4

Unequal Development in the Capitalist Transition and in {he Bourgeois Revolution

1. One can hardly avoid asking whether the road of capitalist development has exhausted its potential in our modern world. To be precise: Can currently underdeveloped countries still catch up to the advanced capitalist countries, still become like them, by following the capitalist road?

A survey of the past, of events and of their interpretation, of what really happened and what was predicted, shows that capitalist development has always been unequal. There have always been some countries and regions that were more advanced and others that were backward. Today’s most advanced countries were not always so. Thus we must continue to analyze the concrete forms taken by the unequal development of capitalism in advanced and retarded, peripheral and “peripheralized” countries.

I. The different capitalist roads. The peasant component of the bourgeois revolution. Unequal development at different stages in history.

Marx and Lenin always believed that there were different roads of capitalist development and that these were related to class struggles and to hegemonic class blocs: the French road was different from the Prussian road, for instance. We can list an almost infinite number of roads and have something different to say about them from one day to the next. Is the English road, for example, responsible for the current decadence of Great Britain? Is there a Brazilian road and what are its particular features and perspectives? All cases are equally interesting.

It is usual to make a distinction between the revolutionary and the nonrevolutionary roads of capitalist development. Historical materialism will not permit us to conceive of capitalist development as an economic fact, that is, as an isolated transformation of the relations of production through the evolution of the productive forces, without the active intervention of political transformations.

Doubtless, new capitalist relations of production appear first within the previous system, whether tributary or feudal, and thus initiate the process of capitalist revolution. But, as long as political power remains feudal, they cannot develop fully. At a certain stage, then, power itself must change. This change constitutes the bourgeois revolution, strictly speaking. This is why in every case the development of capitalism is preceded by a change in the class content of the state. The revolution of 1688 in England, that of 1789 in France, German and Italian unification, the abolition of serfdom in Russia in 1861, American independence and/or the Civil War, the Meiji revolution in Japan, the fall of the Manchus in China, the Mexican revolution, the revolution of Ataturk, that of Nasserism, and many others represent qualitative breaks. Before them, power was precapitalist (feudal, for instance); after them, it was capitalist. But are all of these really revolutions? Marxists believe that 1688 in England and 1789-1793 in France were revolutions,'while the abolition of Russian serfdom and the Meiji and Nasserian coups d’etat were not.

If we want our words to have precise meanings which do not vary with the context and if we want to incorporate the Marxist-Leninist discovery about the conditions of revolutionary change necessary to the abolition of capitalism, we must define the “bourgeois revolution” as the abolition of the old state and the creation of a new one. In contrast to the adaptation of the old state for new purposes, its abolition involves not only violence (that is, in fact, the destruction of its legitimacy by means external to its own legal framework) but probably also the mobilization of massive (and therefore popular) and powerful social forces.

In this respect, it is obvious that the revolution in France, 1789-1793, was violent and popular, but so was the Mexican revolution, for instance. On the other hand, 1688 in England was scarcely more so than the Meiji revolution. The process of German and Italian unification, like the civil and foreign wars of Ataturk, was certainly violent and in a sense radical. But were these popular movements? And how much less so than in France?

2. In reference to the capitalist content of the era ushered in by these revolutions, we can define its popular content by its peasant component. A bourgeois revolution thus would be one which culminates in a violent class struggle between peasants and feudal elements in the countryside. The peasants win this struggle, impose the abolition of feudal rights and the division of land. Thus they impose themselves on the rising urban bourgeoisie, generally pushing the old merchant and financial big bourgeoisie into the counterrevolutionary camp and allying with the new potential bourgeoisie of artisans and petty producers. This opens the peasant road of capitalist development by accelerating differentiation within the peasantry and, ultimately, by creating a rich, exploitative kulak peasantry.

But by this definition there has only been one real bourgeois revolution: the French. The English revolution was scarcely one. The Mexican revolution took a similar form to the French revolution but it did not generate vigorous capitalist development: Mexico remained underdeveloped. Why? Probably because its revolution did not take place in the same period of global history, as we shall see.

The American road also diverged from the above pattern. From the beginning, it had a colonizing peasantry free from any feudal restrictions. This was true in the North of North America (British nonslave colonies), in Australia, and in New Zealand. To develop on this foundation, capitalism did not need an antifeudal revolution.

The above considerations finally lead to a question too often ignored: Is it correct to speak of a bourgeois revolution? Should we not restrict the term “revolution” to cases where the exploited classes challenge the global order, rather than use it to designate struggles between exploiting classes as well? If so, we can speak of a peasant but not of a bourgeois revolution. When a peasant revolution takes place, it opens the way to capitalist development; but it is not the only road this development can take. For capitalism had already developed within feudalism. Similarly, feudalism had developed within the slave system of the ancient world. Slave revolts and revolutions accelerated its development, but we cannot speak of a “feudal revolution. ” Is the expression “bourgeois revolution” not an invention of bourgeois ideology?

The transition to capitalism does not necessarily involve a revolution because it is a transition from one class society to another. This is why we cannot apply the lessons of this transition to the socialist transition. The abolition of classes involved in socialism presupposes a revolution carried out by the exploited. However, if such a revolution does not take place, the contradiction between the productive forces and the relations of production continues to operate within capitalism—and ultimately engenders, by evolution and not revolution, the transition to another class mode, the statist mode, which is discussed below. Reformist theory confuses this evolution, which cannot abolish classes but which can substitute new for old ones, with the abolition of classes, or socialism. At the limits, the revolution of the exploited may fail and engender this evolution toward the statist mode.

3. Thus the model of a bourgeois revolution is for all intents and purposes limited to France. From this a question arises: Will the revolutionary (exceptional) or nonrevolutionary (general) character of the capitalist road have differential effects on the subsequent class struggle, the one which becomes determinant in capitalist development, that is, the struggle of the proletariat against the bourgeoisie?

Three aspects of this question need to be considered. The first concerns the development of Marxism. Yes, it seems as if the revolutionary character of the transition to capitalism in France did affect later class struggles: Babeuf and Buonarrotti were not French by accident. And French socialism was one source of Marxism. But it was not the only one. The lack of revolutionary maturity in Germany accounts for German philosophy (Hegel in particular) and the character of English capitalist economic development, wherein ideology and politics played a minor role, accounts for Ricardo.

The second aspect of the question concerns the pace of subsequent capitalist development. This is a very controversial question. One view, based on the pace of capitalist development in France compared to that in England and Germany, holds that the French peasant road was an impediment to accumulation. According to this view, the bourgeois revolution should not be a peasant revolution and becomes one only rarely, due to a particular conjunction of class struggles and alliances. But this view has not always been accepted. Another view has it that the peasant road adjusted the relations of production to the needs of the development of the productive forces in the most radical and therefore the most appropriate way, giving them their maximum potential for later development.

The third aspect of the question concerns the class struggle in today’s imperialist era. There is no question of adopting a historical determinism which goes back so far into the past as to negate the importance of the impact of more recent circumstances on the class struggle. These new circumstances, those involving social-democratic ideological hegemony in relation to imperialism, for instance, have an infinitely more decisive impact.

4. Today, as in the past, capitalist development remains unequal and follows different roads. On the world scale we can distinguish at least between the central road of the imperialist centers and the road of peripheral, dependent capitalism in the countries dominated by imperialism and therefore underdeveloped. The question remains as to whether the latter are in a stage or in a permanent condition.

The analysis of unequal development can be enhanced by the method of comparative history. But it is important not to lose sight of the period in which particular developments take place. Thus, unequal developments in the beginning of capitalism (from the thirteenth to the sixteenth centuries in Europe), in the mercantilist era (1660-1800), in the preimperialist period of industrial capitalism (1800-1880), and in the imperialist period (since 1880) have neither the same meaning nor the same perspective.

II. Unequal development in the ancient and feudal world

5. Feudal Europe was not a homogeneous entity. Its regional social formations were of qualitatively different kinds and played different, unequal roles in their interrelationship. For these formations interacted and constituted a true whole, which because of its dominant feudal nature we are justified in calling global.

I characterized the feudal mode as a peripheral, tributary mode, meaning that in contrast to other, more advanced tributary societies the feudal European mode was an early, incomplete, and complex variant. The proximity of the more or less primitive barbarian community (Iberians, Celts, Germans, Slavs) explains its incomplete character: the absence of state centralization and redistribution of the tributary surplus, its “feudal fragmentation.” We can see its particular character clearly if we compare it to a pharaonic Egypt or imperial China. In the complete tributary mode (1) the fief was administrative and (2) the state generally coincided with a unified national formation.

The complexity of the European situation is certainly due in part to the fact that Christian feudalism arose from the disintegration of the Roman Empire. The imperial formations, first Hellenistic and then Roman, constituted in that part of the world the first tributary imperial constructs. In the ancient East, the transition from the primitive community to the tributary mode, the general form of advanced precapitalist class society, occurred very early. Having achieved its complete form in Egypt and Mesopotamia, the tributary mode progressively developed in rougher forms elsewhere, among the Hittites, the Medians, the Persians. But the region remained divided into relatively small states, separated by still primitive zones. The attempts at empire building (of Egypt, Assyria, and Babylonia in Persia) were too superficial to make of the Orient a single, national unit like China. In the interstices of this unequally developed and divided Orient, commercial societies had found a place: Phoenicia, then Greece. Slavery had spread in these societies along with the development of the market. The empire of Alexander, the successor Hellenistic states, then the Roman Empire repeated the imperial pattern without substantially advancing it. These empires remained heterogeneous in ethnic terms and tributary centralization remained unequal. Within them coexisted diverse modes of production, from the primitive community to the complete tributary mode, with some commodity exchange. Along with this slave enclaves developed.

In its turn the Roman Empire might have evolved into a complete tributary form and have gradually become more homogeneous. At any rate, it fell before doing so. Three entities grew up on the ruins of Rome: the Christian West, Byzantium, and the Arab-Islamic state. These latter two groups probably went further than the Roman Empire toward constructing the tributary mode, although they did not become complete. This progress was visible on the level of national unification, which has left its traces in our own day, at least in the Arab area (cf. 76b-6. 76b-7).

On the other hand, the West remained marked by the primitive societies of barbarian Europe. This is precisely the reason why feudal Western Christianity offered the most favorable conditions for the transcendence of the tributary mode and the rapid growth of the capitalist mode. Unequal development manifested itself in this manner. The long history of the ancient East, of Greek, Hellenistic, and Roman antiquity, of the Western, Byzantine, then Ottoman, and Arab-Islamic successors, is the history of the gradual development of the tributary mode and of its transcendence by capitalism beginning in its least advanced periphery: barbarian, then feudal, Europe.

To suggest that the empires of oriental and Roman antiquity were evolutionary stages in the establishment of a complete tributary formation is to say that the tributary form is superior to the forms of antiquity. It is also to contradict the thesis which places the asiatic mode of production before the slave mode and thereby contradicts the comparative level of the development of the productive forces. It is probably inaccurate to suggest that these attempts at empire might have homogenized the Mediterranean area as had occurred in China. Among other things, this fails to take account of the ethnic diversity of the region. The obstacles were such that imperial attempts to homogenize the area failed.

Nonetheless, striking progress toward homogenization was made extremely quickly in the course of several centuries, or even several decades. In the Asiatic Orient linguistic unification on the basis of Aramaic laid the foundation for subsequent and rapid Arabization. In the West the Romanization of Italy, Gaul, and Iberia testifies to the power of the tendency toward homogenization. It is possible to draw too strong a contrast between the fragmentation of Europe and the Middle East on the one hand as against Chinese homogeneity on the other. The linguistic unification of China was limited to writing, closely related to state unity and tributary centralization, while regional diversity of spoken languages—which still exists—threatened imperial unity during several millenia. In the West the tendency toward homogenization never ceased working! Beyond the variation of history, Arabization and Islamization at one end, and the establishment of absolutist national monarchies following the feudal fragmentation caused by barbarian and other invasions at the other, both illustrate this tendency.

6. The history of Western Christianity should be reexamined in terms of this global framework. The feudal mode, as an incomplete tributary form, dominated the whole of the Christian West. But it did not spread evenly throughout the region. One can distinguish three unequally developed subregions of feudal Europe. The most developed of these was Italy and the regions that make up the area known today as the Languedoc (Spain was conquered by the Muslims). In this relatively developed region feudal forms did not expand because they came up against a more solid ancient heritage, particularly in the cities which were more important here than elsewhere. The second region, including northern France, England, Holland, western and southern Germany, and Bohemia, was partially developed. Feudal forms grew and capitalism found its most fertile soil in this region. Farther east and in the north (eastern Germany, Scandinavia, Hungary, Poland, and Russia) the original level of development was not as high and the pretributary community was quite close. Feudalism appeared later and took particular forms related on the one hand to the modalities of integration of these regions into Europe (the Hanseatic League, Scandinavia, Prussia, and Poland) and on the other hand to the modalities by which relations of external domination functioned (Turkish occupation of Hungary, Mongol occupation of Russia, Teutonic occupation of the Baltic regions, etc.).

7. Returning to, the feudal mode, which dominated the area, three aspects of its history should be emphasized: (1) feudal fragmentation and its meaning in relation to the specific phenomenon of the church, (2) the persistence of market relations, their origin, and their effects, and (3) the ways in which feudal societies expanded.

Feudal fragmentation, unlike the centralization of the complete tributary form, was characterized by a particular set of relations between the economic base (tributary) and the ideological superstructure. In all the modalities of the tributary mode ideology was the dominant instance, in the sense that social reproduction operated directly on this level. However, in the complete tributary mode, this ideology was the ideology of the state, even though it may have taken a religious form. In this case the superstructure was perfectly adapted to the relations of production.

Conversely, in the feudal mode the ideology, which was Catholicism, did not act as a state ideology. Not that anything in Christianity precluded this. Under the Roman Empire, Christianity became a state ideology as it did in Byzantium and in the Russian orthodox world, i.e., precisely in those regions closest to the complete mode. But, in the feudal West, Catholicism was resisted by the fragmentation of the tributary class and by peasant resistance, evidence of the survival of the spirit and ideology of the original communal societies. The independent organization of the church reflected this less perfect adaptation of the superstructure to the relations of production. This created a more flexible and therefore a more favorable climate for subsequent evolutions and adjustments to the exigencies of the transformation in the relations of production. These adjustments took two forms: the modification of the ideological content of religion (Protestantism), and the elevation of religion to the place of state ideology (in the form of Gallicanism or Anglicanism, for example), as royal absolutism gained strength in the period of the mercantilist transition.

8. Since external and internal market relations continued to exist, we cannot conceive of feudal Europe as a subsistence economy composed of a series of fiefs. Long-distance trade with Byzantine and Arab areas, which had been more advanced for a long time, Monsoon Asia, and Black Africa, and the impact of this trade on internal European and local trade gave structure to feudal Europe. The coexistence of predominantly rural zones, which were less urbanized, and zones of commercial and artisanal concentration testifies to this particular structure. Italy, with its artisanal and merchant cities (Venice, Florence, Pisa, Genoa, etc.), and southern Germany and the Hanseatic League have a place in medieval Christianity which can only be understood in terms of these market relations. By reference to the later characteristics of the European mercantilist world economy Wallerstein speaks here of “mini world economies” (50-4). In these regions, particularly Italy, not only were the productive forces more highly developed (manufacturing) but also embryonic capitalist relations appeared sooner. However, it is not these advanced regions that ultimately became the centers of capitalist development but the partially developed regions described above.

9. The expansion of the feudal system took place differently from that of complete tributary empires and led rapidly to the mercantilist transformation of forms of social organization. The complete tributary systems showed a remarkable capacity for geographical expansion without a qualitative transformation of their internal organization. This type of expansion, under appropriate geographical and other conditions, may have continued for centuries: Chinese history provides the best example of this.

In contrast, the homothetic expansion of feudal Europe was brief—a century and a half from 1150 to 1300 (cf. 40-3, 40-4, 40-8, 50-4). This expansion without change, carried out by breaking new land and by colonization, underwent a crisis from 1300 to 1450, propelled by decreasing output from existing technology. This led to a series of technical revolutions in agriculture, facilitated by the flexibility of the relations of production, which also underwent change: serfdom was lightened or abolished, payment in money was substituted for payment in kind or in work, and so on. A second wave of expansion, which already had new characteristics, followed: the search for food products or wood through the colonization of new lands, whether reconquered from the Arabs (Spain and Portugal) or located on the Euro-Asian steppes (the Ukraine and Siberia) or the islands of the Atlantic.

This occurred not only on the initiative of the feudal lords, whose income had diminished due to the effects of the transformation in the relations of production; through a class struggle which was particularly sharp—perhaps due to the proximity of the primitive community—the peasants forced feudal tribute to be lightened. It was at once the initiative of the merchants and monarchs. This expansion initiated the establishment of the economic system of the mercantilist world, which formed the transition to capitalism. And it was precisely in this system that the old advanced regions (Italy and the Hanseatic League) lost their advantage and dominant position to the new centers of northwestern Europe.

10. A series of questions arises concerning the nature—feudal, capitalist, or transitional—of the mercantilist system. There are two contending viewpoints. The majority position sees in the three centuries from 1500 to 1800 a transitional period during which the capitalist mode gradually established itself within the feudal system. Based on certain analyses of Marx and Engels, historians who adopt this position believe that the absolute monarchies were able temporarily to constitute themselves as a power above classes by exploiting to their own ends the feudal-bourgeois conflict. The minority tendency, whose best known exponent is Perry Anderson (50-1), holds that the dominant character of the economic and political system remained feudal and that the absolute monarchy was a means by which feudal elements responded to the threat of the rising bourgeoisie.

Of course, the answer to this question is related to the class struggles of the period, the interrelation between them (peasant and bourgeois struggles), and their relation to the development of the productive forces. The debate about the respective roles played by the disintegration of feudal relations of production and by the development of the Atlantic market economy with the birth of capitalism must be placed within this framework. Here also three viewpoints emerge. According to the first the disintegration of feudal relations under the impact of peasant struggles was alone responsible for the birth of capitalism. According to the second the mercantilization of the economy, following from the import of American gold and silver, was decisive. Finally, according to the third these two poles are part of a dialectical unity.

The facts do not speak for themselves with regard to any of these questions. Facts are chosen to serve theoretical hypotheses and are interpreted in the light of them. In addition, the facts are extremely varied. The most serious studies prove only one thing: that class struggles were not the same in France, Italy, or Russia, the development of the productive forces was unequal,

and the effects of the Atlantic economy manifested themselves in different ways.

11. Thus we need to develop an overall theory of the mercantilist system. A theory (and not simply a history) of the mercantilist system must answer the central question, i.e., whether the mercantilist period was still feudal, already capitalist, or transitional. If the latter, the theory must make explicit the play of forces which made the growth of capitalism inevitable. But at the same time it must also account for the inequalities and asymmetries that developed during this period, both between Europe and its colonies, dependencies, and overseas partners and within Europe itself.

There is an extensive literature on these questions, which the reader would find useful; notably the volume edited by Rodney Hilton (50-2), the recent work by Perry Anderson (40-1), and the studies of the mercantilist world system by Wallerstein, Cox, Frank, Vilar, and others (50). As long as we deal in general terms with the overall effects of the explosion of Atlantic commerce on European societies, we will not make much theoretical headway, for the reactions to these effects were different in every area.

The first example concerns economic effects in the strictest sense of the term (prices and wages). Of course, everywhere inflation followed the influx of American silver (not because of the sudden rise in the quantity of coin, as Bodin thought, but because of the reduced price of its production, as Marx understood). But the price-wage distortion evolved very differently from one region to the other of Europe, changing the relative profitability of manufacturing activities, the relative real weight of ground rent in money, and the real income of the small commercial peasants and/or the gentlemen farmers.

Both Wallerstein and Pierre Vilar correctly trace the gradual movement of inflation from the West to the East. While in 1500 the price differential between the Mediterranean and Eastern Europe was 6 to 1, by 17 50 it w.as 2 to 1. But Wallerstein notes that the price-wage distortion at times favored and at others discouraged nascent capitalism. In Venice the too rapid rise in wages ate into the profit margin. In France and Spain on the other hand, real wages dropped too much and as a result the market for manufactured goods was insufficient. In England it seems that a sort of optimum condition was created by the stability of wages, which did not return to the 1250 level until six centuries later in 1850.

These distortions brought about an important result: the modification of the international division of labor. Wallerstein remarks that the decisive change which took shape in the seventeenth century was not in technological progress but in the localization of activities. The old manufacturing regions (Italy and Flanders) declined because their prices were too high and because they were unable to overcome French and English protectionism. On the other hand England, up till then an exporter of wheat and wood, became a manufacturer and exporter of manufactured goods.

The second example concerns relations of production. All European societies responded to the call of the market, but in such different ways that it is not correct to say that money everywhere destroyed feudal relations. In some places it did destroy them, but in others it strengthened them. In the West, particularly in England and also in France to a lesser extent, old feudal relations gave way either to a small landed peasantry (although still subject to seigneurial rights, albeit in a lightened form), or to a land tenure system which was less disadvantageous to the tenants. To the east of the Elbe the opposite took place, serfdom was strengthened and the corvee made heavier. In America, although commodity production was much more important than in Europe, slave, quasi slave, or serf relations prevailed in the plantations, the mines, and the encomiendas. This illustrates the point about the correlation between slavery and commodity relations.

The third example concerns political and ideological evolution. The monetarization of the economy and the impact of this on the development of the transformation in the relations of production taken as a whole at times strengthened the state and at other times undermined it. Wallerstein proposes an attractive thesis to deal with this question: in the centers (where the commercial balance was favorable due to their growing capacity to export manufactures) the influx of monetary means facilitated the creation by the monarchy of a bureaucracy which in turn made higher taxes possible. In the periphery, where the situation was reversed, the first transfer of money closed a vicious circle which weakened the state. This much is true. But Poland nonetheless was caught in this vicious circle and disappeared as a result, while Russia was able to avoid it and strengthen its state apparatus. Whatever the case, and even if this somewhat too economistic and mechanistic argument seems unsatisfactory, the other attempts to deal with this question are unacceptable. The Protestant ethic (Weberian idealism) is an illusion, as Wallerstein has stated. If we compare Italy and Poland, Spain and Hungary, we can see that Catholicism, like Protestantism, could be adapted to very different situations. To invoke nationalism to explain the establishment of strong nation-states and regionalism to account for the lack of such states is tautological. We are reduced to narrative history, which does nothing more than explain the immediate flow of events.

The debate about the feudal vs. the capitalist character of the mercantilist period gets us nowhere because the question is incorrectly posed. The real question is: What were the existing classes, how were their struggles and alliances organized, and how did the economic struggles of these classes, as well as their ideological expression and their effect on political power, interface?

There is probably general agreement that the period was a transitional one, wherein feudal and capitalist relations coexisted. There is probably also general agreement that the dominant character of society was feudal in England until the revolutions of the seventeenth century (Cromwell, then 1688), in France until 1789, and in Germany and Italy until nineteenth-century unification. The feudal nature of political power was a sign of this dominance. But it would be formalistic to view bourgeois revolutions as absolute breaks with the past. For the class struggle between feudal and bourgeois elements began before and continued after this break, becoming involved in the organization of power and modifying its

content. Cromwell’s radical revolution was followed by a restoration, then by a second mild and incomplete “revolution” (I hesitate to use the term) carried further by the peaceful extension of the franchise in 1832. In France, the revolution that culminated in 1793 was followed by a long restoration. The revolution in 1848 was still part bourgeois, part proletarian (but already in 1793 embryonic proletarian demands followed on the heels of the bourgeois revolution, as Daniel Guerin, following Marx, notes [51-3]) and was followed by a second restoration. German and Italian unification were not revolutionary but created the conditions for sweeping social change. Was the abolition of serfdom in Russia in 1861 the bourgeois break? Or was it February 1917? Moreover, history has shown that the socialist revolution is no different: the class struggle continues after it, although it creates a point of no return in the process of social change.

The mere existence of the feudal reaction is insufficient to allow us to characterize Western absolutist power as feudal. At the same time there was the development of a free peasantry, initial differentiation of capitalist classes within this peasantry (“laborers,” “bras nus,” yeomen, and agricultural workers), the expansion of manufacturing, and differentiation within the crafts as they threw off the guild restraints.

12. Thus I propose the following five theses relative to the transition to central capitalism.

(1) Each mode of production is characterized by its own contradictions and thus by its own specific laws of motion. The feudal mode, as one member of the large tributary set, is characterized by the same fundamental contradiction (peasant producers-exploiting tributary class) as all the other types of the tributary mode. But there are no laws of transition. Each transition involves the working out of a historical necessity—the transcendence of the old relations of production so that the latent and mature development of the productive forces may take place on the basis of new relations—through the concrete interrelation of numerous specific contradictions within a social formation (and not a mode of production). There are no laws for the transition to central capitalism any more than for the transition to peripheral capitalism or to socialism. There are only concrete situations.

(2)    The feudal mode, as an incomplete, primitive, peripheral form of the tributary mode (which existed in complete form elsewhere, including China and Egypt) had a profound inherent tendency toward completion. In this sense, the movement from the feudal fragmentation of the Middle Ages to royal mercantilist absolution is not a chance occurrence. The primitive character of the feudal mode resulted from the combination of the disintegration of the Roman Empire, which was evolving toward a tributary form, and the acceleration of the transformation of the barbarian communal mode. Perry Anderson has made this point beautifully (50-1). The greater flexibility deriving from the incomplete character of the feudal mode made for its more rapid transcendence through the early growth within it of embryonic forms of the capitalist mode.

(3)    The class groups present during the mercantilist period were therefore three: the peasants, the feudal lords, and the bourgeois. The tripartite class struggle involved shifting blocs of two against one. The struggle of the peasants against the feudal lords led to differentiation within the peasantry and to the development of petty agrarian capitalism and/or to the adaptation of feudalism to an agrarian capitalism of large proprietors. The struggle of the urban bourgeoisie (merchants) against the feudal lords interacted with the peasant struggle and gave birth to manufacturing, the putting out system, and so forth. The bourgeoisie tended to divide into an upper fraction which tried to compromise (royal protection of manufactures and merchant companies, enoblements and assumption of seigneurial rights, etc.) and a lower fraction which was forced to become radical.

(4)    The tendency for feudal fragmentation to evolve toward absolutist power took place on the basis of these struggles. Depending on the relative power of each group (and subgroup) this evolution sped up or stopped, took a certain form and content (support of a given principal class). Power thus gained a certain autonomy, to which Marx and Engels called attention. It was ambiguous and switched its support from one to the other. If the establishment of centralized states (which some too simply call feudal) did not forestall but rather accelerated the evolution to capitalism it is because class struggles intensified within them.

Here my thesis is that by the time the tributary mode acquired its complete form in Europe (with the absolute monarchies) it was too late: the new class contradictions (agrarian capitalism and manufacturing capitalism) were already too far advanced for the state to arrest their development in any real way. In relation to these combinations, which have particular features in each case, we must analyze: (a) the movement of the international division of labor (between the regions of mercantilist Europe and between certain of them and the overseas peripheries they created) and (b) the content of the great ideological currents (Reformation, Renaissance, Enlightenment) which have to different degrees a big bourgeois, a petty bourgeois (agrarian and/or artisanal), a peasant, and even at times an embryonically proletarian (where the bourgeoisie is born, so is the proletariat) character.

(5) At the end of the period there emerged a world conditioned by the results of a new type of unequal development, different from the results of the unequal development of previous eras (tributary, feudal): the unequal development of the mercantilist period. In 1800 there were capitalist centers on one side and peripheries on the other, the latter for the most part created by the emergence of the former. But among capitalist centers some were complete (England and to a lesser degree France) and others were not; we must trace their subsequent history.

13. With this theoretical apparatus we can now make sense of the different evolutions which took place within mercantilist Europe. Let us return to Wallerstein (50-4), Cox (50-11), and Frank (50-10), who have made an analytical advance on the basis of the center-periphery distinction. By emphasizing the effects of center-periphery relations on the dynamic of the centers, they have made a decisive contribution to a field previously distorted by Eurocentrism. Unfortunately, Perry Anderson’s almost total neglect of the center-periphery problem reduces the significance of his work.

Wallerstein’s distinction, based on the introverted or extroverted nature of central and peripheral economic development, beginning in the mercantilist period as a prelude to the subsequent establishment of the complete capitalist system and of contemporary imperialism, has remarkable synthetic power. Of course, the introversion or extroversion results from the combination of class struggle in the different regions of the system during the period.

England is the model par excellence of a mercantilist center. Wallerstein observes that this nation was not only commercial but manufacturing and commercial. It tightly controlled its imports in order to strengthen its autocentric development; it was not autarchic but conquering. He remarks that the true religion of this absolutist state was not Protestantism but nationalism, as the existence of Anglicanism indicates.

The French model is analogous (including on the religious and ideological plane: Gallicanism), except for its diverse external attractions (Paris and the north were pulled toward Anvers; the west toward the New World; the Midi toward the Mediterranean). These attractions were the internalization of external struggles: Huguenot and Catholic alliances with foreign powers, England and Spain, which the king finally broke after protracted struggles; the attempt of Franqois I to thwart Charles V in his drive to establish a continental empire; and pointless battles in Italy and Flanders.

At this stage, the other regions of Europe failed to become complete mercantilist centers. The previously more advanced regions (Italy and Flanders) declined. The Italian cities declined not because the establisment of the Ottoman Empire dried up their trade (on the contrary, it brought a new expansion of West-East commerce) but precisely because they were more advanced (we have seen the effects of their advanced character on the prices-wages-profits dynamic). The same applied to Flanders. Holland took the place of these countries. It remained a commercial and maritime power whose prominence hung in the Anglo-Spanish balance: the Dutch kept their place so long as England did not yet control the seas and Spain, fearing English depredations, was less afraid of Holland. This accounts for the short-lived rise of Holland, followed by its stagnation and retreat until its belated industrial awakening, based essentially on colonial pillage.

Spain and Portugal, which were the first to create a periphery, paid for this advance with their subsequent backwardness. They rested content with monopoly profits from the pillage of America and used them to pay for the import of English and French manufactures. Thus they became economically extra verted and dependent. Their parasitical role and underlying poverty became suddenly apparent when they lost control of America. At the same time, they helped to strengthen the introverted and aggressive autonomy of the English and French centers.

Russia reacted to the threat of peripheralization by creating its own periphery in Asia and by strengthening its state. When in the nineteenth century it was integrated into the world system as an exporter of wheat and an importer of manufactured goods, it escaped the fate of semicolonization thanks to the strength of its state, which actively intervened to promote autonomous industrialization of the country. The same was true for Prussia. On the other hand, as a wheat exporter, Poland quickly became peripheralized. Its state grew weak and then disappeared. Sweden, unsuccessful in its initial attempt to use foreign conquest to compensate for the weakness of its agriculture and the strong resistance of its peasant communities to feudalism, just managed to escape Poland’s fate. Turned inward, it was integrated into the world system only very belatedly but directly as an advanced, autonomous industrial center.

Thus the division of the capitalist world took place during the mercantilist period. The industrial centers (through the growth of their manufactures and the flourishing of petty rural and craft capitalism) satisfied their own needs (and in that were autocentric) and thus acquired a decisive capacity for external aggression. The peripheries, created as incomplete, extraverted economies complementary to those of the centers, furnished wheat, sugar, and precious metals. The wheat, sugar, and metals were produced within modes that were precapitalist in form (serfdom or slavery) but were new in the sense of having been established directly by or for the metropoles because this made possible the superexploitation of labor power.

But by the end of the mercantilist period vast regions of the world were still not part of this center-periphery division. Certain European countries were not deliberately peripheralized but rather were blocked, retarded, and still could have evolved in either direction. This was the case for Spain, Portugal, Italy, Germany, Austria, Hungary, and Russia. Poland disappeared to their profit. All these countries became autonomous centers during the nineteenth century. Relay points of the center-periphery system also became autonomous centers: New England took over almost all of English America, for example. Other regions were still exterior, to use Wallerstein’s terminology: Japan, the Ottoman Empire, China. These countries were involved in world mercantilist commerce but remained completely autonomous. They exported and imported— in small quantities and in a completely controlled way—what their ruling classes wanted to exchange, generally rare products. In the Indian Ocean trade did not foster accelerated accumulation in the center as did Atlantic trade. India and Indonesia, partially subdued by military conquest, had not yet been made into peripheries. This did not occur until the Industrial Revolution, when the English systematically destroyed Indian manufactures and crafts and the Dutch established semislavery plantations in the Indies. Finally, Black Africa, despite its apparent autonomy, had already become peripheralized during the mercantilist period as a provider of slaves for the American periphery.

IV. Unequal development in the bourgeois revolution

14.    Unequal development within mercantilist Europe resulted from combinations of class struggles particular to each formation. Studies of the peasant component of these struggles (50, 51) have inspired four theses.

15.    First thesis: the struggle between exploited peasants and their tributary (feudal) exploiters is the decisive one in the combination of struggles leading to the capitalist transition. Where the complete character of the tributary mode made this struggle more difficult, the (urban) bourgeoisie lacked the ally it needed to force the power to deal with it; this slowed the transition to capitalism. The reverse was true for feudal societies, that is, incomplete tributary societies (Europe and Japan). This is the expression of the unequal development of systems. Obviously, when the bourgeoisie was too weak, peasant struggles failed because in themselves they could not produce capitalism. This was the case for the peasant wars in Germany, while peasant struggles in England and France cleared the way for capitalist development.

The peasant-tributary class struggle certainly characterized all precapitalist class societies. It was their primary contradiction, just as the proletariat-bourgeoisie contradiction is primary in the contemporary capitalist system. The peasant revolt is to precapitalist class societies what the strike is to the capitalist system.

But just as proletarian struggles vary greatly in intensity and radicalization from one country and one period to the next, so too do peasant, antitributary struggles. The objective (perhaps determining) framework fostering or dampening this intensity lies in the origins of tributary society. The modalities of the transition to feudalism in the regions still close to primitive communalism were probably the decisive factor in fostering intensity. There people could still remember, and were perhaps still experiencing, feudal dispossession, at the same time as the new class struggle against feudalism was beginning.

However, this general framework was not determining in an absolute and mechanical way. Diverse circumstances accentuated or reduced its potential impact. Among these circumstances was the extent of external market relations: long-distance trade. It is highly likely that the mercantilization of the Atlantic economy (especially the transition to payment in money and the attraction of new consumer products which the feudal class had to purchase) sharpened the basic class struggle in Europe. Peasant and bourgeois struggles interacted and mutually reinforced one another in an escalating historical spiral. The development of trade gave the peasants an ally and at the same time an outlet for their independent commodity production when they extracted concessions from the feudal lords. The development of petty agrarian capitalism freed a labor force and thus increased the possibility that manufactures, urban commerce, and so on would develop. Conversely, where the bourgeois or peasant element was weak, a reverse spiral put a brake on the necessary movement of history.

Other circumstances also intervened. The external expansion of the tributary mode attenuated peasant struggles (similarly to the effects of imperialist expansion on the proletarian class struggle). This expansion took the form of the colonization of “empty” lands (by the Portuguese, the Spanish, and the English in America; by the Russians in Siberia and the Ukraine—there is an analogy with the effects of proletarian emigration to North America and Australia). But it also took the form of colonizing foreign peoples (Germanization of Slavic lands, etc.), in which case national struggles obscured the class content.

For all these reasons, the political play of classes in relation to power as well as the content of the related ideologies acquired a certain autonomy. Generally, the great ideological currents that accompanied the transition to capitalism were ambiguous: they contained a peasant and a bourgeois component (for instance, Protestantism). The fact that the peasant component was rarely completely independent (it was so only in the religious form of millenarian “communism”) shows that additional development of the productive forces was historically necessary before a classless society could become possible.

16. Second thesis: the more intense and radical the peasant struggle, the more revolutionary the process of overthrowing the feudal state and the purer the bourgeois character of the successor state (this is almost tautological). Does it also follow that the process of capital accumulation will be more rapid? This is debatable.

As we know, Marx distinguished between the revolutionary road of the transition to capitalism and the Prussian (we might say reformist) road. In the first the peasants freed themselves from feudal tutelage, establishing a “simple petty commodity” economy of free peasants. Differentiation was taking place among them and resulted in a kind of diffuse agrarian capitalism. In the same way crafts workers, freed from guild restrictions, created small, dynamic industrial enterprises. “The producer became a merchant.” The reverse took place where commercial capitalism became merchant-entrepreneurial, manufacturing, and then industrial (putting out) capitalism and/or when the feudal lord became a merchant lati-fundiary. The second road, then, did not result from internal necessity but from external factors, from integration into the mercantilist and capitalist (though pre-monopoly capitalist) system. “Revolution from above” or even reform rather than revolution, although with the necessary participation of social forces from below?

The French revolution is the model of the radical bourgeois revolution. As analyzed by Albert Soboul, the bloc of free peasant and petty craft producers stood against the bloc of the oligarchy of great feudal proprietors and the commercial and financial big bourgeoisie (51-1). Later the empire and then the Restoration tried to impose a compromise to safeguard the interests of the big bourgeoisie and the great capitalist proprietors descended from the feudal lords. However, the abolition without compensation of seigneurial rights and the sale of national goods, which could not be reversed by later reactionary forces, strengthened the position of the small peasantry, particularly its kulak sector. According to a widely accepted thesis, adopted by Eric Hobsbawm, the weight of this small peasantry slowed the subsequent development of capitalism in France (51-6).

The English revolution was, in fact, less radical. In this country the free small peasantry and its rich yeoman sector were older and had been the champions of the Cromwellian revolution (followed by the Levellers, whose revolutionary ideology was radical in a way unparalleled at the time). Here reactionary forces were able to impose a compromise more favorable than in France to the big bourgeoisie and the great landed aristocratic proprietors who had begun the agricultural revolution. This was a form of capitalist modernization similar to that effected by the Prussian Junkers and the great Russian, Polish, and Hungarian proprietors. The revolution of 1688 testifies to the nature of this compromise, under which England lived until in the mid-nineteenth century the abolition of the Corn Laws destroyed the standing of agrarian capitalism to the exclusive profit of industry.

My interpretation of the different paces of subsequent industrial development (fast in England, slow in France) differs from that of these two conflicting theses. In France, the factor that slowed industrialization was not the existence per se of a tenacious group of petty peasant proprietors, because a process of internal differentiation could rapidly have destroyed such a group. It was the power of the proletariat that forced the peasant alliance on the bourgeoisie. The French proletariat had this power not because of its numbers (which in the nature of things was in proportion to the level of industry) but because of the radical antecedents of the revolution. The peasant alliance had its price: agricultural protectionism, which put a brake on the internal differentiation of the peasantry and checked industrial growth both by slowing the rural exodus and by limiting the means of industrial accumulation.

England overcame this obstacle sooner. Differentiation within the peasantry accelerated before the Industrial Revolution, in conjunction with the modernization of the great estates. The Industrial Revolution therefore had at its disposal a bigger proletariat than it had anywhere else. This proletariat almost became radicalized after the Industrial Revolution, during the time of Chartism. Perhaps the safety valve provided by massive emigration explains why this failed to happen. Whatever the case, the bourgeoisie could not make the internal peasantry into its ally against the proletariat. It therefore turned to an alliance with the external peasantry, the American farmers. In the process it sacrificed the great English proprietors, although they were modern. Furthermore, it resorted to the pillage of India and brigandage in Ireland, with its deplorable ideological consequences.

The third road, the American road pointed out by Lenin, also involved rapid industrialization. Here, the small peasantry did not come out of an antifeudal revolution. I maintain that New England was a byproduct of English mercantilism and was characterized by exceptionally widespread simple commodity production within its social formation. The example of the United States, even more than that of England or France, shows that this mode contained the seed of rapid capitalist development, in accordance with Dobb’s thesis (50-3). It is true that other exceptional conditions favored this development, namely, the extent and wealth of the country, immigration, and the surplus from the internal slave colony.

The Prussian road does not necessarily slow subsequent industrialization. The means of accumulation extracted by the superexploitation of the peasants was large enough to accelerate industrialization, particularly as the unified German state made sure it was not absorbed in overly high ground rent. Here we can see clearly the manner in which the emerging new economy fit into the world circuit. Where the ruling class became an exporter of agricultural products, the country was led into a process of dependence and unequal exchange to the detriment of internal accumulation. But where the ruling class became an industrial exporter, financing industry from the agrarian surplus, the Prussian road was very effective. The first possibility occurred in Hungary and Rumania, for example; the second in Germany, Japan, and Italy. Russia was somewhere between the two.

Thus the speed of industrialization does not depend mainly on whether the bourgeois revolution takes a revolutionary or a reformist road. The class struggle and the alliances made by the bougeoisie after the bourgeois revolution are the prime determinants of this speed. Often a strong proletariat slows down accumulation. Inversely, accumulation may accelerate after a serious defeat of the proletariat. A good example is the economic growth of Germany after the Second World War. Defeated in 1933 to reemerge on the political scene only in 1945, the German proletariat had very difficult working conditions. In 1965 the wage bill in German industry was still only 55 percent of that in the United States and 74 percent of that in France. But the rapid growth that resulted from this in the period 1950 to 1970 allowed salaries to catch up. In 1974 the same percentages were 99 percent and 83 percent, that is, the relationship between Germany and France was reversed. * The accompanying surplus in the external balance accentuated this tendency by the overvaluation of the mark and the devaluation of the franc. This took place within a rightwing social-democratic political framework perfectly controlled by capital. Other outcomes are possible from a conjuncture of effective resistance on the part of the exploited: high salaries may lead to either stagnation or intensive technical progress. But this parallel is instructive in that it reveals how the French peasantry, strong in its alliance with the bourgeoisie, was responsible for the slow pace of accumulation.

17. Third thesis: in radical bourgeois revolutions, the radical peasant component goes beyond capitalist demands. It calls into question class society as such. Albert Soboul notes that the poor peasants in France did not want the division of communal lands which the rich ones were demanding (51-1). Thus communal lands were maintained in large regions and disappeared only slowly and gradually during the nineteenth century, as the rich peasants

‘‘These figures are derived from a recent study by the Ministry of Research and Industry, GRESI, La situation des Etats-Unis au debut de l’administration Carter, July 1977, p. 30.

acquired the means to take advantage of land improvement contracts with the municipalities under their control.

We can find poor peasants resisting the objective necessities of capitalist development elsewhere; in contemporary northern Portugal, for instance. Should we consider this resistance to be reactionary because it impedes capitalist development of the productive forces? This would reflect a bourgeois class viewpoint, for as we have seen, proletarian resistance also curbs capitalist growth. On the contrary we must stress the progressive character of this resistance, which anticipates the resistance of the class on whose back capitalist development of the productive forces takes place: the proletariat (10-5). Daniel Guerin’s insistence on the embryonic proletarian character of the struggles of “bras nus” and poor peasants has met with violent criticism, which seems to me to be social-democratic in inspiration. For the struggle of poor peasants is certainly a struggle against class society per se (50-3).

18. Fourth thesis: radical or not, peasant struggles in the transition to central capitalism, that is, before the imperialist era, have always ultimately served the interests of the bourgeoisie and not the peasantry. Depending on their modalities they favor one or the other section of the bourgeoisie: the kulak petty agrarian bourgeoisie formed in the differentiation of the peasantry; the great capitalist landed proprietors integrated into the market and using modern technology, i.e., the agrarian big bourgeoisie; or the industrial bourgeoisie itself. But the goal of the radical wing of the peasant movement—an egalitarian, communal peasant society without classes—was never realized.

This failure shows that while further development of the productive forces required a society with new relations of production, this would still be a class society, capitalist society. This is an expression of historical necessity.

Today, however, in the framework of the imperialist system, the same capitalist mode is no longer able to realize the full potential of the productive forces on the periphery of the system, due to the effects of the domination, superexploitation, and distorted development caused by capitalism. In light of this, radical peasant struggles can no longer be seen objectively as part of the bourgeois revolution but rather are part of the socialist revolution. The poor peasantry opposes class exploitation and this time has the ally which it lacked in France in 1793: a real proletariat.

Doubtless, the countries of the contemporary periphery are not all weak links in the imperialist system, nor are they the only weak links. Southern Europe is perhaps a weak link in the center of the contemporary system. If so, it is not for the reasons given above, which apply only to the periphery. The peasantry is disappearing in the center, and thus can no longer be the main reserve of revolution.

V. Summary of conclusions

19. The contrast between the European world economy that developed during the mercantilist transition and the expansion of previous tributary empires underlines the uniqueness of the transition to capitalism and thus forces us to rethink the fundamental questions of historical materialism.

Territorial expansion in other advanced societies never took this form. The centralized tributary Chinese state integrated newly colonized southern regions as ordinary provinces, subjected to the same system of tribute collection centralized by a prebendary bureaucracy. On the other hand, European expansion created for the first time a real periphery based on unequal specialization of production. While an empire is a political unit, the world European system is an economic one; that is, the links between its different parts are economic and not necessarily nor primarily political. This is not a chance coincidence. On the contrary, it reveals essential facts about the function of relations between the base and the superstructure in different modes of production.

I have developed the thesis that the tributary mode was the more general form of precapitalist class society; that slavery was exceptional and, like the simple commodity mode, marginal; that feudalism was a peripheral form of the tributary mode and that, precisely for this reason—because it arose earlier, it was still marked by the characteristics of original communal society—it could be transcended more easily. Thus Europe was endowed with its singular destiny.

The tributary mode defines at once relations of domination (class-governing state and governed peasants) and relations of exploitation (extortion of a surplus in the form of tribute). The transparence of the relations of exploitation implies the dominance of relations of domination, that is, of political ideology. Such a mode, in its complete form, is highly stable. It can bring about development of the productive forces without disrupting the relations of production (combination of relations of domination and exploitation). This is a reminder that the view of the mechanical determination of the relations of production by the level of development of the productive forces is not a Marxist one but a vulgar economist one.

The type of progress made in the productive forces is not immaterial and neutral but in fact is determined by the relations of production. Technology is not an autonomous prime mover springing from progress in human understanding in some lay version of God in Enlightenment philosophy, but is subject to the requirements of the relations of production. For instance, the complete tributary mode in Egypt and China was able to direct the development of the productive forces toward considerable technological advances in irrigation and construction (financed by agricultural progress) and in communications (roads, postal service, etc.), and thus to stengthen the tributary mode itself.

Slavery is not an autonomous mode of production. It is a political concept which defines a type of domination, just as personal dependence, serfdom, or bourgeois right are other personal statuses which constitute a framework of relations of domination. The existence of slavery does not necessarily imply a slave mode, which would mean a relation of exploitation of the slave. But this relation is exceptional and in general appears only where slaves produce a commodity for their masters. The slave mode is therefore associated with another dominant mode of production: either a communal mode (lineage), or a tributary mode (Classical antiquity), or a capitalist mode (the United States in the nineteenth century).

In principle, the tributary mode, like the communal mode, precludes commodity relations. These appear in the interstices of nonmarket societies as an associated, dominated mode or, more often, in the external relations of the communities or tributary empires (long-distance trade). And it is precisely in such exceptional circumstances, wherein commodity relations predominate at least sectorally, that the slave mode develops.

These conceptual clarifications increase our understanding of the nature of European feudal society, the reasons for the particular forms of its expansion, and the genesis of capitalism. If feudal Europe was not an empire, this is because the feudal mode was a peripheral form, an incomplete form, of the tributary mode. The dismemberment of state power and the noncentralization of the surplus originated in the distant past: in the nature of the takeover of the Roman Empire by barbarians who had scarcely left communal modes. The primitive forms of the tributary mode are thus more flexible than its complete forms. It was backward Europe that went through the capitalist transition from the tributary mode and not the advanced Orient. This expression of unequal development disproves the thesis of linear and continuous development of the productive forces and of their determination by successive modes of production.

F rom 1150 to 1300 territorial expansion of the feudal mode took place without difficulty, thanks to the abundance of virgin territory (we see a similar phenomena in Africa). Its contraction from 1300 to 1450 (demographic expansion met falling outputs of the current technological level) reduced feudal income and brought on a crisis. The lords’ attempts to find new lands led to the enormous expansion of Iberia into America and of Russia into Siberia. At the same time extremely violent forms of labor exploitation were introduced: once again slavery appeared (in America), contradicting the mechanistic thesis that it is a more backward mode of production than feudalism. Serfdom reappeared in Eastern Europe, always in conjunction with the birth of capitalism.

The attempts to establish a European empire nevertheless failed, always for the same basic reason: feudal resistance, heritage of the old freedoms of communities which were far less subjugated than in the more advanced forms of the tributary mode (China and Egypt). Again this contradicts the assumptions of the asiatic mode of production. The failure to establish such an empire led to a capitalist solution to the problem: the juxtaposition of central, national absolutist states, free cities, and autonomous provinces and the establishment of the periphery (America) of the European economic system as a prelude to the unequal capitalist development of modern times. .

Just as essential was the opposition between the center and the periphery of the system. Since the system is an economic one, it is in the economic realm that new divisions arise. The economy of the centers is autocentric; that of the peripheries is extraverted and constrained by the unequal division of labor to produce a lower order of merchandise at lower remuneration. The roots of unequal exchange go back to the first centuries of capitalism.

20. The nature of unequal development prior to the establishment of the capitalist system—notably in the transition to feudalism, in feudal expansion, in the mercantilist transition, and finally in the bourgeois revolution—is different from the kind of unequal development familiar to us in the imperialist era of capitalism. The universality of unequal development does not mean that we can derive a few simple laws according to which history eternally repeats itself. Center and periphery, complete and incomplete are concepts different in content and plane from one period to another.

Thus it is not possible to offer a general periodization for universal history prior to imperialism. The specific periodization of European history outlined above only highlights the different and unequal forms of capitalist development in Europe. In this history, the central pivot of the analysis is the class struggle among the three elements of the society—feudal lords, peasants, and bourgeois— and the interrelation of these struggles with the evolution of the state.

21. The national question developed gradually in the course of this unequal development out of the capitalist transition and the bourgeois revolution. During this process nations in the modern sense of the term appeared only in the centers that bourgeois revolutions had made complete: England and France. For the rest of Europe, the national question was not yet settled at the dawn of the nineteenth century. It was gradually settled during the particular process of unequal development, the subject of the next chapter.

Chapter 5

Unequal Development in the Capitalist Centers

The break represented by the emergence of central capitalist nations during the eighteenth century is so important that 1800 marks the decisive turning point of universal history, the birth date of universal history. Nevertheless, the gradual consolidation of the central zone of the world capitalist system (Europe, North America, Japan, Australia) and the definite division of this system into central and peripheral zones took an entire century. During this century the national question was gradually resolved in Europe, as the central capitalist formations under consideration emerged. A series of questions known as regional questions were still outstanding; this is related to the problem of unequal development.

I. The national question and the emergence of central capitalist formations

In 1848 revolution broke out in France and appeared likely to enflame all of Europe. The Communist Manifesto proclaimed the socialist revolution. However, except for the Paris Commune, during the following three-quarters of a century and until the Russian revolutions of 1905 and 1917, capitalism was not in jeopardy. Although violent struggles rocked and transformed Europe, they were all national struggles.

In 1848, then, there were only three nation-states constituting more or less complete capitalist formations: England, France, and the United States. These three more or less national states had emerged from the long history of the maturation of capitalism and of unequal development during the feudal and mercantilist periods. In France and England the class struggle involved three groups— the feudal lords, the bourgeoisie, and the peasantry—and even three and a half, insofar as in rare moments (Cromwell, 1793) the nascent proletariat sounded a discordant note. In the United States (at least in the northern states) a capitalist formation without feudal antecedents was born. After the Industrial Revolution, the compromises resulting from the series of bourgeois revolutions and the Restorations that followed them became stabilized and the bourgeois-proletarian struggle came to the forefront.

This class struggle was unequivocally on the national level. Bourgeois and proletarians belonged to the same nation, a selfsatisfied nation, formed gradually during the three preceding centuries. Certain unresolved national problems—most importantly, that of Ireland—surfaced later and had an effect on these class struggles. But they were minor in that they did not determine the basic form taken by the most important question, the social question, to use the contemporary expression. Witness English Chartism and the Paris Commune.

These three nations aside, what was Europe like at that time? There were small bourgeois nations—Holland, Denmark, Sweden —which had not yet entered the industrial era. There was Portugal, a nation blocked at the mercantilist stage. There was Spain, only partly a nation, where the same blockage had destroyed the historical possibility of amalgamating Castillians, Catalans, and Basques (be it by “iron and fire,” as in France the Languedoc had been Gallicized). But beyond the Rhine and the Alps was a conglomeration of principalities and empires that were neither national nor capitalist. Here the belated emergence of capitalism coincided with the emergence of nations instead of following it. Thus in this part of Europe class struggles (which constituted in the final analysis the motivation for all the battles that took place there) were bound up with national struggles. More precisely, class struggles to a large extent took the form of national struggles. Thus the twenty-five years following 1848 were primarily given over to German and Italian unification and the four decades after that to the break-up of the Russian, Austro-Hungarian, and Ottoman empires. Of course, German and Italian unification and the establishment of the Danubian and Balkan national states were bourgeois revolutions, but well-disguised ones.

There is a vast literature, notably by Marx and Engels themselves, devoted to these questions. It has been seriously analyzed and commented upon in studies which are neither Marxologistic nor pure and simply laudatory exegeses, and by Marxists from the regions in question: Karl Kautsky, Rosa Luxemburg, Otto Bauer and all the Austro-Marxists (Karl Renner, Josef Strasser, Otto Strasser), Anton Pannekoek, Lenin, Trotsky, Stalin, and so on (60). These analyses are all well presented and developed. I would simply like to draw the reader’s attention to several points.

1. European history during the decades 1850-1914 was in fact primarily the history of national struggles. This was so much the case that Marx and Engels not only wrote extensively on these questions but also found it necessary for the proletarian movement to take a position about them. They were correct on the principle, although certain of their positions are debatable.

Marx and Engels considered classes to be more important than nations. Thus they adopted a pragmatic attitude toward national struggles and subordinated self-determination to the exigencies of what they saw as the longer term interest of the proletariat. Confronted with the absence of clear class struggles and the violence of national struggles, they sometimes substituted nations for classes, “investing nations with the role of classes” (60-1). They spoke of progressive and reactionary nations. It is true, as we will see, that the nations in question were progressive because of their possible contribution to the bourgeois revolution, while the reactionary nations were feudal. In this discussion there were no proletarian nations.

For the moment, let me make the following remarks without commentary. Marx and Engels did not discuss the division of the world into imperialist nations and nations dominated by imperialism, a division that appeared only later. But if today we were to use the language of Marx and Engels and to state that England, France, Germany, or the United States were reactionary while putting the Egyptian, Arab, Cuban, or Vietnamese nations in the revolutionary role, many objections would be raised.

2. Marx and Engels based their classification on the famous distinction between “nations without history” and “historical nations. ” The latter are those which were able to establish a state, that is, which had their own ruling classes. They were nations of the nobility (Russians, Poles, Hungarians) or the bourgeoisie (French, English, Germans, Italians). The former included those that did not succeed in establishing a state, and were thus dominated by exploiting and foreign classes (feudal). These were peasant nations (Czechs dominated by feudal elements and the German bourgeois, Croats by Hungarian feudal elements, the Balkan peoples by Ottoman feudal elements, etc.). At times there are certain simplifications, not to say errors, in this area: there was a Croatian feudal class in Croatia, for instance. But this is unimportant. At times there was a nascent local bourgeoisie (Czech, Greek) but it was very weak. Nations “without history” are thus peasant nations to the extent that they really correspond to the classificatory criteria of Marx and Engels.

Marx and Engels had no sympathy for these peasant nations, which they judged incapable of making a bourgeois and a fortiori a proletarian revolution. Due to this the worst feudal reaction was able to manipulate them. The example which haunted Marx was the behavior of the armies (in large measure Czech and Croatian) that massacred the 1848 revolutionaries in Austria. This convinced Marx and Engels that the Slavic peasants of the Danube and the Balkans were subject to tsarist manipulation by means of Pan-Slavism used in the most reactionary way against the German people, potentially more advanced as they were divided into bourgeois and proletarians.

Today we can easily recognize their error in judgment. Marx certainly foresaw the development by stages from the bourgeois to the socialist revolution in Germany (and later in Spain). He had the brilliant insight of unequal development, an insight which Lenin was able to clarify. But he did not envisage the development by stages from a peasant to a socialist revolution—although it was a peasant rather than a bourgeois revolution that broke out in Russia. And yet elsewhere, in France, Marx understood very well that the bourgeois revolution was radical only to the extent that its peasant component was strong.

Insofar as the bourgeois revolutions of 1848 had no strong peasant component, they could not become radicalized, for the bourgeoisie already feared the proletariat and made sure to suppress the peasant component. Marx should have asked if the failure of the Czechs and Croats to support the Germano-Austrian revolution was due to their feeling that this revolution had nothing to offer peasants like themselves. But he did not ask this question.

I see two reasons for this. The first is circumstantial and lies in Marx’s veritable phobia about Russia. This clouded his mind to such an extent that certain of contemporary China’s foreign policy judgments seem subtle by comparison with Marx’s errors about Russian diplomacy. Marx thought Palmerston was a Russian agent and accused England of playing St. Petersburg’s game in the Ottoman Orient. He went so far as to support the Ottoman yoke against states made independent by the Russians. He was in error about the Pan-Slavic Congress of Prague (on which point Bakhunin was correct; cf. 8lb-5), endowing the anti-Russian Poles with revolutionary virtues which they did not possess and which he would not grant to the Czechs.

The second reason is less circumstantial and thus more serious. Despite his remarkable analysis of the peasant and bourgeois components of the French revolution (the distinction between the revolutionary and the nonrevolutionary roads of capitalist development), Marx believed that the peasant revolution could occur only under the leadership of the bourgeoisie. He did not see that when this is impossible (and this he does say), the revolution must take place under the leadership of the proletariat, even where the latter is embryonic. Nonetheless, we must excuse Marx on this point: in his time the proletariat was less than embryonic in peasant societies (except in Bohemia). Fifty years later Lenin did not hesitate to take issue with Marx about this vital problem.

Under these circumstances Marx preferred the bourgeoisie to the peasants and thus came up with some strange options. He made a sort of eulogy of the “civilizing mission” of the bourgeoisie: the German bourgeoisie in the East (Engels struck an almost pan-Germanist note) and the English in India. Marx celebrated the annexation of Texas by the “civilized” Americans from the Mexican “savages”; in reality the abolition of slavery there in 1823 created problems for the American southerners. He held onto certain illusions, countered adroitly by Bakhunin, about the advantages of a centralized state—but he changed his mind fifty times on this problem, as seen in his eulogy of the Paris Commune. Marx had a firm conviction that there was nothing to hope for from the Russian (peasant) people who, even if they set off a revolt, would not be able to carry it further except with the support of a revolution in the West. Trotsky inherited this error in judgment.

Two erroneous conclusions, proven false by history, derived from Marx’s and Engels’ judgments on these questions. First, Marx and Engels did not foresee that these same peasant nations would be much more revolutionary in the socialist transition than many others: thus the Yugoslavs, Greeks, Albanians, and Czechs, in contrast to the Hungarians and Poles. The contradiction they did not perceive is that in the historical nations where national feudalism and then the bourgeoisie were strong, the peasantry had much more difficulty in aligning with the proletariat than in the nations without history, where these exploiting classes were weak because they were foreign.

Secondly, Marx and Engels believed that nations without history were going to be gradually assimilated into the superior culture of their conquerors. The same thing would happen to them as happened to other ethnic groups (Bretons, Scots) that were assimilated and absorbed by the French and English nations and were no more than ethnographic fragments devoid of political importance. The question of regionalism in the developed centers is taken up below. But Marx and Engels underestimated the time it took for these assimilations to occur (they are still only partially complete) in the history of the most advanced mercantilist centers. And the pace of capitalist development among the peoples of eastern and southeastern Europe was going to be far more rapid than that of any possible assimilation.

I discovered in the work of Alexander Koyre (80d-4) that the expressions “historical nations” and “nations without history” were first used in 1837 by the Russian writer Polevoi, who attempted thereby to offer a justification in the Slavophile spirit for the destiny of Russia. Whatever the case, subsequent developments, contrary to Marx’s predictions, once again demonstrated the universality of unequal development. For these peasant nations, backward in the bourgeois phase of their development, appeared more advanced in the subsequent struggle against capitalism when it was forced upon them and eventually entered the socialist transition under more favorable conditions.

3. However, Marx understood the Irish question perfectly. At first he encouraged the Irish to renounce nationalism and to join the English proletarian movement, Chartism. Later he did not hesitate to take up the cause of oppressed Ireland unconditionally, and to affirm that, so long as the English proletariat did not rid itself of chauvinism, nothing could be expected of it. This position is all the more remarkable in that the Irish were not oppressed by a barbaric Tsar but by liberal England.

This judgment largely redeems the errors Marx made about eastern and southeastern Europe. For in England Marx was an activist whose position directly affected the movement. And he understood the problem and the correct attitude from the first. He did not feel involved in the struggles of eastern and southeastern Europe, where the workers’ movement was moreover as yet nonexistent. He observed this from outside, as a journalist, on the basis of secondhand information derived for the most part from reactionary sources.

4. These discussions continued after the death of Marx and Engels and took a new turn in eastern and southeastern Europe due to the emergence of socialist parties (60). Four observations should be made about these discussions.

First, the great majority of socialists in this region were preoccupied by the danger of the great states breaking into qualified and nonviable micronations. To avoid this break-up, Otto Bauer and Karl Renner invented the strategy of “personal and cultural autonomy.” It seemed to them important to safeguard for socialist society, which would soon come into being, an adequate framework for the productive forces. In this period, Rosa Luxemburg observed, the framework suitable to the needs of these productive forces was no longer the nation-state but the conquering, imperialist state. The same logic led Otto Strasser to demand freedom of emigration for workers.

Second, a great many socialists of the region continued to think that the process of assimilating peoples of diverse races would quickly diminish the importance of nationalities. Kautsky believed that the Czech language, which had become a peasant language, would disappear along with the growth of urbanization, as workers and bourgeois alike adopted German. Moreover, he looked forward to this in the name of the universalization of culture, the progressive work begun by the bourgeoisie and completed by the proletariat. On this base, Otto Strasser thought that the national question had no importance for manual workers; it was only important for those sectors of the petty-bourgeoisie that “made a living through language” (teachers, lawyers, etc.). For them, language was a means of production, while for the worker it was only an accessory, the means of production being the tool.

Third, on this same basis, Rosa Luxemburg questioned Marx’s positions with regard to Poland. She who defended the Balkan peoples against oppression by the backward Turk saw no need to defend Polish independence against the Germans or even the Russians. In her mind, the Polish movement was far from being the only serious revolutionary manifestation in Russia: the Russian autocracy would be overthrown by a revolution in Russia itself.

Fourth, and a bit at countercurrents, there is the Leninist position, grounded in the basic distinction between oppressing and oppressed nations, a distinction that is sometimes forgotten. For this reason, Lenin did not adopt Rosa Luxemburg’s position with regard to Poland, although he knew that the Russian revolutionary movement was far from negligible.

5. The definition of the concept of nation emerged gradually during nineteenth-century European history. Marx was not particularly interested in it. On the other hand, the Austro-Marxists were led to ask the question in the following way: When bourgeois and proletarians speak the same language, do they have the same culture, a common culture which in fact defines the nation? Some (Otto Strasser, for instance) thought not, claiming that the life experiences of the exploited and the exploiters were too different to constitute a common culture and almost a nation. These people played down the importance of the national reality. Others (Pannekoek, for instance) believed to the contrary that the national reality was undeniable because the classes of a single nation shared a common experience, be it only that of struggle.

Without taking the analysis very far, Kautsky suggested that the concept of nation appeared only with capitalism. For him, to speak of a peasant nation would be a contradiction in terms. It would fall to Stalin to make explicit what was only implicit here: the unifying element of the markets in capital, commodities, and labor power. As I have said, the simultaneous emergence of nations and of capitalism is unique to European history (although perhaps an analogous problem exists in the contemporary third world) where capitalism overcame feudal fragmentation. But this does not necessarily occur.

II. Questions of “regionalism” in the advanced centers

Development has always been unequal in all class societies. Due to the character of the alliances-compromises made in the course of its evolution, the bourgeois revolution itself engendered subsequent inequalities in the development of capitalism. These inequalities developed on several planes simultaneously. Internally (within a national or multinational state) they took the form of regional inequalities, which sometimes coincided with national conflicts. Internationally they took the form of unequal paces in the accumulation of capital from one country to the other within the group of central capitalist formation on a world scale. Beginning at the end of the nineteenth century, the division of the planet into dominant imperialist formations and dominated, incomplete colonial or semicolonial capitalist formations assumed its definitive, contemporary shape.

The absolutely general character of unequal development can lead to confusion. If the analysis is too vague, if it equates all manifestations of unequal development regardless of context (inequality between center and periphery, or between centers, or within a center) and reasons by analogy, it will miss the particular features of each case. These are on the level of the structure of the class blocs particular to each situation: alliances within blocs, classes assuming the leadership of blocs, the extent of the opposition of blocs, the determination of subordinate classes, the interrelation with foreign class alliances and oppositions in a system of formation. This structure is not fixed; it evolves under the impact of its internal and external contradictions.

Thus in each case we must (1) analyze the historical establishment of the blocs that created the situation, starting with relevant class struggles; (2) analyze the direction which this structure would take on its own, that is, if the initiative were left to its ruling classes, whose relations would be modified as accumulation took place; and (3) define (this is the goal of the exercise) the strategy used by the exploited classes to make the structure evolve differently, to make it break apart, to put in its place an effective bloc of exploited classes which would bring about the end of exploitation.

This is the direction of the foregoing analyses of the unequal formation of capitalist centers on the one hand and of the unequal formation within the world system on the other (theory of the center and the periphery and of the class alliances and conflicts on the world scale during the imperialist epoch). The history of unequal development thus did not end with the bourgeois revolution. It continued during the Industrial Revolution of the nineteenth century, finally assuming its contemporary, complete shape during the imperialist period. The contrast between dominant imperialist centers and underdeveloped, dominated peripheries thus became the predominant form of unequal development. The door to the establishment of new capitalist centers is henceforth closed, while the era of the stages of the socialist revolution is opened.

What follows will not deal with this determining form of the division of the imperialist system but with the emergence of unequal development within the central social formations during pre-monopoly capitalist industrialization.

The Italian case

The Italian case is exemplary for two reasons. First because it is particularly clear. Second because much more than others it generated discussion on a high scientific level. The figure of Antonio Gramsci dominates this discussion. But it should be pointed out that Gramsci’s great thesis has been called into question or significantly added to by such authors as E. Sereni, Rosario Romeo, Sergio Romano, Benedetto Croce, Nicola Zitara, Cape-celatro, and Antonio Carlo (61).

1. First thesis: having been blocked during an earlier period, Italy was globally threatened with peripheralization at the beginning of the nineteenth century (it lost its advance over the rest of Europe from the thirteenth and fourteenth centuries and became even more backward during the entire mercantilist period). Italy escaped this fate through the initiative of the northern agrarian and particularly the Piedmontese bourgeoisie.

The Risorgimento and unification, up to the establishment of the protectionist tariff of 1887, were the work of this northern agrarian bourgeoisie. It is not adequate to characterize this unification, as is often done, as a compromise that sealed the class alliance between the northern bourgeoisie and the feudal elements of the south, excluding the peasant element (of the south especially) from the bourgeois revolution. It must be added that what I call the northern bourgeoisie was at the time of Cavour still primarily an agrarian bourgeoisie. It had been produced by a twofold process: internal transformation of the old feudalists into capitalist gentlemen farmers and differentiation-kulakization within the peasantry, partially freed by the French revolution. The bourgeoisie of the time was not yet industrial. And even its merchant function had been undermined by the long decline of Genoa and Venice and the integration of the latter into the Austrian feudal system.

The agrarian bourgeoisie feared that the radicalism of an antifeudal peasant movement would challenge its own well-established power in the Piedmont. This is why it preferred the more tractable alliance with the southern feudal elements. It favored free trade also—not only because freedom of trade allowed it to emerge as a bourgeoisie by destroying feudal relations or forcing them to modernize, but also and especially because it envisaged its integration into the (young capitalist) European system as an agrarian bourgeoisie. Had it persisted on this path, the whole of Italy would have been peripheralized just as Hungary was.

It is interesting to compare Italian with Prussian and Russian history. In the latter countries also the latifundiary agrarian bourgeoisie predominated. In Prussia, to the east of the Elbe, they were called Junkers and monopolized state power. But the annexation of the Rhineland by Prussia, while it did not modify the class content of the state, gave it a nascent industrial economic base. This contributed to putting the German Bismarckian state on the road to accelerated and autonomous industrialization. In Russia, although state power was also completely aristocratic (latifundiaries in the process of integration into the capitalist system, especially after 1861), the state promoted and strengthened industry. From this resulted the mixed character of subsequent Russian evolution— neither totally peripheralized (as a wheat exporter) nor openly evolving toward autocentric industrial predominance.

In contrast, what we can call the agrarian bourgeoisie of the Balkans and the Ottoman Empire was integrated into the world system as a peripheralized, exploiting class. The most typical example is probably Egyptian large proprietors, who themselves shifted to cotton production for England after the failure of autocentric industrialization by Mohammed Ali under the Ismaili Khedivate during the War of Secession (77c-1). The Greek and Turkish agrarian bourgeoisies acted similarly, especially with regard to tobacco (76b-7). The combination of great latifundiary capitalist property (or, in Greece, small capitalist property) with a commercial and financial bourgeoisie which became a comprador bourgeoisie typifies the evolutionary course that Italy might have taken.

2.    Second thesis: the autocentric industrialization of Italy was initiated by the Italian state and financed by a levy on ground rent in the north and especially in the south of the country. Four questions arise here: (a) Did the protectionist tariff of 1887, maintained until Italy joined Europe and its common market beginning in 1950-1958, promote or impede this evolution? (b) Was the surplus extracted from the south responsible for the new and growing unequal development between north and south? (c) Was this form of industrialization more or less rapid than other possible forms based on a peasant revolution might have been? (d) Has contemporary European integration modified these perspectives?

3.    Italian historians are unanimous in their agreement that the industrialization of Italy was initiated by systematic state support, which brought about the formation of finance capital. State responsibility for the rapid construction of rail and road networks, the creation of a monetary system and a credit network, and the formation of an important merchant marine supported by the state meant that Italian capitalism had, from the beginning, a relatively more concentrated structure. Somewhat like Russia, Italy entered the monopoly stage without really having gone through the prior stage. The intensification of this characteristic following the 1930 crisis, with the creation of the Institute for Italian Reconstruction and its affiliates to rescue Italian industries, gave a strong state bias to contemporary Italian capitalism.

Protectionism was an essential means, a condition for the process of industrialization, which would not on its own have been able to prevail over competition from more advanced countries within its own national market. The liberal rhetoric of contemporary ideologues of imperialism, who claim that protectionism slowed down development because it imposed costs and distortion unfavorable to optimalization, totally lacks historical perspective (71a-l 1).

4. Was Italian industry financed by the surplus extracted from the south? Gramsci’s analysis does not preclude this possibility, despite certain over-hasty deductions. Gramsci merely noted that the northern (agrarian, then industrial) bourgeoisie achieved unification without calling on the southern peasants but by concluding an alliance with feudal-style landed proprietors. The question of whether these proprietors were feudal or not has been raised only recently, so far as I know. But this was not Gramsci’s basic question. His thesis was only that an agrarian revolution in the south would have (1) accelerated capitalist development and (2) made development less unequal between the north and the south. While the second point is certainly valid, I have some hesitation in agreeing on the first.

Contemporary historians of Italy’s south have undertaken to demonstrate that industrialization was largely financed by a surplus extracted from it, thanks to the state which the northern bourgeoisie monopolized through the unification of the fiscal and public finance systems. To prove this, Nicola Zitara and Capecelatro and Carlo have compared the fiscal burden on the north and south, respectively, and the distribution of public finances. They have

also studied the effects of the liquidation of the Banco di Napoli in favor of a centralized credit system (61-5, 61-6).

The question of protectionism is related to that of the surplus. Is Sereni spelling out what was implicit in Gramsci when he claims that protectionism represented the convergence of northern industrial and southern agrarian interests because it allowed the rate of ground rent to rise (61-2)? This is very debatable, because the agrarian interests protected in this case were northern rather than southern. Zitara, Capecelatro, and Carlo have in fact shown that unification destroyed southern self-sufficient cereal agriculture, which could not compete with the modern cereal and animal agriculture of the north. This led to southern specialization in agricultural exports (wine and oil).

Can we speak of true conquest and colonization of the south by the north, as do the Italian Meridionalists? Colonization during the contemporary imperialist epoch fulfills a precise function: to promote the acceleration of accumulation in the dominant centers by the extraction of a considerable volume of surplus labor through the maintenance and reproduction of forms of exploitation that were originally precapitalist but have been subjugated. The resulting extraverted distortion of dependent development conditions the reproduction of this superexploitation. I accept this analysis, which is not incompatible with Gramsci’s thesis. But it extends his analysis in a way which he himself could not do, given his ignorance of the problematic of formal domination through which the surplus labor of precapitalist modes is transformed into surplus value and profit for dominant capital. In this sense, southern Italy played exactly this role; the thesis of the Meridionalists seems correct.

Moreover, the Italian case is not unique of its type. Did not New England have an analogous internal colony, the slave South, which specialized in the export of cotton thanks to the superexploitation of the slaves’ work?

5. Returning to Gramsci, can we claim that an agrarian revolution in the south of Italy would have accelerated the development

of national capitalism? Rosario Romeo thinks not (61-3). His thesis, which is also Hobsbawm’s, is that the survival of feudal relations enabled pressure to be maintained on the peasants' income (60-8). The surplus product, extracted by means of rent, was used for rapid accumulation via fiscal measures. An agrarian revolution would have destroyed this model of accelerated accumulation.

I have already stated that the agrarian revolution can boost capitalist development because differentiation within a peasantry subjected to market exchanges can occur very rapidly. If industrialization was curbed in France, this was for a different reason: the antiworker bourgeois-peasant alliance.

Let us give Gramsci his due. He was not interested in the pace of capitalist growth (which is a bourgeois preoccupation) but in the style of its development as it affected the anticapitalist struggle. On this level he was completely correct: the road taken by Italian unification brought about unequal development between the north and the south, while an agrarian revolution would have created the conditions for a different, homogeneous, and thus truly unifying development. Gramsci noted that unequal development impeded the anticapitalist struggle because it kept the rural masses of the south outside the proletarian battle. How can we contradict him when we know the support given to fascism in southern Italy?

Today, the Meridionalists are only carrying the same line of reasoning a bit further. Why do the southern masses support the Right? Is it not because what the northern-based Left has to offer them does not match their aspirations? The Meridionalists are not unfaithful to Gramsci when they treat north-south relations in terms of the center-colony problematic; nor when they recall the nature of the social-democratic alliance and the complicity of the I northern proletariat, which supports its bourgeoisie in the superexploitation of the southern “external proletariat,” a proletariat of small producers subjected to the formal domination of capital. But they make certain people uncomfortable.

6. This is ancient history, however. The immaturity of the northern social-democratic (and/or anarcho-syndicalist due to its

weakness, some would say!) proletariat, its defeat in 1920-1922 have been transcended since 1945. Furthermore, Italy’s decision to join the European Common Market, a decision which is now irreversible, put an end to the old protectionist measures. Finally, the massive emigation from the south to the northern factories, the establishment of industry in the south, undertaken on a large scale with the rapid modernization of the last quarter century, have completely changed the givens of the situation. The old Risorgimentist alliance no longer has any meaning and the conditions for panItalian proletarian unity have been created.

I am reluctant to be so optimistic. Is Zitara wrong in pointing to the bourgeois character of the working-class position, an apologia for the development of the productive forces (which are capitalist in this case)? In the past, he reminds us, the working class did nothing (except verbally) to support an agrarian revolution in the south. Some have suggested that they feared this would diminish the productive forces. Today the working class sees in the establishment of industry in the south the means for the creation of a southern working class. Zitara sees in it the appropriation of southern space by big capital, under conditions analogous to those of the imperialist export of capital. I might add that the European discourse remains disquieting. For once again, in the name of the development of the productive forces, which is the bourgeoisie’s concern, what will not be accepted? And how will escape from the claws of “Germano-American” Europe be possible if we support this discourse?

7. Third thesis: southern Italy was no more backward in 1860 than northern Italy. Colonization was entirely responsible for its backwardness. It would be necessary to make a thorough study of Italian history before judging this thesis of Capecelatro and Carlo. But the ravages of West-centered historiography elsewhere give reason to take their arguments seriously.

These authors claim that Sicilian agriculture ceased to be feudal in the second half of the eighteenth century. Under the impact of the influx of American silver via Spain, the great proprietors modernized and became large-scale producers of wheat for the market. Rent was paid in money. Advanced rural proletarianization had led to urbanization and to the establishment of manufacturing, as the exports from Palermo indicate. As the abolition of feudalism by Murat at Palermo conformed to internal forces, the Bourbons, on their return, were unable to reinstate it. Southern Italy was nonetheless integrated into the world system as a periphery in England’s wake. English imports had killed the silk industry but encouraged wheat export. Moreover, the same was true at this time for the north, where the bourgeoisie was still exclusively agricultural. This was the meaning of the 1820-1821 revolution, followed by the Bourbon method of initiating industrial expansion, i.e., protectionism and appeal to foreign capital. The collapse of the Bourbons was due to the attitude of the free-trade agrarian bourgeoisie, which abandoned its king to support the King of Savoy. Thus it was southern reactionary forces that welcomed unification.

If these theses are correct, do they contradict those of Gramsci? I believe not. In fact, Gramsci in no way confused capitalism and industry nor believed that the northern bourgeoisie was already industrial when it brought about unification. But it was destined to become so. Of course, Gramsci underestimated the contribution which the superexploitation of the south made to industrial accumulation because he was unaware of the problematic of formal domination. But this development extends Gramsci’s analysis rather than contradicting it.

In any event, whether or not southern Italy was as advanced as northern Italy in 1860, the devastating effects of unification are hardly debatable. China or Congo, the consequences of imperialism are everywhere the same.

8. The unequal development of capitalist Italy is related in certain respects to the more general problem of the unequal development of centers and peripheries during the imperialist period. I would not draw this conclusion for all forms of unequal development within centers. First it would be necessary to examine in more detail examples such as French regionalism (Brittany,

Languedoc), Ireland, and the South of the United States, where we should ask whether blacks constitute a nation or not.

The case of Brittany

9. The history of Brittany is an interesting case of unequal development within an advanced formation that became a nation through a long process of transition from feudalism to the absolutist-mercantilist tributary form. This transition was capped by a radical bourgeois revolution, which cleared the way for accelerated accumulation after the Industrial Revolution. If the French nation at the head of the Federation in 1790 was not yet a totally complete reality, its establishment was already well advanced. The Languedoc, the Basque country, Brittany, and even Corsica and Alsace-Lorraine had been undergoing Gallicization, in some instances for a very long time. That the peasants kept their original languages for another century until the primary school of the Third Republic imposed French on them; that Alsace-Lorraine had its process of Gallicization interrupted by its integration into Germany in 1871-1918; that in lower Brittany and in Corsica, Breton and Corsican had not yet disappeared—these facts only indicate that even in the advanced capitalist centers assimilation is less rapid than certain Austro-Marxists thought it would be. The bourgeois classes and the urban world were already Gallicized in 1790.

The dominant bloc that established itself on the national level during the revolution and the compromises that ensued are not abstractions. This bloc was reproduced concretely at different levels, both regional and local, of the national reality and took on different colorations according to its local functions.

It is thus useful to analyze how it functioned in Brittany, as Yannick Guin does (62-1). The general lines of his analysis of the class struggles and of their interrelation with class struggles on the scale of France as a whole are convincing. According to Guin, in 1789 Breton feudalism was of the poor type: relative fragmentation of the small rural aristocracy, large zones of small property. The church, which here held no significant amount of land, provided the organic intellectuals of this feudal formation in the form of country curates. The Girondist commercial and maritime bourgeoisie was oriented toward the sea (in connection with mercantilism and Antilles slavery); it moved into the countryside less than elsewhere in France.

Under these circumstances the bourgeoisie, which in France as a whole succeeded in joining with the peasants against feudalism, was stopped in Brittany by the combination of peasant revolt and aristocratic counterrevolution. The restoration that followed 1793 brought about a compromise: the rural bloc (aristocracy and peasants) was allowed to remain hegemonic in Brittany provided that it accept the hegemony of the big bourgeoisie over France as a whole.

For a century such an alliance operated in this way. Within Brittany the rural bloc (the whites) was dominant, isolating the urban bloc composed of blues (the local bourgeoisie) and of reds (the small local bourgeoisie). The hegemony of the industrial bourgeoisie over France as a whole both helped and hindered rural aristocratic proprietors in modernizing (producing for the market, buying equipment, etc.). The latter were able to do so without losing their leadership of the countryside, leadership which functioned on the ideological plane through the Concordat and through paternalistic formulae (e.g., Christian Democracy).

The capitalist development resulting from this compromise accelerated beginning in 1914 and especially in 1945, and finally broke up the alliances on which it had been based. Industry and the appearance of a working-class proletariat gradually undermined the traditional dependence of the descendants of the reds on the blues. On their side the blues, faced with the threat of socialism, made peace with the whites (by abandoning anticlericalism). In the countryside the process of modernization accelerated the disintegration of the rural world (massive emigration) and substituted for the old peasantry, which was relatively closed (self-subsistence polyculture) small, modernized, and specialized proprietors strongly dominated by agroindustrial capital (formal domination). The great capitalist proprietors had lost their political importance as a means of controlling the peasants. Electoral power shifted to the urban zones. A white-blue alliance replaced the blue-red one. Industrial capital intervened directly in the peasant economy without the mediation of the aristocrats. Out of this disintegration of the old alliances emerged the autonomous movement of the small peasantry subject to formal domination.

Breton ideology, which served in the nineteenth century to unify the rural bloc (wherein the aristocrats presented themselves, in a verbal defense of regionalism, as the defenders of the rural world against the misery of industrial capitalism), changed its content. It became the ideological expression of the peasant revolt, with the ambiguities that this revolt of small producers necessarily comported. Due to this, it met with a favorable response in the petty bourgeoisie (students) that wavered between capital and labor. The regionalization it proposed matched the strategy desired by the big bourgeoisie.

10. Although I believe that Yannick Guin’s analysis of class struggles and of the interrelation with national struggles is correct, I am not always convinced by his conclusions. Did not the counterrevolutionary resistance of the Chouans (the failure of the bourgeoisie to separate the peasants from the aristocracy) result from the concern of the ruling elements of the bourgeoisie (before Ther-midor and particularly afterward) not to foster a radical peasant revolution, the seed of which existed? In this case, is it not onesided to characterize the Chouannerie as counterrevolutionary? Is there no analogy between Czechs and Croats, who expected nothing from the timid bourgeois revolution of 1848, and the peasants of northern Portugal who expected nothing more from the socialists and communists in the Lisbon government?

Finally, so be it: the French revolution was not to be remade. We can only note the absence of an embryonic proletariat, an absence which resulted from the objective immaturity of capitalist relations at the time. This proletariat, despite its courage, was crushed by the bourgeoisie and did not succeed in allying with the poor Breton peasants.

And so? Why is it that from 1914 to the present the reds have not succeeded in allying with the peasants and cutting them off from the embourgeoisified aristocracy? Should this not have been the strategy of the workers’ movement? Why did the latter leave the initiative to the bourgeoisie, and find itself in no better position when the blues abandoned it to re-ally with the whites?

And when the peasants, abandoned in their turn by the whites, brought into capitalism and subjected to its formal domination, began to revolt, was it not the task of the workers’ movement to ally with them because theirs was a struggle against capital? Is it correct to consider this struggle lost in advance because it contravenes the “development of the productive forces”? Does not the struggle of the working class itself, by reducing profits, also prevent maximum accumulation? Is the role of the exploited to make it easier, by their silence, for the exploiters to bring about the development of the productive forces?

Should we not also take a different position with regard to the support of the petty bourgeoisie for this peasant revolt? Which petty bourgeoisie are we talking about? Small producers (artisans, shopkeepers) threatened by capital, or the new petty bourgeoisie composed of nonmanual workers and proletarianized employees already exploited by capital? In the latter case would not an alliance with the peasants, equally exploited by capital, be correct? And why would the working class hesitate to join it?

Should priority be given to the development of the productive forces or to the class struggle? Is the task of the proletariat to do nothing which objectively impedes the development of the productive forces? Is this not a social-democratic way of understanding this task? Should not the proletariat reject this goal, which is that of the exploiting classes, to concentrate exclusively on fostering the contradictions of this development in order to build an effective revolutionary bloc?

Is it not onesided to consider the demand for regionalization as the new strategy of the big bourgeoisie? Like many others, is this demand not ambivalent? Of course it can be coopted by the bourgeoisie, at least if it is part of an overall social-democratic strategy. But could it not also serve as a lever of anticapitalist mobilization?

Even if it served the agrarian bloc in the past, can Breton ideology be unilaterally characterized as reactionary, given the anticapitalist struggles that have attended its rebirth? Why? Because it goes against the development of the productive forces and the steamroller of cultural homogenization, which is only the generalization of the bourgeois ideology of homo consumens universalis? Are we talking about reviving a corpse or a dying entity (the Breton language)? Or are we talking about a protest against bourgeois ideology hiding behind the smokescreen of universality?

The Irish case

11. The case of Ireland resulted from a process engendered by the same family of historical conditions as that of Brittany. However, Ireland’s fate was very different (62-3). Invoking the religious factor as an explanation is unconvincing: in Germany, Catholics and Protestants are not killing each other. In fact, if the outcome of the Irish problem has been different from that of the Breton problem this occurred independently of a different relation of power. During a long period Ireland was as populated as England— because in England the bourgeoisie made a compromise with the feudal aristocracy, one which was much more favorable to the latter than in France. The English bourgeoisie never considered siding with the Irish rebellion against the English proprietors. Perhaps it was even the power that the English aristocracy gained from its domination over Ireland which forced the English bourgeoisie to conclude the compromise begun in 1688.

Following this, the bourgeoisie passed to the English proletariat its contempt, to put it mildly, for the fate of the exploited Irish peasants. This total lack of solidarity corrupted the English workers’ movement very early on, as Marx observed, and prepared it to accept the imperialist ideology, so aptly formulated by Cecil Rhodes, about the export of the social question.

The case of Catalonia and the Basque country

12.    This case is interesting because it inverts the terms of the current problem of unequal development. Here the oppressed nationalities are those of the regions where capitalist development is furthest advanced (62-4, 62-5).

We cannot understand a phenomenon of this type if we disregard the formation of unequal development in Spain during the feudal and mercantilist periods. No one knows how the Spanish nation would have evolved if the development of the peninsula had not been blocked at this stage, the country being corrupted by the wealth too easily taken from America. Thus Spain played the role of an intermediary rentier, collecting its tithe between America and northwestern Europe until it lost its position and thus became useless. If internal accumulation had taken place, a Spanish nation would doubtless have resulted. We cannot know if this would have happened by the Castellanization of Catalonia, the Catalani-zation of Castille, or a synthesis of the two. At any rate, the Languedoc was Gallicized, and Spain would have been able to evolve toward the formation of a capitalist nation, complete both on the economic level and on that of linguistic homogenization.

Spain stagnated at this stage for two or three centuries during which the central power constantly oppressed the Catalan and Basque minorities. When beginning in the 1950s, sudden industrial growth led to Spain’s overcoming its backwardness, it was again confronted with the national problem. But in the meantime this had become the problem of an advanced, multinational center.

The case of advanced multinational centers:

Belgium, Switzerland, Canada

13.    Which is more important, the nation (the question of the relations between different peoples of one country) or the state as

the framework within which the regulation of capital accumulation occurs? In fact, the establishment of class blocs occurs within the framework of the state, because state policy—both internal (credit, conjuncture, control of the workforce, national economic policy) and external (place in the international division of labor and methods of external economic policy)—brings this establishment about. This state may be national or multinational.

It is not impossible for a multinational bourgeois state to function. The Swiss confederation functions well despite real national conflicts which the federal system contains within the cantonal framework. It is true that Switzerland is an exception due to its position in the world system and that it has created this chef d’oeuvre of bourgeois policy, cantonalizing politics while at the same time having an integrated economic policy for the confederation. In fact, Switzerland, like the United States, proves that regionalization can be a means of lowering the level of political consciousness.

It is true that in a multinational state the balance is rarely equal among the constituent nations. The Walloon bourgeoisie dominated Belgium for a long time and oppressed the Flemish (peasants). Recently, the process of accumulation has led to the preferential development of industry in Flanders and the new Flemish working class has become significant. It is this new working class, which is social-democratic (in its more backward political forms, particularly Christian-Democratic ones) that has raised the language question.

The same can be said about Canada, whose exclusively English bourgeoisie has ruled over the peasant, conquered people of Quebec. The emergence of the demand for Quebec nationality stems from the industrialization of the province. This demand takes particular forms because it is confronted by the domination of the United States, which encountered no such resistance in English Canada, where it brought the local bourgeoisie under its sway like any North American provincial bourgeoisie.

The case of the United States

14. Let us remind ourselves of several questions: Do blacks and whites belong to the same nation? What does a (bourgeois) nation mean if it has within it real (for a long time legal and now de facto) discrimination other than that based strictly and solely on class? Is this analogous to the problem of the Jews in the capitalist countries where they are discriminated against? Marx told the Jews to renounce their Jewishness. The American Communist Party during the 1930s developed the thesis of a black nation within its territory, the South, its foreign occupiers, the whites, its emigrants, the blacks of the northern cities (62-6, 62-7, 62-8). What is the situation today, now that the majority of blacks have broken all ties with the South and hence lost their status as a minority of oppressed peasants?

Beyond this, does the American nation exist? The state certainly does. The federated states are not nation-states, and despite their size they are no more than Swiss cantons, that is, means to reduce political questions to the level of local quarrels. Beyond this, two theses are possible and perhaps complementary. Either the American nation really exists because all origins have been transcended not ethnically (the melting pot is a myth) but culturally. Or this transcendence occurred through a reduction to the lowest common denominator, the culture perfectly suited to capitalism, that of homo consumens.

Furthermore, the case of the United States poses a more general question, that of recognition of organized social minority groups. The cultural-ethnic groups (blacks, Italians, Polish, WASPS, etc.) may constitute groups of this type, which obviously do not enjoy equal status (WASP domination is evident). The Zionist position claims that there are Jewish communities.

The regional question and the problem of “underdevelopment”

15. Based on this overview, several general observations can be made. First, we should not confuse inequalities of development in the centers with national inequalities. The latter can interact with the former but the two can also exist separately, not interact, or reverse positions. Moreover, we should not a fortiori equate the problem of these inequalities in the centers with that of the center-periphery opposition in the imperialist system. The analogy has its limits. In one case—that of Italy—the problem is very similar. But this is an exception. Inequality is not a problem of the use of space. This contemporary technocratic division has as its goal the mystification of the nature of the process of unequal development, which is inherent in capitalism: the operation of blocs on the state level both globally and locally.

The struggles and controversies over regional problems raise all the questions of the universality of culture in relation to the development of the productive forces. Doubtless regional inequalities in development express the unequal development of the productive forces. But the relation is not one of unilateral cause and effect by one on the other. It is dialectical: the original unequal maturity of the productive forces explains the different modalities of the hegemonic blocs, modalities which in turn widen the gap in the development of the productive forces. In this general sense, the different regional and national inequalities in development during the capitalist era are analogous and must be studied in the same way, i.e., by analyzing the dialectic of class struggle-relations and forces of production.

Nevertheless, one important difference makes it wrong to transpose to regional problems the general analysis of the center-periphery interrelation on the world scale of the imperialist system: regional inequalities exist within the framework of a unified capitalist state. As we have seen, the social reproduction of the capitalist system takes place by means of state policies directed both toward the internal conditions of this reproduction (internal state policies) and toward external conditions (external policy). Neither the supra-state instance nor supereconomic autonomous imperialism exists with regard to national states. The interrelation of internal class blocs and the interrelation of international alliances are not of the same type. Local internal blocs line up in relation to a hegemonic national bloc, which expresses itself in and through the state.

Chapter 6

Center and Periphery in the Capitalist System:

The National Question Todav

The theme of this chapter relates to the whole of my work, which has been concerned primarily with analyzing the material base for the reproduction of the contemporary capitalist system as a world system (70, 71, 72). I will not return to this analysis here but will restate the conclusions relating to the unequal international division of labor (section I) in order to use it as a basis for describing and analyzing the class structure of the contemporary imperialist system and for placing contemporary national questions within this context (section III).

I. The unequal international division of labor,

the material base of the contemporary imperialist system

Analysis reveals a fundamental difference between the auto-centered model of accumulation and that which characterizes the peripheral capitalist system, thereby disproving all linear theories of stages of development. Complete, autonomous capitalism is impossible in the periphery. The socialist break is objectively necessary there. In this very specific sense, the national liberation movement is a moment in the socialist transformation of the world and not a stage in the development of capitalism on a world scale. This is a perpetual question, although'one which is constantly posed in new terms. It is these new terms which I will examine here.

It is worth noting that the concepts of center and periphery, basic to my analysis but rejected by all proimperialist currents within Marxism, were introduced by Lenin in direct relation to his analysis of the imperialist system (82-10).

1.    The determining relation in an autocentered capitalist system is between the sector producing mass consumer goods and the sector producing capital goods. This relation effectively characterized the historical development of capitalism in the center of the system (in Europe, North America, and Japan). It thus abstractly defines the pure capitalist mode of production and was so analyzed in Capital. Marx in fact showed that in the capitalist mode of production there is an objective, i.e., a necessary, relation between the rate of surplus value and the level of development of the productive forces. The rate of surplus value essentially determines the structure of the social distribution of national income, its division between wages and profits, and thereby that of demand: wages correspond essentially to the demand for mass consumer goods, while profits are totally or partially saved with a view to investment. The level of development of the productive forces expresses itself in the social division of labor: the distribution of labor power in appropriate proportions to each of the two sectors.

2.    Although this model is schematic, it is faithful to the essence of the system. By abstracting external relations I do not mean to suggest that capitalist development takes place in an autarchic, national framework but that the basic relations of the system can be understood by abstracting these relations. More precisely, external relations are subject to the logic and the needs of autocentered internal accumulation. Furthermore, the historically relative character of the distinction between mass and luxury consumption also clearly comes in here. Strictly speaking, luxury products are those the demand for which derives from the consumed portion of profit, while the demand that derives from wages grows with the development of the productive forces. However, this historical progression in the type of mass products has decisive importance for an understanding of the problem at hand. When the system began the demand structure fostered the agricultural revolution by offering an outlet for food products on the internal market. Agrarian capitalism thus preceded the origin and achievement of the capitalist mode in industry.

3. We can draw three important conclusions from this model. First, the appearance of the capitalist mode of production in the regions destined to become the centers of the world capitalist system flowed from an internal process of disintegration of precapitalist (here feudal) modes. The disintegration of the feudal relations of production in the rural European world constituted the social framework for the agricultural revolution, which preceded and made possible the industrial one. A prior rise in agricultural productivity made possible the expulsion from the rural world of a surplus, proletarianized population and at the same time created the marketable food surplus necessary for the production of this proletariat.

Second, the articulation in time and space of the class alliances that enabled the new capitalist relations to spread in industry took different forms but always expressed the same basic condition: the alliance of the new dominant class (the industrial bourgeoisie) with landed property (either peasant, after a French-style revolution, or latifundiary when old feudal property was transformed and integrated into the market, as in England or Germany) within the framework of a complete and powerful national state.

Finally, the subjection of external (economic and political) relations to the needs of internal accumulation thus gradually created the world capitalist system. This system emerged as a group of autocentered and interdependent (although unequally advanced) central formations and of peripheral formations subject to the logic of accumulation in the centers that dominated them.

I conclude from this that the view of stages of development (with simply a certain historical lag from one to the other) is generally valid for the gradual establishment of the centers but is not so for the peripheries. This conclusion is the underlying cause of all the implicit and explicit disagreements about the future of the third world. The counter thesis holds, explicitly or implicitly, that despite their extraverted origin, underdeveloped economies are progressing through specific stages in their evolution toward the establishment of autocentered, complete economies. These will be capitalist or socialist depending on the case, for reasons outside the domain defined by this analysis.

4.    Let us consider the stages in the evolution of the peripheries of the capitalist system, at least since the middle of the last century. In this model of accumulation in the periphery of the world system an export sector was created, on the initiative of the center, that would play the determining role in creating and shaping the market. To understand the underlying reason why it was possible to create this export sector, we must look to the conditions which made it profitable. National central capital was not forced to emigrate by a lack of possible outlets in the center: it emigrated toward the periphery in search of higher returns. The equalization of the rate of profit redistributed the benefits accruing from these higher returns and made the export of capital appear to be a means of combating the tendency of the rate of profit to fall. The real reason for the creation of the export sector was to obtain from the periphery products that formed the basis of constant capital (raw materials) or variable capital (food products) at prices of production below those for analogous products, or substitutes for specific products produced in the center.

5.    Here is where the theory of unequal exchange comes in. The products exported by the periphery are attractive to the extent to which the gap between the returns to labor is greater than the gap in productivity. And it may be so from the moment the society is subject by all economic and extraeconomic means to this new function of furnishing cheap labor power for the export sector. From then on, the principal articulation that characterizes the accumulation process in the center—which is translated by the existence of an objective relation between the returns to labor and the level of development of the productive forces—completely disappears. The returns to labor in the export sector will be as low as the economic, social, and political conditions allow. As to the level of development of the productive forces, it will be heterogeneous (while in the autocentered model it was homogeneous), advanced in the export sector and backward in the rest of the economy. This backwardness, maintained by the system, is the condition that enables the export sector to avail itself of cheap labor power.

6. Under these circumstances the internal market created by the development of the export sector will be limited and biased. The limited nature of the internal market accounts for the fact that the periphery attracts only a limited amount of capital from the center, although it offers a higher return on it. The contradiction between the capacity to consume and the capacity to produce is resolved on the level of the system on the world scale (center and periphery) through the growth of the market in the center, with the periphery playing a subordinate and limited role. This dynamic leads to a growing polarization in wealth to the benefit of the center.

Nevertheless, once the export sector reaches a certain size, an internal market appears. Compared to the market created in the central process, this market is biased against the demand for mass consumer goods in favor of luxury goods. If all the capital invested in the export sector were foreign and if all its projects were reexported to the center, the internal market would in fact be limited to the demand for mass consumer goods, a demand in itself limited by the low level of returns to labor. But in fact, part of this capital is local. Moreover, the methods used to assure a low return to labor are based on strengthening diverse local social strata which keep the system going: latifundiaries here, kulaks there, commercial comprador bourgeoisie, state bureaucracy, and so on. The internal market is thus primarily based on the luxury demand of these social strata.

This schema effectively corresponds to historial reality in the first phase of the imperialist system. This phase probably had its golden age between 1880 and 1914, although it began earlier in

Latin America and lasted in other places, notably in tropical Africa, until the 1950s. This was the age of the colonial pact, the colonial and semicolonial form of dominance over the peripheries.

7.    This model is qualitatively different in three respects from the central model. First, the capitalist model was introduced from the outside by political domination. Here precapitalist rural relations did not disintegrate but rather were deformed by being subjected to the laws of accumulation of the central capitalist mode that dominated them. We can see this in the absence of a prior agricultural revolution, that is, in the stagnation of agricultural productivity.

Second, the class alliances that provided the political framework for the reproduction of the system were not primarily internal class alliances but rather an international alliance between dominant monopoly capital and its (subordinate) allies. Broadly, the latter were feudal elements (read: the range of varied dominant classes in precapitalist rural systems) and the comprador bourgeoisie. There was no complete and independent national state which really served these local classes but only an administration in the service of monopoly capital, either directly (colonial case) or indirectly (semicolonial case). Third, external relations were here not subject to the logic of internal development but rather were the driving force and the determinant of the direction and pace of development.

8.    Today this first phase of imperialism is over. What forces brought this about and what kind of evolution ensued? The antiimperialist national liberation movement was the motive force of the transformation. This movement united in effect three social forces: (a) the nascent, superexploited proletariat, (b) the peasant mass, doubly exploited by the dominant local classes and by monopoly capital to whose advantage the feudal elements had entered into the world market, and (c) the national bourgeoisie, at this stage more a potential than an actual class, which wanted to modify the terms of the international division of labor in order to gain an economic base for itself. In fact, the internal division of labor under the colonial pact was simple: the periphery exported only primary products, with which it had to import all the manufactured goods necessary to meet its needs, primarily the needs of luxury consumption; it could not develop industry. The national bourgeoisie and the proletariat vied for the leadership of the national liberation movement, that is, the leadership of the peasant revolt.

Overall, this first phase ended in the victory of the national liberation movement under bourgeois leadership. The victory forced imperialism to accept a change in the terms of the division of labor and made possible the beginnings of industrialization in the third world. We can date this victory. In some places it came early: in Mexico with the 1910 revolution; in Turkey under Kemal Ataturk; in Egypt with the Wafd; in Brazil and Argentina in a populist form. In other places it came late: in southern Asia after the Second World War; in Africa with the independence of the 1960s. Except in East Asia and Cuba, where the national liberation movement opted out of the world capitalist system, everywhere the triumphant national bourgeoisie followed a strategy of industrialization that now has a name: the strategy of import substitution.

9. Because of the specific articulation expressed in the link between the export sector and luxury consumption that characterizes the peripheral model, industrialization through import substitution begins at the end. That is, with products corresponding to the most advanced stages of development in the center, with durable goods. These products are big consumers of capital and scarce resources (skilled labor, etc.). This results in a basic distortion in the process of resource allocation in favor of these products and to the detriment of the production of mass consumer goods. The latter sector is systematically neglected: there is no demand for its products and it does not attract the financial or human resources necessary for it to modernize. This is how we can explain the stagnation of subsistence agriculture, the potential products of which are in low demand and which has no serious means of transforming the allocation of scarce resources. Given the structure of income distribution, the structures of relative prices, and the structures of demand, the choice of any development strategy based on profitability necessarily brings about this systematic distortion.

Seen from the social perspective, this model leads to a specific phenomenon, i.e., the marginalization of the masses. By that we mean an array of mechanisms which impoverish the masses and which take a variety of forms: proletarianization, semiproletarianization, impoverishment without proletarianization of the peasants, urbanization, and massive growth in urban unemployment and underemployment, to name a few. The function of unemployment and underdevelopment here is thus different from that in the central model: the weight of unemployment keeps the returns to labor at a relatively rigid minimum and blocks both the export and the luxury production sector. Wages are not at once a cost and an income that creates a demand essential to the model but are only a cost, with demand originating from outside or from the income of privileged social groups.

The extraverted origin of development, which continues despite the growing diversification of the economy and its industrialization, is not a sort of original sin external to the model of peripheral, dependent accumulation. For this is a model of the reproduction of the social and economic conditions for its operation. The marginalization of the masses is the very condition for the integration of the minority into the world system, the guarantee of a growing income for this minority, which encourages it to adopt Europe-type models of consumption. The extension of this model of consumption guarantees the profitability of the luxury production sector and strengthens the social, cultural, ideological, and political integration of the privileged classes.

10. At this stage of diversification and deepening of underdevelopment, new mechanisms of domination and dependence appear, cultural and political as well as economic. The latter include technological dependence and the domination of transnational firms. The luxury production sector calls for capital intensive investments which only the great transnational, oligopolistic firms can mobilize and which are the material underpinning of technological dependence. But also at this stage more complex forms of property structure and of economic management appear.

Historical experience shows that the participation of local private or public capital, even in a subordinate role, in the process of industrialization through import substitution is common. It also shows that at least in the bigger countries the development of export and luxury production sectors may be sufficient to enable the creation of a capital goods sector. The state is often the impetus for this. The development of basic industry and of a public sector does not mean, however, that the system is evolving toward an autocentered, complete form. For this capital goods sector serves not the development of mass consumption but the growth of export and luxury production.

11. This second phase of imperialism is in no way a stage toward the establishment of an autocentered economy. It is not the reproduction of an earlier phase of central development but, on the contrary, an extension of the first extraverted phase. In fact, three points can be made.

a. The agricultural revolution has still not taken place. Probably we need to introduce certain qualifications. The national bourgeoisie in power has often moved to eliminate old imperialist allies and particularly to carry out agrarian reforms that lay the basis for the beginning of capitalist agriculture (the “green revolution”). Can this development erase the original backwardness of agriculture and bring the peripheral model close to the central model? This question must be answered not only in theory but also in fact. Paradoxically, the relative backwardness of agriculture is such that third world countries where the majority of the population is rural, have become importers of food products. The reason for this is political: in our era the bourgeoisie must depend on those classes, however broad (kulaks instead of big proprietors), that are capable of dominating the peasants. It cannot depend on the peasant mass, whose interests conflict with its own. Although the central bourgeoisies have sufficient time for gradual primitive accumulation based on the peasant alliance, the bourgeoisies of the periphery are doubly constrained by the external pressure of the monopolies and the internal pressure of socialism among the peasants.

b.    The dominant class alliances are still international: the bourgeoisie replaced old feudal and comprador elements as the subordinate ally of imperialism. Due to this, the bourgeoisie, beginning in this second phase, loses its former national character: it becomes “compradorized. ” The national state that it dominates therefore remains weak and only partially integrated.

c.    The development process continues to depend on exports, which consist of raw materials. This primary means of financing necessary imports of equipment in the last instance determines the pace of growth, which in this sense remains extraverted.

12.    The demand for a “new international economic order” brings about the crisis of this second phase. Reduced to its essentials, this demand seems to be the following: to force a rise in the price of raw materials exported by third world countries in order to create additional means, with the import of advanced technology, of financing a new stage of industrialization. This stage would be characterized by massive exports of manufactured products to the centers from the peripheries, which have the advantages of natural resources and a cheap, plentiful workforce (thus the demand for access to the markets of developed countries for these industrial products).

This demand has been the apparent common goal of the entire third world since 1973. It is presented as the necessary and sufficient condition for the achievement of political independence through the acquisition of an economic base. It is also presented as a possible common demand of all the states of the third world, independent of their social options and their international sympathies.

13.    This new situation raises several essential questions which must be discussed quite openly. The first is whether the local bourgeoisie—which generally controls these states—can struggle against imperialism and impose its point of view. Certain authors in fact claim that this new international division of labor is the strategic objective of imperialism itself; that this demand is being manipulated by the monopolies, particularly North American ones;

and that it is thus not a proper goal for third world states which are in conflict with imperialist strategy. These authors usually give preeminence to interimperialist conflicts (United States, Europe, Japan) rather than to this apparent north-south conflict. We know that this theory was widely discussed at the time when the oilexporting countries raised oil prices in 1973 and it had rightwing, leftwing and even ultra-leftwing versions. The facts do not support this interpretation. Indeed, it is nothing more than the naive view of the ultra-left which, taking its desires for reality, would like the bloc of bourgeoisies to be totally unified throughout the world so as to simplify on paper the tasks of the proletariat (70a, b).

In the past, the peripheral bourgeoisie clashed with imperialism. The monopolies did not plan the transition from the first to the second phase of imperialism: it was imposed by the national liberation movements when the peripheral bourgeoisies won from imperialism the right to industrialize. But I have argued that the strategy of industrialization followed during this second phase transformed the relations between the peripheral bourgeoisie and the monopolies. The peripheral bourgeoisie ceased to be national and became the junior partner of imperialism by integrating itself into the new division of labor. Today this partner is rebelling and demanding new modalities in the division of labor. This does not make it national, since its demand is contained within the system; but still it is rebelling. Should this rebellion succeed, it would simply inaugurate a new phase of imperialism, characterized by a new division of labor. For there is no doubt in theory that this rebellion can be coopted. But in theory only; for what counts in history are the accidents along the way, and some serious ones can occur in the peripheries and the centers during the contradiction-filled transition from the second to the theoretical third phase of imperialism.

14. The second question is whether this eventual third phase would or would not be a stage toward the autonomy of the peripheries. The third world bourgeoisies claim so, as they stated during the second phase. But the facts have shattered these illusions, which were shared by an important sector of the third world Left.

Indeed this demand, if it were met, would in no way be a stage in a process of development leading gradually to the creation of complete capitalist formations similar to those of the developed centers. The reason for this is that the new division of labor would be based on export of cheap manufactures by the periphery—that is, products which, given comparative productivity, would permit the rate of profit to rise on the scale of the world system. The worldwide equalization of profit would then modify relative prices and because of this would mask tjie supplementary transfer of value from the periphery to the center. In other words, the new division of labor would perpetuate and aggravate unequal exchange. It would also perpetuate in the peripheries the distortion of the demand structure to the detriment of mass consumption, just as in the preceding phases. The development of the world system would thus remain basically unequal. From then on, external demand would continue to be the principal driving force behind this type of still dependent development.

Let me add that in the framework of renewed dependence, the backwardness of agriculture would also be perpetuated. No doubt one could introduce certain qualifications here because, despite everything, capitalism would continue to progress in agriculture as it began to do during the second phase of imperialism. But here its pace would be much slower than in traditional and new export sectors and in luxury production for the internal market, all of which benefit from the massive import of the most advanced technology.

15.    Within this general framework, we should question the real meaning of the slogans about autocentered development and collective autonomy, slogans that accompany the demand for this new international division of labor. The first slogan really has no content. It is nothing more than the ideological justification for the unfounded claim that development by progressive stages within the world system of unequal division of labor would lead to economic independence.

16.    On the other hand, the second slogan has a meaning in this perspective, but a very specific meaning. The first phases of imperialism implied no cooperation between countries and regions of the periphery. Exclusively extraverted and limited in their industrialization by the needs of their internal markets, the peripheral economies had nothing to exchange with one another. In principle, the third phase in the unequal division of labor would not create more positive cooperation among third world countries, except to join them in struggle for a rise in the prices of their primary exports (through producers’ associations), since this second wave of peripheral industrialization would be impelled by export to the centers.

Yet the countries of the third world are very unequally placed to take advantage of this new division of labor. Those which are best placed by virtue of their economic potential (abundant natural resources, most advanced proletarianization, etc.) and their political stability (legitimation of the power of the weak local bourgeoisie, military power, etc.) could move faster down the road of new dependency if they also had at their disposal the markets of less developed countries and if they had direct access to their providers of cheap raw materials and food products. The problem of so-called subimperialism becomes relevant here.

One example will illustrate this division in the interrelation of the third and fourth worlds within the new global perspective. Taken'together, the Persian Gulf states, Egypt, and the Sudan—if the political conditions existed, which is far from the case today— would be a good candidate. The Persian Gulf states would furnish the capital, export industries would be concentrated in Egypt, the Sudan would export food products to the latter. But let us take a closer look at the mechanisms of this interrelationship. Even if Sudanese agriculture could be modernized to furnish the necessary exportable surplus, its productivity would long remain below that of the advanced countries. But Sudanese food products would have to be competitive with those of North America on the Egyptian market in order to keep Egyptian salaries as low as possible. This would be possible only if superexploitation of the Sudanese peasants continued (rewards to labor more unequal than the distribution of productivity). The Egyptian proletariat would also be superexploited; its low wages combined with its relatively high productivity would allow export of its products to the centers. A double and articulated unequal exchange would take place to the benefit of the center. The Sudan would cease to be directly dependent on the center and become the partner of the first-rank periphery, where export industry would be concentrated.

17. If this is the content of the organization of the new phase of imperialism, can the triple demand for national autonomy, collective autonomy, and a new world order also have a completely different meaning with different goals? If so, under what conditions?

The neoimperialist interpretation of this program is that of a new international division of labor to which internal strategies such as the objectives of intra-third world cooperation are subjected. But the same program takes on another meaning entirely when the procedure is reversed, i.e., when we first define the internal goals of real, autocentered and popular development and then examine the ways in which the world order would have to be changed to make the realization of these goals possible (cf. 74c).

True autocentered development is necessarily popular development. For extroverted development in all the phases of evolution of the imperialist system effectively benefits the dominant privileged classes which are allied with the monopolies. Inversely and complementarily, popular development can only be national and autocentered. To serve the great masses of the peasantry, industrialization must first be used to increase rural productivity. In the same way, those wishing to serve the urban popular masses must stop luxury production for the local market and exportation, both of which are based on the reproduction of a cheap labor force. Let us look more closely at this two-pronged strategy of national independence and social progress.

Up to now, industrialization in the third world has not been conceived of as a means to agricultural progress. In reverse order from the countries of the center, where the agricultural revolution preceded the industrial one, the countries of the periphery imported the second without having begun the first stage. This explains the distortions characterizing these countries and the renewed dependence in which they are trapped. Thus it is necessary to turn the tide. Third world industry continues to be parasitic in the sense that it gets its accumulation by levies from the rural world in real terms (it obtains its labor power from the rural exodus) and in financial terms (fiscal levies, internal terms of exchange unfavorable to the peasants, etc.) without in turn supporting agricultural development. How can this be changed? Clearly, all criteria of profitability, which are necessarily based on the reproduction of price structures and structures of income distribution, must be totally rejected and replaced by other criteria for the allocation of resources. Two essential questions arise here: (1) how to join a modern industrial sector, with a changed basic orientation, with that of small, rural industries, making possible the direct mobilization of latent forces of progress; and (2) why the social form necessary here is rural collectivization, even at a low level of development of the productive forces, and not private agriculture, however reshaped by radical agrarian reform. It is only under these conditions that progress in agriculture, which must first overcome its historic backwardness, can finance healthy industrialization and create a food surplus to guarantee national independence.

In the same way, industry must be put in the service of the poor urban masses and cease to be run according to criteria of profitability, which favor the privileged local market and export toward the developed centers. In no case can industry so transformed adopt ready-made technological models from the developed countries. Nor can it find them in the older technology of the centers by borrowing yesterday’s production techniques, as the theme of intermediary technology suggests. The problem here is different, since industrialization must bring about the agricultural revolution, while in the center the former was built on the latter. The real question revolves not around the conditions for the transfer of technology but the creation of conditions favoring creativity in this area, not for reasons of cultural nationalism but for objective reasons. Another problem should be pointed out, that is, borrowed technology necessarily carries with it capitalist relations of production, while the social framework needed for the agricultural revolution and urban mobilization must be socialist. This question is essential. It translates the necessary character of socialism in the periphery, which is the indispensable condition for progress and independence and not merely the result of an ideological or moral decision. For this reason, I will continue to argue that the movement for national liberation in the periphery constitutes first a moment in the socialist transformation of the world and only later a phase in capitalist development.

18.    Although a model for autocentered development is not synonymous with autarchy, internal and external political factors may lead to the latter, whether it is desired or not. This may be the case not only for large countries such as the USSR or China but also for small countries such as Korea, Vietnam, Cambodia, Cuba, or Albania. Although autarchy in itself is not synonymous with autocentered development, it does provide the condition for it in certain historical circumstances, such as, for example, Burma.

But if autarchy is too abruptly imposed it can impede autocentered development by creating additional costs, which may be very heavy in certain cases. For we cannot reject totally the theory of comparative advantage; we must note only that if the international division of labor is unequal the theory loses its validity. A country that chooses the autocentered and popular road may find that importing certain inputs needed to accelerate development (notably, in some cases, energy or certain raw materials or types of equipment) may be cheaper than doing without them.

19.    To deal with this type of problem, the liberated states of the third world could act collectively in two ways. First, they could practice mutual aid. Since they are rich in natural resources, which are most often exploited exclusively to the profit of the developed countries, they could exchange among themselves raw materials useful to their national projects for autonomous development. Currently, these imports almost always go via the developed

centers, which control the raw material markets and centralized payment facilities. Through mutual-aid agreements (commercial and multilateral payment agreements) the liberated countries of the third world could by-pass these intermediaries. Furthermore, exchange of technology could accelerate the introduction of appropriate production techniques, since the problems which these countries have to resolve are often similar.

This type of intra-third world cooperation is very different from what takes place within the neoimperialist framework. It is no longer a question of common markets that can only produce and aggravate inequalities in development. I am proposing the general outlines of an overall agreement (package deal) in the spirit of cooperation in the service of national, autonomous development.

20. The second type of collective action is designed to modify the international division of labor between the developed countries and the countries of the third world. This means the reduction of inequality and no longer simple change. Already at the present time a good number of third world countries subscribe to the idea of countering consumer monopolies with associations of raw materials’ producers and of strengthening these associations by establishing a collective support fund. In fact, this would necessitate, to start with, national, state control over the exploitation of natural resources. By this I mean not only formal nationalization of this exploitation but also and especially the regulation of the export flow and its reduction to the level of imports set by the internal strategy of autocentered development. For currently the extraverted strategy is based on exactly the opposite relation: exports are first pushed to the maximum, solely to service the demand from the centers, and then the question is raised as to how to utilize the returns from these exports. The unequal international division of labor rests on this strategy. To reduce the inequality in the division of labor certainly means to reduce the flow of raw materials exports.

The formidable resistance of the developed world to this reduc-j    tion is evidence that the center cannot do without the pillage of the

| third world. If this pillage were stopped, the centers would as a

consequence have to modify their structures in order to adapt to a new and less unequal international division of labor. Then and only then could we begin to speak of a real new world order and not only of new terms in the unequal international division of labor.

21. These two general lines, that of a new imperialist order and that of an order that would initiate real progress in the liberation of third world peoples, are not two abstract themes. They are already colliding in the real world, and are the source of daily conflicts.

The reason for this is above all the contradictory nature of the national liberation movement, which is at once the expression of capitalist development and of the crisis of capitalism. Capitalist and socialist tendencies thus are constantly at odds within the movement itself, precisely because the forces of capitalism are ever those of a weak, peripheral, dependent capitalism which objectively cannot realize the goals of a complete capitalism. These forces are in conflict in all third world regimes. In those countries which have broken with capitalism, these bourgeois tendencies persist, as we well know. But conversely, the capitalist states of the third world do not have the complete and unequivocal character of central capitalist states. This explains the volatile nature of their regimes and the wide range of situations, from triumphant neocolonialism to nationalism in conflict with imperialism, by way of shameful or crisis-ridden neocolonialism.

For the conflict with imperialism has certainly begun. The themes of the new international order have up until now been totally rejected, as the failure of the fourth UN Conference on Trade and Development (UNCTAD) and the north-south negotiations indicate. On the ideological level, the Club of Rome is trying to counter with an alternative construction. This is because the themes of the new order convey the aspiration to control natural resources and to strengthen national states, an aspiration that imperialism does not accept.

Theoretically, the new unequal division of labor would satisfy everyone, the peripheral bourgeoisies and the monopolies in the center. For the transfer of industries would bring about the recreation of an unemployed reserve army, which a quarter century of growth has reduced to the point where the system has lost its normal flexibility. And this unemployment would allow the rate of surplus value to rise in the center itself. In the longer run, the center would develop new activities for the overall control of the system— the quartenary industries (software, research and development activities, etc.), new growth industries, the military sector—thereby renewing and deepening the conditions for social-democratic hegemony in the center.

But as we know, in the long run we are all dead. Today resistance to the transfer of industries still overwhelmingly prevails. This pushes up against the wall the bourgeoisies of the third world who as the weaker partners must carry all the weight of the crisis. Thus it becomes impossible to attenuate the violent social contradictions in the third world: the food deficit is growing, the establishment of export industries has been put off sine die, and so on. Because of this, political conditions can evolve in a direction favorable to the initiation of autocentered development. Such is reality: the struggle of the third world against the dominant imperialist hegemony. For many reasons, this struggle is still today the primary force for the transformation of the world.

II. The class structure of the contemporary imperialist system

The unequal international division of labor accounts for the class structure of the contemporary imperialist system.

In 1976 world population passed the 4 billion mark. Of this total ISO million are in the developed capitalist centers (Europe: S70 million; North America: 2 50 million; Japan: 110 million), 2 billion are in the dominated peripheries (Asia: 1300 million; Africa: 400 million; Latin America: 350 million), 1,350 million are in noncapitalist countries (the USSR and Eastern Europe: 360 million; China, Vietnam, Laos, Cambodia, Korea, Cuba: almost 1 billion).

The capitalist centers’ active population, which consists over-

whelmingly of urban wage workers, is divided into three basically equal parts: the working class; the old petty bourgeoisie and the new proletarianized one; the middle (basically salaried) and capitalist layers and classes. Among the 240 million wage workers exploited by capital there are today, with the crisis, almost 25 million unemployed (about 7 percent of the active population).

The population of the periphery is still about four-fifths rural (only Latin America and the Arab world are as yet highly urbanized) and it is estimated that 75 percent of the peasants are poor and/or exploited. But the urban population of the periphery (400 million) is almost two-thirds as large as that of the centers (600 million) and is growing much faster. The unemployment figure for third world cities is at least 50 million, according to the most conservative estimates, that is, twice the unemployment figure in the center in a time of crisis and six or seven times this figure in prosperous times—which are prosperous only in the system’s center.

The income distribution of these classes on a world scale is set out in Table 1. It is important to keep these figures in mind. The basic question of our era is precisely whether the center-periphery combination constitutes a single world, a single system, or two relatively autonomous realities. If one believes, as I do, that the imperialist system is the prime dominant reality, one must draw several conclusions.

1. The bourgeoisie and the privileged social layers attached to it, which form about one-tenth of the system’s population, monopolize almost half the income. This is in gross terms equal to a rate of surplus labor extorted in relation to labor paid on the order of 100 percent (see below for the meaning of the calculation).

The categories “middle and bourgeois layers” include the bourgeoisie in the strict sense of the term—the class that owns and controls the means of production—and the technical and social managers of this control who, despite the fact that they are wage earners, share in varying degrees the lifestyle and ideology of the bourgeoisie. The income of these layers includes the nondistributed profits of enterprise.

Table 1

r    World Income Distribution by Class (1975)

(i)

Millions of persons

(2)

Percentage

of(l)

(3)

Average income per person ($)

(4)

Total income (billions of$)

(5)

Percentage

of (4)

A. Centers Peasantry

35

3

4,300

150

6

Working class

“inferior” category

50

4

3,000

150

6

“superior” category

60

4

4,500

270

10

Proletarianized petty bourgeoisie

110

8

5,200

570

21

Middle and bourgeois layers

90

7

12,000

1,080

40

Unemployed

25

2

Total of A

370

27

6,000

2,220

83

B. Peripheries Peasantry

poor and exploited

600

44

200

120

4

middle

150

11

400

60

2

owners and capitalists

50

4

1,000

50

2

Working class

50

4

600

30

1

Proletarianized petty bourgeoisie

80

6

800

65

2

Middle and bourgeois layers

20

1

6,800

135

5

Urban unemployed

50

4

Total of B

1,000

73

460

460

17

Grand Total

1,370

100

1,950

2,680

100

Discrepancies in percentages result from rounding.


Center and Periphery 151


The concentration of the bourgeoisie in the center of the system obviously results from its imperialist character. The peripheral bourgeoisie is still largely rural. In the periphery, only the urban bourgeoisie has a European type lifestyle and this class makes up scarcely I percent of the population of the system. The middle layers and the urban bourgeoisie of the periphery (the rural element of the bourgeoisie is included in the peasantry) are still very small numerically, the more so as half its members and its incomes derive from Latin America.

2.    All the other social classes furnish surplus labor in various forms to the ultimate benefit of capital, which dominates the whole of the system and exploits all its parts. This is true not only for the working class but also for the proletarianized petty bourgeoisie (salaried workers who are less and less skilled), the pauperized petty bourgeoisie (small producers chained to market mechanisms), and the great mass of peasants. Islands outside the system—ethnographic reservations—are insignificant in our day.

3.    Today we cannot confuse the proletariat with the working class, still less with the working class of the imperialist centers alone. The employed working class is composed of at least four parts. One-third is today exploited by capital on the periphery of the system, where an at least equal mass of unemployed persons exists. Although it produces under technical conditions which are often comparable, it is deprived of the most elementary rights. This part df the working class receives no more than one-sixth of the wages of the working class exploited in the center of the system (the rate of surplus value here is probably on the order of 400-500 percent on the average).

In the center the working class is more and more divided into two parts, the more exploited of which is growing in relative proportion and is gradually being dispossessed of the rights it had won. This type of division of the working class is doubtless not entirely new but has taken on greater proportions and become more systematic as a result of the global strategies introduced by capital during the Second World War in the United States (when

the black population largely took the place of the old working class in the northern metropolises), and extended to postwar Europe with the massive immigration of the 1960s. In its wake have followed characteristic political and ideological effects: the opposition of old union and partisan organizations, spontaneous movements, instability of unemployment (marginalization of the youth), conjunction with the women’s movement (with its working class element), and so on.

I have drawn a line between the “inferior” and “superior” categories of the working class in the centers, corresponding grossly to a numerical division. This enables me to distinguish between the relatively stable part of the working class and that which labors under more difficult, more unstable, and more poorly paid working conditions. Based on divisions that are national (immigrants in Europe), racial (blacks in the United States), regional (southerners in Italy), sexual (temporary female employees), this division has already radically altered the conditions of the class struggle from what they were only half a century ago. Immigrants, minorities, women, and young people today make up almost half the working class in the centers.

The absolute number of the working class (salaried manual workers) of the periphery is no longer negligible. But the majority of these workers are employed in small firms: employment in big mining, transportation firms, and in manufacturing industries is limited. This is not due primarily to the fact of lesser productivity (corresponding to a lesser concentration of capital, especially indigenous capital), for these small enterprises are often modern. It is due above all to the structure of the international division of industrial labor, which is unequal and weighs on the side of light and subcontracting and maintenance industries in the periphery. Correcting for the differences in the style and cost of living from city to country, the average wages of the working class are often as low as the incomes of the peasantry.

For the peripheries, I tried to give an indication of urban unemployment only, without taking account of rural underem-

I

154 Class and Nation    I

ployment, whether overt (peasants without land who can sell their j labor power only for part of the year) or hidden. The estimate of 25 percent of the active population is conservative in the extreme.

The superior part of the working class in the centers is not growing in number (and thus is decreasing proportionately). It is still highly organized, but it also includes a large proportion of foremen, supervisors, and the like, whose jobs are in between direct production and the organization of work. The “labor aristocracy,” which believes it should support the capitalist social and ideological system, is recruited from this category.

The active industrial reserve army has never been small, contrary to ideological rhetoric. It has never been less than 25-33 percent of the working class. But the mass of it, which is structurally stable, is becoming more and more localized in the periphery. Once again this is a new phenomenon, one which appeared after 1945. The conjunctural fluctuations in unemployment in the center remain important but small in relation to the continued growth of the reserve army in the periphery, even in a period of prosperity. This fact obviously has an impact on the comparative conditions of the class struggle and also has ideological and political consequences. The new tendencies in the international division of labor (redeployment) articulate with this structure.

4. The categories grouped under the rubric of “proletarianized petty bourgeoisie” are heterogenous in appearance. I have drawn a line here at an income level that is not significantly higher than that of the upper categories of the working class. Probably the term “petty bourgeoisie” is not really appropriate. It defines quite well the status of petty producers (artisans and small merchants), certain categories of which are gradually being destroyed by competition from modern capitalist enterprises. But it is misleading when applied to the new and numerically expanding petty bourgeoisie, which consists primarily of wage workers who, having nothing to sell but their labor power, are in fact proletarians (as their salary level indicates). Furthermore, the process of progressively taking the skill out of these nonmanual jobs is very rapid. The over-

whelming majority of this category (80 percent) already consists of wage workers, notably of this type. It is true that there exist at the same time new categories of petty producers, car mechanics, for instance, but, unlike the old producers, the latter are frequently in a situation of formal submission to dominant capital. Doubtless, social stratification empirically based on income data has the drawback of this heterogeneity.

The numerical mass of the proletarianized petty bourgeoisie, wage workers in the main, is already greater than that of the working class on the scale of the system as a whole. The living standard of this new proletarian stratum—it has only its labor power to sell—is not significantly different from that of the working class. Its concentration in the center of the system results in large measure from the unequal international division of labor between the center and the periphery. The ideological effects of the formation of this new proletarian layer are already visible: examples include radical movements in America based on a different problematic than that of the traditional working class (gay liberation, the feminist movement, etc.), linked perhaps with the nature of the integration of this category into the work process. It remains to be seen what form this category will take: an autonomous class, a part of the proletariat, or a wavering petty bourgeoisie.

The category “proletarianized petty bourgeoisie” of the periphery is defined so as to group together all the occupations of the petty urban world whose incomes are scarcely higher—this means these workers cannot have a Western mode of consumption. But this category of wage workers in the modern sector (the analogue of the new petty bourgeoisie) is in the minority here (30 million?), while the subcategory of artisans, small merchants, and domestics is in the majority.

5. The mass of the poor peasantry (microfundiaries, small peasants without modern technical means of production) and the exploited peasantry (agricultural workers, sharecroppers, etc.) in the periphery makes up the great bulk of the producers of the imperialist system: 44 percent alone, 55 percent if we include

middle peasants. The income of this enormous mass is tiny: 4 percent of the total product of the imperialist system.

Is it possible to use a table of the equivalents, expressed in incomes, of production within the capitalist system, to analyze the contradictions within this system (without reducing it to a simple and abstract capitalist mode) and pinpoint the tendencies in the accumulation which they control?

For the vulgar economist there is no problem. Prices are the only economic reality: there is nothing other than the immediate phenomenal appearance; value in the Marxist sense is a “metaphysical” category and a pointless detour; capital and labor are two distinct factors of production. The income of each class thus corresponds to its contribution to production, the productivity of each factor being measured by its reward, with allowance made for imperfect competition. But all this is merely a vulgar tautology.

For the vulgar Marxist this table poses no problem either. The reasoning would be along the following lines: if group A were a single country, the value produced would be $2,220 billion (thus $8,700 for each of the 225 million productive workers). The value of labor power would be measured by the value paid to the producers (here $1,040 billion). Surplus value—the form of surplus labor in the capitalist mode—would be $1,080 billion and the rate of surplus value would be about 100 percent.

For group B we cannot speak of the capitalist mode in the strict sense but can speak of surplus labor, since we are talking about a class society (“half feudal, half capitalist”). The value produced is $460 billion; this is $520 per productive worker (880 million in number). Labor productivity is on the average 6 percent of that in A. The volume of surplus labor extorted by the exploiters—landed proprietors and capitalists—is $185 billion (50 + 135); and the rate of surplus labor in relation to necessary labor is 185/275, or 67 percent. Although workers in B are poorer than those in A, they are less exploited.

Of course, this version does not preclude the possibility of transfers of value from B to A, but only under three conditions: (1) as the ownership of the exploiting capital in B comes from A, the visible profits are transferred from B to A; (2) if there is equalization of profit on the scale of the group A + B, a systematic distortion in the organic compositions (higher in A) brings about a value/price of production distortion unfavorable to B; or (3) we take account of imperfect competition. But all this remains quantitatively small.

I do not accept this view, which derives from a systematic obfuscation of the fact of imperialism, expressing a bourgeois point of view within distorted Marxism, whether social-democratic or revisionist. In fact, the very nature of this table is problematic. The prices in which incomes are accounted constitute an immediate empirical category resulting from the summation of the real remuneration of labor set by the conditions of its exploitation and of profit calculated around a certain rate (or several). We cannot deduct comparative productivities from the comparison of incomes (salaries plus profits). We must do the reverse, that is, begin with a comparative analysis of working conditions which define the comparative productivities and the rates of extraction of surplus labor. For the tendencies for the equalization of profit are superimposed on combinations of returns to labor and labor productivity which vary with the conditions of exploitation.

Moreover, capital does not really dominate the whole of the work process systemwide: the great mass of agricultural production and a good part of petty artisanal production are only subject to the formal domination of capital over the process of production without its always being involved in the direct work process. Thus the existing social classes cannot be reduced to two, the bourgeoisie and the proletariat, nor can the system be reduced to a capitalist mode of production functioning on a world scale.

The peasants of the periphery are integrated into precapitalist modes of production by the type of social relations of production and the level of development of the productive forces, which are class modes. This is why the hypothesis of self-subsistence agrarian societies corresponding to earlier communal modes, to the division of society into classes (or the transition to the formation of classes) is only partially applicable and ultimately incorrect: it discounts the integration of the agrarian societies of the periphery into the imperialist system. For in their turn these precapitalist class societies are certainly integrated into the imperialist system. The surplus labor furnished by the exploited peasants and extorted by their traditional exploiters takes the form of commodities circulating throughout the system. Inside underdeveloped countries, it constitutes a material element of the value of the labor power of the local proletariat; and on the outside it constitutes the elements of the value of constant capital and of the labor power of the exploited proletariat in the center.

Furthermore, this integration takes a number of forms. It may be exclusively market integration, with capital intervening not at all in the immediate labor process. More and more this intervention is taking place, the producers remaining free in appearance but in appearance only: they are forced to buy fertilizer, insecticide, agricultural instruments and machinery, to produce a given product under the supervision of the buyers, agrobusiness firms, or the extension services that oblige producers to adopt given production techniques. Due to this, subjection to capital is gradually becoming a reality.

Thus more than two classes exist because there is not a single mode of production, the capitalist mode, but rather several interrelated modes within the capitalist system. It is this global domination of capital over the system that allows us to speak of value as the dominant, general category of the form of the product. Of course, the category of surplus value is more limited in its applicability and cannot, like that of surplus labor, be extended to precapitalist modes. But the domination of capital brings about the transformation of the surplus labor of the exploited producers outside the capitalist mode into surplus value and finally into profit for capital in general and for its monopoly sectors in particular. Because of this it is appropriate to reduce the mass of surplus labor monopolized by capital (a mass created within the capitalist mode and in the

integrated and subject precapitalist modes) to the value paid to the labor power directly and indirectly exploited by capital. This gives an overall rate of surplus value for the system, one that controls the level of the rate or rates of profit.

I can illustrate this line of reasoning with regard to the transfer of value (the terms of transfer are debatable; I am really talking about the distribution of value among the existing classes) based on the figures in Table 1 and on hypotheses, as realistic as possible, related to the different levels of development of the productive forces in the different modes of production articulated, as well as the forms and rates of the exploitation of labor. In fact, production figures as taken from national accounts are not estimates of value but of estimated quantities at prices of production, with abstraction made of imperfect competition. Thus we are looking at transfers in relation to prices of production, that is, systematic distortions in actual prices as compared with production prices due to different conditions of the class struggle and the extraction of surplus labor. I will take the precaution of recalling that in Marxism labor productivity is the productivity of labor in a given branch producing a commodity having a given use value and that there is no sense comparing productivity from one branch to another, as vulgar economies does in its confusion between productivity and profitability.

Thus one could reason as follows. Suppose that the direct producers in the center (working class, peasants, proletarianized petty bourgeoisie: 255 million workers) are exploited under technical conditions which maximize the productivity of their labor in each of the branches of production concerned; and take 100 as an index of this productivity for each of these branches. The return to labor here is about $4,300 per worker and the value created about $8,700, the rate of surplus value being about 100 percent.

In the periphery there are 50 million workers, 80 million proletarianized petty bourgeois, and 750 million peasants who work in conditions of productivity and exploitation which are not the same as those in analogous branches of production in the center. Productivity is comparable in industry because the capitalist mode has been established there. Nevertheless, it can be stated that average productivity in the periphery is comparatively at an index of 50 (it is probably higher). Taking this difference in productivity into account, the value produced by these 50 million workers at the average rate of exploitation of the center (100 percent of surplus value) would be .50 x 50 x $8,700, or $220 billion. If the value of the industrial production of the periphery given empirically, i.e., in going prices, is less than this it is because the rate of exploitation of the workers is much higher than in the center (their salaries are not even half of those in the center but are seven times less), and because the resulting extra surplus labor is not necessarily made up for by a volume of profits that would presuppose a considerably higher rate than in the center. As a result, effective prices differ from prices of production.

As to what the proletarianized petty bourgeoisie produces, I hypothesize an average comparative productivity index of only 30, to take account of the fact that the portion of noncapitalist artisans is relatively larger here and that wage workers in the modern tertiary sector of a capitalist structure analogous to that of the center are smaller in number. The value produced is, still according to these hypotheses, .30 x 80 x $8,700, or $210 million. Here also, we can see that the returns to labor are in a 1 to 6.5 relation, while productivity is only in a 1 to 3 relation.

Agricultural productivity in B is one-tenth that of A, according to figures from the UN Food and Agricultural Organization. The physical product per agricultural worker, measured in comparable physical terms (quintals of grain, with all production being reduced to this equivalent) is in fact in a relation of 1 to 10. Even assuming that the value produced by the peasants of the periphery is reduced to that of its living labor component, with the contribution of dead labor (capital) being zero, if the peasant mass in fact did not furnish extra surplus labor compared to that extorted from the peasants in the center, the return per peasant would here be . 10 X $4,300, or $430, while it is in fact only $240. The extra surplus labor is (430 — 240) x750, or $140 billion and the value of the product is underestimated by that amount (it is in appearance 120 + 60 or $180 billion).

In all, according to these hypotheses, the extra surplus labor extorted from the producers of the periphery due to the harsher conditions of exploitation is on the order of $290 billion, the value produced by these producers being on the order of $220 billion for the workers, $210 billion for the proletarianized petty bourgeoisie and 180 + 140, or $320 billion for the peasantry, for a total of $750 billion, while the apparent value in current prices is only $460 billion.

Where does this extra surplus labor of almost $300 billion go? If we accept that the income of the peripheral bourgeoisie ($135 billion) results from a normal rate of return on the capital it controls (the same as that in the nonmonopoly sectors elsewhere), this surplus labor must be transferred to the center, where it swells the income of the capitalist class (which, without this, would have $780 billion instead of $1,080 billion) and perhaps even (in part) that of the workers who are otherwise exploited. Of course, if the rate of profit is higher in the periphery than in the center, a part of this $300 billion would be in the global income of $185 billion, from which the bourgeoisie and the landed proprietors of the periphery benefit.

In any event, the existence of this mass of extra surplus labor, wherever it goes, allows the average rate of exploitation and profit to rise on the scale of the system. Without this, income distribution, instead of being $1,415 billion for the workers and $1,265 for the bourgeoisie (rate of extraction of surplus labor: 90 percent) would be $1,715 billion against $965 billion (corresponding to a rate of exploitation of 57 percent).

This statistical illustration of the nature of the imperialist problem is not arbitrary. On the contrary, the basic statistics and hypotheses are conservative and tend to underestimate the magnitude of the surplus labor extracted on the periphery of the system. This calculation rests in fact on a systematic comparison of real

productivity and real return to labor which reveals that the disparity always operates in the same direction: the return to labor in the periphery is always much less than the comparative productivity and this disparity is always considerable.

This means simply that the misery of the peripheral workers does not stem only from the backwardness in the development of the productive forces. The peripheral workers are also superexploited. How and to whose profit?

The superexploitation of the peripheral workers—the surplus labor which they furnish—could benefit, in principle: (1) the local classes which exploit them (landed proprietors and local capitalists); (2) capital dominant on the scale of the system, that of the monopolies; and (3) the workers (or some of them, at least) of the imperialist centers. We cannot a priori reject any of these three possibilities. We must first analyze concrete reality and then try to understand theoretically and politically the meaning of this reality in terms of the class struggle.

The volume of surplus labor extracted from the workers, employees, and peasants of the periphery is obviously much too great for me to believe that it is retained completely by the local exploiting classes in the form of rent and profit. The total income of these exploiting classes ($185 billion) is in fact less than the extra surplus labor extracted ($300 billion). Admitting that ground rents are excessive (we know that there is no normal rent level determined by an economic law, but that this level is determined by a power relation among the three partners in the class struggle) and that the rate of profit for indigenous capital is higher than in the center (which no serious empirical study confirms: the highest rates of profit go not to indigenous capital but to monopoly capital), nevertheless, as a decisive proportion of this surplus labor does not appear in the income distributed in the periphery, it can only be undergoing a transfer to the center. This is an invisible transfer because it is included in the price structures.

If, moreover, this surplus labor were retained by the local exploiting classes, we would see a prodigious development of

capitalism, which could then resolve the problem of underdevelopment. For, however antipathetic these classes are, they are not overall any more parasitical than their counterparts in the center. But up to the present time there has been no development of this magnitude. Contrary to the bourgeois theory of underdevelopment, the periphery is not poor but impoverished because it is superexploited, and it is this superexploitation that both reproduces its poverty and retards its development.

How and why is this superexploitation possible? An analysis of the concrete conditions of class struggle is necessary here. The survival—the reproduction even—of precapitalist relations of exploitation is the means of this superexploitation. The distortion in the structure of development based on the unequal international division of labor imposed by imperialism brings about a continuous reproduction of an industrial reserve army of massive unemployment (while this same division of labor reduces this reserve in the center, that is, transfers the inherent contradiction of the capitalist mode to the periphery of the system it dominates). This creates for the young proletariat, deprived of all rights (which is no accident), conditions unfavorable to its struggles.

We must push the analysis of class struggle beyond this point. For since transfer takes place, this system of superexploitation works to the benefit of monopoly capital. The local exploiting classes are only the intermediaries, the junior partners, in this exploitation. This is precisely where their responsibility lies: in their collusion with imperialism. And it is precisely because imperialism benefits from this superexploitation that it operates via international class alliances.

In turn, these alliances have brought about, on the one hand, the reproduction of precapitalist relations and on the other, distortion in the development of capitalism based on the unequal international division of labor. This is why historical development has generally not destroyed precapitalist modes (while development in the center has by and large broken them up) but on the contrary has reproduced them by subjecting them. This essential point escapes

those superficial analysts who equate capitalist development in the periphery with capitalist development per se.

Does the transfer of surplus labor benefit dominant capital, the proletariat in the centers, or both? It would be very surprising if most of this transfer of surplus labor failed to benefit monopoly capital. For after all, in the class struggle monopoly capital has the last word (as long as we remain within the imperialist system) and thus defines the strategies for the international division of labor in accordance with its own interest, which is to raise the global rate of exploitation.

This said, the transfer nevertheless affects society as a whole and in all its aspects and determines simultaneously the conditions of asymmetrical reproduction, accelerating the capacity for accumulation in the center and reducing and deforming it in the periphery. The transfer thus reproduces the conditions for the unequal international division of labor. It is this asymmetrical structure that gives the workers in the center the possibility of carrying on their economic class struggles under more favorable conditions. It allows salaries and productivity to grow in tandem over a long period, bringing about a relative loss which capital makes up for by continually raising the rate of extraction of surplus labor in the periphery.

But at the same time these conditions create a fertile soil for the political illusions of reformism, which has thereby achieved hegemony among the workers of the center. It is these ideologies— interclass national solidarity based on the recognition of the decisive importance of sources of supply of raw materials to assure regular growth in the center, old and new nationalism (panoccidentalism with racist overtones)—more than the material corruption of the labor aristocracy (which also exists but is impossible to measure) that reproduce imperialist ideological hegemony.

The reader can see that this way of formulating and answering questions begins with the analysis of class struggle and of exploitation. The point of departure is, in fact, a survey of the modes of production (type of relations of production and level of development of the productive forces). Based on that, labor productivity

was evaluated in the different areas of activity on the one hand and on the other hand the rates of extraction of surplus labor that characterize these areas in the conditions of fundamental, immediate (exploited against direct exploiters) struggles. The only condition for the validity of the method is the recognition that the imperialist system is the basic reality, that is, that the product of the labor of all the direct producers of the system is commodified and therefore has measurable value. I am not unaware that a part of this product is directly consumed by the producers. But the peasants are no longer self-subsisting and except for several unimportant islands, are all also forced to produce for the market.

I began with the analysis of the concrete conditions of the exploitation of labor and of the class struggle rather than with immediate economic quantities (production estimated by current prices, distribution of their equivalent in incomes), because the latter are, in the final analysis, derived from the class struggle and do not express primary economic laws. A few points should be born in mind in relation to this.

a.    The method does not suppose a reasoning in value terms in the Marxist sense but only in prices of production. The analysis in value terms is indispensable and is the only one which can answer the questions that leave Sraffan analysis speechless, as I argued in The Law of Value and Historical Materialism.

b.    The world system is dominated by the commodity (and by value) and all the precapitalist modes subjected to capital’s domination therefore produce commodities. The terms of exchange between them can thus be such that the surplus labor created in one place is appropriated in another: value can be transferred. But this cannot result from the mechanical working of the law of value of the same type as the equalization of profit (73b-1). Is this a pure power relation, or rather, does it result from the real workings of the class struggle? I opt for the second, richer, line of thought.

c.    I am not concerned with calculating the value or values of labor power in discussing what the workers objectively need to reproduce it. In listing the incomes attributed here and there in nominal terms I am not concerned about their real purchasing power. For if real salaries are by chance not as bad as the comparison of nominal salaries might indicate, this is because, as Rey concludes, “behind each exploited worker stand ten equally exploited peasants” (73b-l).

On the contrary, any method which begins with prices leaves out the class struggle and leads to an economistic reduction of Marxism. It gives preeminence to the law of value (which would directly determine price) over historical materialism (the class struggle). All theories that deny that surplus labor is transferred from the periphery to the center presume, implicitly if not explicitly, that price is the starting point. To say that productivity in the periphery is 6 percent of that in the center because the product per worker (at stated prices) is 6 percent is to ignore the relations of production, the labor process, and the extortion of surplus labor and thus to descend to vulgar economy. It is of little importance that these theories are accompanied by declarations about the preeminence of the relations of production over circulation, and so on. These are additions that contradict the essence of the method of analysis.

Elsewhere I have expressed my views about this proimperialist current within Marxism, which obviously is not itself exempt from the effects of the class struggle. This brand of Marxism, limited to 4 percent of the exploited workers of the capitalist world, can no longer act as a subversive force. It no longer even convinces the 4 percent whom it claims to lead. They are gradually abandoning all references, even verbal ones, to Marxism, which has taken refuge in academic rhetoric (90-4). On the other hand, my analysis corresponds to the interests of 90 percent of the men and women of the capitalist world. It lays the basis for a worker-peasant alliance, an alliance of all exploited workers, on the basis of internationalism, that is, the conditions necessary to change the world.

The method which I reject is based in a West-centered and

linear conception of history. It leads directly to seeing current

struggles in terms of the development rather than the overthrow of capitalism. If underdevelopment is backwardness and not superexploitation, capitalist accumulation will gradually overcome it; the national liberation movement is an integral part of the still rising bourgeois revolution; the possible resistance of the peasants to this development is useless and reactionary. On the contrary, our thesis is that national liberation is part of the crisis of capitalism, of the socialist revolution; and the resistance of the peasants today, that is during the imperialist era, is revolutionary because it lays the foundation for the worker-peasant alliance.

It is important to be aware of the political origin of the gradual development of this line of thought. It developed within the national liberation movements in Asia, Africa, and Latin America. The question raised was whether the peasantry of the periphery was exploited not only directly by local feudal elements but beyond that by dominant capital, and whether due to this, its resistance to so-called development was not evidence of anticapitalist potential. This involved the question of whether it was not incorrect to consider these struggles as necessarily—as vulgar Marxism claims— part of capitalist development, rather than as part of the struggle against all class society. I will not here give the history of the rich and multifarious controversies generated by these questions (cf. 73).

In my own case, critical study of the Nassarian and then the Malian experience in the beginning of the 1960s made it easier to begin criticizing revisionism, culminating with the Chinese cultural revolution. That led me to work out for Africa a typology of modes of extortion of surplus labor from the peasants based on the distinction between the “trade economy” (where I rejected the idea of self-subsistence economy and where the contribution of P. -P. Rey should be noted), the concession economy (where the contribution of Catherine Coquery-Vidrovitch was important), and the reserve economy of South Africa (this analysis was taken up in English several years later by H. Wolpe and thus could finally reach southern Africa).

At the same time, the critique of the traditional analysis of the Latin America communist parties led to questioning the nature— feudal or capitalist—of the rural relations of production in the mercantilist and imperialist periods in Latin America. Although incisive—and debatable—formulations were used in the beginning, the question raised about the effects of asymmetrical integration into the world capitalist system yielded remarkable results. Here the contributions of Andre Gunder Frank, of Fernando Henrique Cardoso, and of many others should be recalled. The return to a critical view of oriental feudalism also belongs here, including the analysis of Kostas Vergopoulos about modern Ottoman Greece, my own about the Arab world, and that of the activists of the Indian subcontinent.

It goes without saying that these criticisms and self-criticisms were motivated by the success of the worker-peasant alliance in China, in Vietnam, and later in Cambodia. Progressively, there emerged analyses that were systematically consistent and formulated the question of the genesis and division of value and of surplus labor on a world scale. The high point of this formulation was the debate about unequal exchange, out of which two camps— anti-imperialist and proimperialist—clearly emerged.

Need I note that this line of thought had to start from the recognition that the imperialist system is the fundamental basis within the framework of which the class struggle operates during our times? The historical preoccupation with the emergence of social classes (in the communal modes) was completely subordinated to that concerning the integration of these classes into the imperialist system. This is why, as rich as their contribution has been on this level (for instance, Meillassoux’ insight with regard to the role of the circulation of wives and of prestige goods) anthropologists who are more concerned with the past, by insisting on the model of self-subsistence, were in danger of developing a line of research which would prove incorrect in the long run because it neglected the effects of the extortion of surplus labor in the imperialist system.

In the course of these controversies, different theses were proposed: the exploitation of the small peasants within a simple petty commodity mode by the exclusive means of the market, the interference of capital in the process of production and the emergence of its “formal” domination, and so on. Different answers were given to the question about the formation and the destination of peasant surplus labor. It would be pretentious to offer a definitive answer to this question, and I am sufficiently conscious of the ultimate importance of the test of praxis to refrain from doing so. In any case, these questions are important and the very fact of asking them while vulgar Marxism obscures them is a sign of the importance attributed to them. But I will observe in passing that these questions are not as new as it sometimes seems: I have found in Kautsky a first example, embryonic but clear, of this type of analysis, which was effectively buried later with the triumph of the reformist ouvrierisme of the movement.

Critical synthesis of these controversies now permits the following five propositions:

1.    The apparent international relations between centers and peripheries must be analyzed in terms of relations between the capitalist mode and precapitalist, subject mode(s).

2.    Subjection-formal domination implies a relation of extortion of surplus labor which is not only based on commodity exchange but also presumes the interference of capital in the process of production, which must be carefully distinguished from the labor process.

3.    The surplus labor transferred does not come from the mechanical workings of the law of value. The price of the transferred surplus thus depends only on a power relation between bourgeoisies (or exploiting classes in general). My analysis of mining rent in the contemporary imperialist system in The Law of Value and Historical Imperialism confirmed this. This power relation rests on underlying relations of exploitation.

4.    As a consequence, “at the same time as each one of its workers, capital simultaneously exploits ten peasants who furnish the agricultural surplus necessary for the reproduction of this worker’s labor power” (73b-l). This quantitative estimate is not arbitrary: it corresponds almost exactly to the real proportions of Table 1.

5. This superexploitation impedes the development of the productive forces in the periphery. As a result, the necessary peasant revolution is not bourgeois but is part of the struggle to overthrow capitalism. For it can no longer be carried out under bourgeois leadership. It will be carried out under the leadership of proletarian ideology or not at all.

Different attempts have been made to measure the transfer of value from the periphery to the center: my own, that of Hosea Jaffe, and that of Andre Gunder Frank (90-4, 72c-5, 72c-6). It may seem odd that since Lenin’s Imperialism so few researchers have dealt with the question of the mechanisms of exploitation in the periphery. Doubtless, it is difficult to isolate these problems from others and the analysis of accumulation on a world scale cannot replace that of the operating mechanisms of capitalism in the center. But this argument does not justify the absence of analyses dealing with particular aspects of exploitation in the periphery, including partial factual analyses, quantitative insofar as possible. In this area, the complicit silence of bourgeois literature and of the dominant current in Marxist literature simply reflects the power of the imperialist-social-democratic alliance.

Andre Gunder Frank’s study of the “disequilibria of multinational commodity exchanges and unequal economic development” provided precious quantitative information about the contribution of the periphery to the financing of accumulation in the center. This study, the first of its kind, tried to evaluate the surplus in the balance of trade of the periphery; in other words, the tribute paid by the periphery to the accumulation of capital in the center. For 1928, this surplus was $1,490 million, which represented 18 percent of the exports from the periphery, and this jumps to 28 percent if we exclude China and North Africa. To this tribute we must add transportation payments related to center-periphery trade (or $1,320 million). In addition, Frank reminds us that these sums, evaluated in current prices, made up only the visible part of the transfer of value: the structure of prices, based on unequal exchange, hides the submerged part of the iceberg.

This surplus allowed Great Britain and Europe to cover their deficit ($2,900 million, half to the advantage of Great Britain and half to the advantage of continental Europe), taking account of the surplus from the United States and the Dominions ($1,410 million). Frank is adamant on this new and essential point: surplus from the periphery enabled Europe to finance its investments in the young centers (the United States and the Dominions). Such an insight is an answer to the argument that investments from the imperialist countries went to the young centers rather than to the dominated countries.

Frank showed that this same structure characterized world trade during the entire imperialist phase. Thus, for the period 1881— 1885, the average annual deficit of Great Britain was $507 million, that of continental Europe was $381 million, while the surplus of the United States was $108 million and that of the underdeveloped countries was $780 million. For the period 1911-1913, the figures were $652, $1142, $536, and $1,258 million (current dollars) respectively. Finally, Frank states that the same was doubtless true for the first part of the nineteenth century, world trade having gone from $500 million in 1820 to $5,000 million in 1870 and $20,000 million in 1913, while the British deficit went from £ 10 million to £100 million and then to £140 million.

There remains an important question that Frank does not address. If this same structure characterized the preimperialist period (1820-1870) as well as the imperialist period, what is the meaning of the imperialist break? There is a strong tendency to underplay the importance of this break, and much confusion has been introduced into this question by all those who want to equate center-periphery conflict within the capitalist system through the different stages of its evolution (mercantilist, preimperialist, imperialist phase) with the conflict between imperialist countries and countries dominated by imperialism. I believe it is necessary to make this distinction very clearly. The fact that the same commercial structure characterized all phases of capitalism with regard to center-periphery trade simply means that the periphery paid tribute to the accumulation of the center during each phase of its evolution.

The nature of the imperialist break is on another level. First on the quantitative level, the export of capital which monopoly had made possible allowed the capitalist mode of production to be directly implanted in the periphery and exploitation to be intensified as a result. To the forms of formal domination and diverse levies on the level of circulation were juxtaposed new forms of real domination which in turn strengthened the original forms by extending their scope. But over and above this quantitative leap, the essential nature of the break is on a decisive and entirely new qualitative plane. From then on, the hegemonic sector of capital, that of the monopolies, acquired the capacity to balance concessions in one place by superprofits in another, through the simultaneous exploitation of labor power in the center and in the periphery of the system. This is the foundation of social-democratic policy, which is thus always social-imperialist. It is at the same time the basis of unequal exchange. The decisive importance of this break, particularly on the level of strategy for the socialist transformation, should be stressed.

Another study by Frank, “Limits of the extent of the internal market by the international division of labor and by relations of production,” recalls the intimate connection that exists between the unequal international division of labor and internal social structure. Frank notes that the unequal division of labor and the disequilibrium of exchange operated during the entire last two centuries to the detriment of the periphery. This occurred independently of the terms of exchange, whether they got better (in the nineteenth century) or worse (in the twentieth century). Unequal exchange in the strict sense in which we are using it belongs to the imperialist phase alone and thus caps a long history of asymmetrical relations. This asymmetry does not relate to the nature of the products exchanged. Frank reminds us of the reasons. The absence of pull effects capable of generating autonomous capitalist development in the periphery is due to the latter’s social structure. Here, too, it is the class alliance of imperialism with the local bourgeoisie that creates the social conditions permitting the reproduction of the conditions for imperialist exploitation, with the modalities which evolved in tandem with those defining the terms of the unequal international division of labor, in conjunction with the phases of imperialism controlled by the development of national liberation struggles.

III. The national question in the periphery of the imperialist system

1. The national question, which in the nineteenth century was primarily that of oppressed European nations, was transferred in the twentieth century to Asia and Africa, where it became the colonial question.

This was not only a geographical transfer. As a correlate of the formation of the imperialist system, it implied a change in the very nature of the national question. The old national question, that of European nationalities oppressed by absolutist feudal regimes, was part of the incomplete bourgeois revolution. The new national question, that of the peoples oppressed by capitalist imperialism, is part of the rising socialist revolution. It is, more precisely, one of those “bourgeois democratic” demands (like the peasant demand for agrarian reform) which can only be satisfied during the bourgeois stage of an uninterrupted revolution under proletarian leadership (70c).

The principal axis of the new national question is thus defined by its anti-imperialist character. The goal of what follows is not to take up those general controversies concerning the nature of imperialism, the meaning and perspectives of the national liberation movement, and so on, and to restate theses I have already put forward in these areas. I am only going to define the nature of the nations oppressed by imperialism, their particular characteristics

today in contrast with those which yesterday defined the oppressed nations of Europe.

2. It does not suffice to proclaim that capitalist development necessarily engenders the transformation of ethnic groups into nations (this development moreover has not been the only path for the establishment of nations). We must also note that only the constitution of central capitalism allows the national formation to take shape. On the other hand, capitalist development in its peripheral forms destroys society and hinders its possible constitution into a nation. The reason is that capitalism is not based on the systematic strengthening of the local commodity, capital, and labor market as the axis of its development, of autocentered development.

Integration into the international system on the basis of the unequal international division of labor and the extraverted character of the economy, with modernization beginning in the new export sectors, does not create a decisive internal market. Insofar as one is created at all, it becomes the basis for an import substitution industry exclusively geared to the demand of the exploiting classes. Production for the satisfaction of the needs of the large masses basically continues to be organized within the rural, self-subsistence framework, following the modalities of predominant formal domination.

The crushing domination of foreign capital removes all meaning from the expression “capital market. ” Local capital, fragmented and subordinate, does not reach the critical mass needed to constitute a capital market. The monetary and financial systems also remain extraverted, partial, and limited in their functions. The predominance of formal domination also prevents one from speaking of a generalized labor market, despite the relative importance of the reserve army of urban unemployed.

All these familiar phenomena of the disarticulation of the economy and of underdeveloped society impeded the formation of a nation. They also modify, in the same way, the meaning and content of the state. The most extreme position related to this problem claims that the peripheral state is nothing more than an administration, an excrescence of the dominant imperialist state,

to which one cannot transfer the classic Marxist analysis that defines the state as the hegemonic bloc of local exploiting classes (77d-10). But this onesided and simplifying thesis does not allow us to understand the differences among the feudal-comprador state (imperial China, for instance), the dependent bourgeois state (modern Egypt), the neocolonial state (government by a comprador bureaucracy close to the colonial administration), or the populist, nationalist state, among others. It substitutes for an analysis in terms of variable alliances (yesterday the feudal-comprador alliance, today the dependent bourgeois alliance; imperialist capital dominant with local, subordinate exploiting classes as transmitters) an analysis in terms of “foreign agents.” But, as extreme as this thesis is, it does draw attention to the submission of the exploiting classes in the international alliance and the direct representation of the interests of foreign classes.

The correct thesis about the peripheral capitalist state of our period must be based on a concrete analysis of the local hegemonic bloc—transmitter of imperialist domination. Because this bloc is weak and subordinate, the countries of the periphery are the weak links in the imperialist chain. Thus the revolutionary bloc can form more easily and in the framework of a general strategy of uninterrupted revolution by stages, create effective tactical alliances likely to erode the hegemonic bloc.

3.    One of the characteristics in which we can see the absence of a national construct is the fundamentally foreign nature of the culture of the local bourgeoisie. Denationalized, acculturated, these dominant classes progressively take on the look of strangers in their own country due to their daily lifestyle, modeled on that of homo consumens universalis. In extreme cases, a caricature of bilingualism obtains: the ruling class uses the language of the old colonial masters while the people continue to speak the vernacular. How can we speak of nation and national culture under such conditions?

4.    The peoples of the periphery, separated by boundaries that are for the most part arbitrary and artificial, constitute neither one nor

several nations, in the framework of the majority of the states that define their international existence. They are formed of one or more ethnic groups, sometimes close (linguistically, for instance) sometimes far apart; sometimes clearly separate geographically, sometimes intermingled and living in symbiosis (farmers and herders of different ethnic groups coexisting in the same area, for example). They may also be very unequal numerically. These ethnic groups have sometimes retained, for all or some of their members, more or less ancient forms of social organization (clans, tribes). Sometimes they have been constituted into precapitalist, advanced tributary ethnic groups (“quasi nations”).

Different modalities of oppression, of ancient or recent origin, characterize the relations between these ethnic groups. There are conquered peoples and conquering peoples of past epochs, majorities and minorities, those whom peripheral capitalist development has favored and those it has disfavored, and those which predominate among the urban elite and those which are excluded from it, among others. As a whole, these realities create conditions unfavorable to the maturation of class consciousness. Class struggles frequently manifest themselves as ethnic struggles; thus they can be manipulated internally and externally by reactionary classes and imperialist forces.

5. Under these conditions, the national liberation movement is often “a national movement without a nation” (77). At a given moment, the unity of the anti-imperialist classes can provide the means to overcome these divisions. Nkrumah’s pan-Africanism, from which developed the Organization of African Unity (OAU), pan-Indian unity, and even the artificial unity of Pakistan show that this is possible. But this kind of national or pseudonational unity survives only with difficulty the circumstances which made it possible for the moment. Once independence is acquired, internal contradictions come to the fore. A sytematic study of these contradictions would merit more attention than it has heretofore received; the break-up of Pakistan, the permanent threat which weighs on India, the civil wars of the former Congo during the

1960s, the civil war in Nigeria, current events in the eastern horn of Africa and in the western Sahara, tribal uprisings (for instance in the southern Sudan) show the instability of these nonnational state units.

6.    Under these circumstances, what attitude should the popular vanguard take with regard to the problem of nationalities? It certainly cannot deny their existence, as is often the official position. It cannof be confenf with (fie goal ofthe abolition ofclass exploitation; it must explicitly put into its program the immediate and real struggle against all forms of discrimination, inequality, and oppression based on ethnicity, language, religion, or custom. But should it go so far as to uphold the right to national self-determination to the point of secession? We cannot avoid this question.

Two principles must be kept in mind. The first is that the right to self-determination up to secession must be recognized in principle. The second is that secession should only be accepted as a last resort when all else has failed, when the vanguard has failed to get the exploited masses to accept a struggle for real local autonomy within the framework of as large a unified state as possible. For the anti-imperialist struggle has nothing to gain from the weakening of the states of the periphery by balkanization, which moreover could go on ad infinitum.

7.    The states of the third world are still unstable. But they are so to different degrees, depending on the character of their precapitalist antecedents and the nature of the hegemonic bloc in power. These antecedents are indeed sometimes nations, tributary quasinations, close ethnic groups, and sometimes fragmented tribes without historic or linguistic unity. The bloc in power sometimes consists of latifundiary classes with roots going back to national precolonial history, sometimes of a clearly constituted though new industrial bourgeoisie, and sometimes, by contrast, almost exclusively of a light comprador bureaucratic layer fabricated by the colonizer and without local roots.

The conjunction of ethnic fragmentation and comprador bureaucratic power defines a type of state that is particularly unstable. It is

no accident that this conjunction, which prevails in sub-Saharan Africa, is accompanied by the absence of national languages and by cultural alienation in its most violent form. The sad past of whole regions of the continent fashioned during the slave trade exacerbates the weakness of these societies. The slave trade not only bled white entire peoples; it also engendered the establishment of slave-trading coastal military states and produced a local ideology of the corrupt despotism involved in this trade. The subsequent Christianization of these societies has perpetuated cultural dependence on Europe, while the comprador bureaucratic power was able to reproduce the despotic and corrupt ideological models of the trade.

Will the new state, resting on these bases, be able to create a nation and civil society? Cornered between dominant imperialism, which can intervene effectively with modest means (coups d’etat, military operations involving a few hundred mercenaries, etc.), and tribal divisions, the state cannot stabilize itself. The peasant struggles, which always take on tribal dimensions, can threaten it, can be manipulated from the outside and inside, leading to the break-up of the comprador bureaucracy. These conjunctions explain in large measure the regressions occurring with accelerating frequency on the continent. Doubtless the formation of civil society, separate from the state, as a concomitant of complete capitalist development, is embryonic everywhere in the third world. But it has more or less begun and it can scarcely do so in the most unstable situations.

Few political thinkers who are conscious of these problems have dared to tackle them. Nkrumah’s greatness lay in his attempt to overcome this problem through pan-Africanism. It was probably utopian, but it had its moment of strong and real impact, without which the establishment of contemporary states would perhaps have been even more uncertain.

8. The national liberation movement has nevertheless sometimes operated within a different situation, in real precapitalist nations (complete tributary ones) or in strong and homogeneous

quasinations of this type (China, Korea, Vietnam, Cambodia among the liberated countries; Egypt, Morocco, Iran, Madagascar, Sri Lanka, Burma, Thailand, and even Indonesia among countries still in the imperialist network). Specific problems relative to the national question are sometimes added to those of the local nation, like the problematic of the Arab nation or that of Latin American pan-Hispanicism.

It goes without saying that these conditions have generally been a factor favorable to the radicalization of the class struggle. In East Asia, we have seen a particularly favorable conjuncture consisting of three elements: first, the marked differentiation of the rural classes on the basis of harsh feudalism, which was the basis for the revolutionary uprising of the peasantry; second, the existence of a proletarian core and of an intelligentsia with cultural roots deep in national history, confronted with the social, political, and ideological reality of imperialist exploitation; and third, the marked character of the national existence of homogeneous peoples (Chinese, Vietnamese, Cambodian, Korean). It is no accident that in this region national liberation paved the way for the establishment of powerful national and popular states whose involvement in the long socialist transition has the best chance of success. It is no accident that in the Congo in 1960-1963 or in Ethiopia at present anti-imperialist and social struggles of great magnitude either failed or succeeded only with much greater difficulty in becoming radicalized and developing a correct strategy. Elsewhere, then, we must think about a strategy which takes account of very different conjunctures from those of East Asia.

9. Marxist discussion of the colonial and national questions is as yet little developed. The viewpoints expressed by Marx and Engels do not suffice as a basis from which to draw general conclusions useful for today. The viewpoints subsequently developed in the congresses of the Second and Third Internationals, and those of Rosa Luxemburg, Lenin, Trotsky, and Stalin treat essentially two series of questions: those about precapitalist modes of production (especially controversies about the asiatic, slave, and

feudal modes), and those about the nature of the imperialist system and national liberation in general (70). The first of these controversies has been the most often disappointing because the most important interested parties, the peoples of Asia and Africa, have been almost totally excluded. Infinite exegesis of several elliptical texts of Marx and Engels (the Grundrisse, journal articles, letters), for which Marxology has a predeliction, is completely inadequate. The second series of controversies furnished for the Third International a global Leninist framework which is basically correct. But it cannot make up for the lack of concrete analysis.

10. Today the situation calls for concrete and systematic thought about the interrelationship of class and national struggles. This thought must be based on the following five principles.

First, the struggle for socialism in the periphery of the imperialist system cannot be separated from, and even less opposed to, the struggle for national liberation. The fact of imperialism obliges us to envisage the transition to socialism as resulting from the historical fusion of the goals of social and national liberation.

Second, this double-edged struggle cannot really be carried through—in terms of either national or social liberation—except by the popular bloc under the ideological leadership of the proletariat. The autonomy of the popular strategy must be affirmed in theory and in practice. This autonomy guarantees the possible success of a strategy of uninterrupted revolution by stages. Its absence reduces the popular forces to a supporting role for bourgeois strategies, which are so many dead ends.

Third, the popular bloc must try to overcome national contradictions among the people and preserve the largest possible state framework.

Fourth, the popular bloc must adopt a flexible tactic, based on a correct analysis of the nature of the hegemonic bloc of the local state and the weaknesses and contradictions that characterize it. It must also know how to take advantage of opportunities to weaken this hegemonic bloc.

Fifth, the popular bloc must be extremely vigilant with regard to

foreign powers and especially superpowers who try to bend all confused forces to the ends of their overall planetary strategy. Each time these principles are forgotten in theory and in practice, movements, even popular ones, objectively become playthings in the hands of the superpowers.

In light of these principles, we could undertake a critical examination of the strategy and tactics adopted during recent times: those with positive outcomes, as in East Asia, and those with less positive or even quite negative ones, including Chile, Argentina, Brazil, Peru, and Latin America in general, wavering between revisionism and Guevaraism; Palestine and Nasserism; communist movements in India, Bangladesh, and Southeast Asia; popular movements of Lumumbaism and of Black Africa and Madagascar in general, and liberation movements in South Africa.

Chapitre VII

La liberation nationale et la transition sociale

La bourgeoisie est-elle encore une classe montante ?

La question fondamentale de notre epoque, sur laquelle s’articulent toutes les autres, est de savoir si la bourgeoisie est toujours une classe montante. Si elle l’est, quelles en seraient les manifestations determinates ? Le progres continu des forces productives dans les centres imperialistes hegemoniques et son role moteur a l’echelle mondiale dans le fagonnement des societes sous tous leurs aspects ? Ou le developpement du capitalisme dans les regions d’Amerique latine, d’Asie et d’Afrique, qui n’avaient ete jusqu’a present que touchees superficiellement ? Ou l’emergence de formes neocapitalistes dans les regions qui avaient rompu avec le capitalisme pour amorcer une transition socialiste : U. R. S. S. et aussi, peut-etre, Cuba, la Chine, le Vietnam, etc. ?

Si, en revanche, on pretend que la bourgeoisie n’est plus une classe montante, quelles seraient les manifestations determinates de la crise du capitalisme ? La remise en cause, fut-elle encore purement intellectuelle et marginale, de la civilisation dans ses centres avances ? La crise des valeurs et l’emergence d’une nouvelle conscience ouvriere autogestionnaire ? Ou encore les impasses du developpement capitaliste en Amerique latine, en Asie et en Afrique ? La possibilite (la necessite ?) d’une radicalisation a partir de la lutte de liberation nationale ouvrant la transition socialiste ? Ou les impasses de la restauration du capitalisme apres la rupture socialiste et le progres malgre tout, par avancees successives et inegales, des experiences de la transition socialiste ?

D’un autre cote, la question de savoir si le capitalisme ne peut etre depasse que par le communisme, auquel conduit la transition socialiste, reste posee. Le capitalisme pourrait-il etre suivi d’un nouveau mode de production de classes encore necessaire (ou tout au moins possible) pour assurer un developpement des forces productives qui permettra de faire de l’abolition des classes une exigence implacable de progres ulterieurs ?

Les elements de la realite immediate sont suffisamment contradictoires pour autoriser, si on le veut, des reponses definitives dans un sens ou l’autre. Et les textes des grands classiques du marxisme, Marx, Engels, Lenine, Mao, sont suffisamment riches pour fonder de telles reponses sur la marxologie. Nous avons prefere nous appuyer sur une double reflexion systematique : d’une part sur l’histoire du developpement du capitalisme a l’echelle mondiale, et, d’autre part, sur l’outillage conceptuel marxiste mis en reuvre pour comprendre cette histoire. Des lors que l’on ne cherche a comprendre que pour agir, il n’est plus possible de pretendre, comme le font les theoriciens bourgeois, separer la science de l’ideologie.

On a deja amorce cette reponse dans ce qui precede : d’une part en suggerant une explication historique et theorique des raisons pour lesquelles le capitalisme est apparu et s’est developpe et en combattant sur ce terrain les propositions theoriques animees par une philosophie occidentalocentriste et lineaire; d’autre part en proposant une analyse plus poussee des contradictions de l’epoque contemporaine, qui se manifestent par l’opposition centre/peripherie au sein du systeme capitaliste mondial dans les differentes phases de l’imperialisme, parce que c’est la base a partir de laquelle peut etre etablie une appreciation correcte du mouvement de liberation et de ses perspectives.

Nous tenterons maintenant d’aller plus loin, en nous transportant de ces plans historiques aux plans, plus generaux, de la nature ambivalente et contradictoire, d’une part, du mouvement de liberation nationale et, d’autre part, de la transition socialiste.

I - La nature contradictoire de la liberation nationale

1) L’analyse occidentalocentriste de la transition au capitalisme neglige le role decisif que la peripherie remplit des les origines. Elle pretend que ce sont les contradictions internes du feodalisme qui seules expliquent ce passage. Elle erige meme cette position en principe du marxisme. Les revisionnistes de notre epoque, inspires par les schemas de Tokei, fondent sur ce principe la conclusion que seule l’Europe pouvait inventer le capitalisme, l’Asie etant condamnee a stagner indefiniment au stade anterieur.

En realite, les contradictions internes sont premieres et decisives. Elles sont les memes dans tous les systemes tributaires et impliquaient le passage necessaire au capitalisme dans tous les cas. Elles pouvaient par elles-memes, et sans aucun effet externe, engendrer le capitalisme en Europe comme ailleurs. Mais il ne faut pas confondre cette proposition generale et l’explication concrete de la transition telle qu’elle a eu lieu effectivement. Si celle-ci a ete amorcee plus vite et plus tot en Europe, ce n’est parce que l’Europe pouvait seule inventer le capitalisme, mais a cause du caractere primitif du feodalisme. Dans la formation concrete, historique, du capitalisme, l’Europe s’est constituee et soumise, des les origines mercantilistes, une peripherie dont l’exploitation a, d’une part accelere le rythme de son developpement propre et d’autre part arrete puis detourne celui des regions soumises. Ce que font les ideologues de l’imperialisme, quand bien meme ils se reclament du marxisme, c’est de confondre des propositions methodologiques fondamentales et le deroulement concret effectif de l’histoire, reduisant ainsi les faits a un simple schema. Si une epidemie avait fait disparaitre toute la population de l’Asie, de l’Afrique et de l’Amerique, le capitalisme europeen se serait constitue quand meme, donc sans peripherie. De meme, si l’epidemie avait fait disparaitre toute la population du globe a l’exception de celle de la Chine, le capitalisme se serait constitue en Chine. Mais il n’y a pas eu d’epidemie, et le capitalisme s’est constitue en fait en exploitant la peripherie. Il faut donc rendre compte de ce fait, et non en eluder la presence genante par un discours pretendument theorique.

Un parallele : le debat sur l’imperialisme. Rosa Luxemburg croyait pouvoir demontrer que le mecanisme de l’accumulation ne pouvait pas fonctionner, meme theoriquement, sans peripherie. Elle avait tort. Lenine a rappele comment les schemas du livre II etablissaient bien la possibilite d’une accumulation sans milieu exterieur. Mais Lenine n’en tirait pas pour autant la conclusion que la peripherie n’existait pas. Au contraire.

2) D’ailleurs, lorsqu’on recuse les « effets externes », s’agit-il veritablement d’effets externes ? Externes a quoi ? Si l’on considere le systeme capitaliste mondial, les relations entre le centre et la peripherie ne sont pas externes, mais bien internes au systeme; et les contradictions du capitalisme doivent etre saisies a ce niveau, dans tout le champ de la realite capitaliste concrete. Pour eliminer celle des contradictions qui embarrassent le plus, on procede a une reduction prealable du systeme capitaliste au mode de production (dans sa purete abstraite). Les innombrables « lectures du Capital» sont alors substituees aux lectures du capitalisme; et la rigidite dogmatique erigee en principe fondamental.

La logique de ce comportement conduit droit a sortir du marxisme. En poussant jusqu’a son terme cette separation entre les effets internes et les effets externes, au mepris de toute dialectique, on devrait parvenir a la conclusion que les contradictions ne doivent meme pas etre saisies au niveau de la formation nationale, mais exclusivement au niveau de l’unite de base ou nait l’exploitation capitaliste, l’entreprise. N’exclut-on pas en effet la circulation de cette analyse appauvrie, pour s’obnubiler indefiniment sur la genese de l’exploitation dans les rapports de production ? Sous le pretexte que, dans le marxisme, la production commande la circulation, on taxe de « circulationiste » toute reflexion sur la circulation, et en fait on cesse de regarder la realite, on sterilise toute reflexion, on s’interdit toute action. La redistribution de la plus-value par la circulation du capital (le livre III du Capital), l’analyse des rapports entre travail productif et travail improductif, la definition correcte du travailleur collectif, l’analyse des alliances de classes propres a une formation, tout cela etant rejete hors du champ de l’etude, on en arrive a une position politique qui a un nom, l’anarcho-syndicalisme, et qui invite les travailleurs a se desinteresser de la politique. Une certaine mode autogestionnaire, au moins dans sa version la plus naive, s’alimente de cette reduction theorique.

Il faut conserver la vision de la totalite. Celle-ci — le systeme capitaliste mondial, en l’occurrence — ne peut etre reduite ni au mode capitaliste pur ni meme a une constellation de formations nationales inegales. Il faut preciser le contenu de cette inegalite, qui ne prend sa dimension que par rapport a la totalite et non par rapport a chacune des parties. L ’inegalite, quelle qu’en soit l’origine, permet une hierarchisation organisee qui, non seulement la reproduit statiquement, mais la renouvelle dynamiquement.

Le systeme capitaliste a toujours ete mondial. Et l’on ne peut rien y comprendre si l’on exclut l’interaction entre les effets internes d’une de ses parties et les effets externes a cette partie. C’est pourquoi l’apport de ceux qui ont mis l’accent sur le role de la peripherie dans la constitution du capitalisme des ses origines n’est ni mince ni meme seulement complementaire. Il retablit l’histoire dans sa vraie dimension. On ne saurait leur reprocher d’avoir « neglige » les effets internes : d’autres en avaient epuise l’etude, et nos auteurs ont utilise leur apport, mais dans une perspective qui, en liant les effets internes aux pretendus effets externes, donnait au capitalisme sa pleine dimension. A partir de ces travaux, il est necessaire de formuler a nouveau des questions fondamentales a la comprehension du capitalisme, entre autres l’articulation entre production et circulation (et la problematique du commerce lointain dans les systemes precapitalistes et dans la transition au capitalisme), la division internationale du travail et l’echange inegal, c’est-a-dire l’organisation du processus productif a l’echelle mondiale, l’action de la superstructure politique et ideologique, etc. Autrement dit, toutes les questions que la reduction dogmatique du capitalisme au mode capitaliste pur s’emploie a eliminer.

3)    Dans ce cadre, la question de l’echec de la transition au capitalisme des societes tributaires les plus evoluees et de la reussite europeenne peut etre posee en termes scientifiques.

Il faut cent tentatives dans l’histoire avant qu’une percee decisive permette d’atteindre un point de non-retour. Le mercantilisme egyptien de Mohamed AH avait amorce un developpement capitaliste qui n’a peut-etre ete arrete par rien d’autre que par l’agression europeenne (cf. 76b-6). Meme en Occident, lorsqu’on y regarde de plus pres, on decouvre qu’avant la percee anglaise il y a eu les tentatives avortees de l’ltalie et de l’Espagne. Va-t-on ramener le miracle europeen aux dimensions de l’Europe du Nord ? Partir de Marx pour aboutir a Max Weber ?

Cette serie d’echecs de societes non europeennes n’a rien de surprenant. Ne voit-on pas, de la meme maniere, les tentatives du socialisme avorter plus frequemment qu’aucune theorie generale ne pourrait le suggerer ? Irait-on conclure de l’echec de la Commune de Paris que la formation frangaise ne pourra jamais engendrer le socialisme ? Et que dire de l’echec

du chartisme anglais au xixe siecle ou de la radicalisation du mouvement

ouvrier aux Etats-Unis au XXe siecle ? Certains pretendent encore, il est vrai, que le socialisme etait impossible en Russie (a moins que la revolution allemande ne vienne a son secours), qu’il est condamne d’avance en Chine, au Vietnam et partout ailleurs qu’en Europe et aux Etats-Unis...

4)    S’il a toujours ete mondial, le systeme capitaliste n’en a pas moins franchi quelques etapes. Dans cette periodisation, la coupure imperialiste est essentielle. Elle marque en effet la fin de la phase montante du capitalisme a l’echelle mondiale et le debut de sa crise. Dans ce sens, c’est bien le « stade supreme » du capitalisme. Naturellement, le capitalisme a continue a se developper apres 1880 et meme a des rythmes tres superieurs a ceux du passe. Mais ce developpement n’a plus jamais permis l’emergence de nouveaux centres : desormais, le developpement du capitalisme est simultanement developpement de l’imperialisme et du sous-developpement. On peut periodiser a son tour la periode imperialiste et meme degager les lignes directrices d’une nouvelle etape possible du systeme imperialiste.

La these des « limites absolues », qu’on pourrait attribuer a Rosa Luxemburg, neglige ce point decisif, que le developpement du capitalisme a la peripherie reste developpement d’un capitalisme dependant et inacheve. Et l’erreur de certaines tentatives de periodisation provient elle aussi d’une appreciation insuffisante de la nature de la coupure imperialiste.

5) Cette coupure ouvre la periode de la transition socialiste a l’echelle mondiale dans le cadre d’un modele de developpement inegal. Telle est l’essence de la these que nous defendons. Car l’imperialisme a transfere le centre de gravite des contradictions du capitalisme, relegue les contradictions majeures d’hier au rang de contradictions secondes, modulees par de nouvelles contradictions. La lutte de la classe ouvriere des centres a cesse d’etre le moteur principal de l’histoire. Cecil Rhodes avait compris que la guerre civile pouvait etre evitee en Europe a condition de transferer les contradictions du capitalisme par son expansion exterieure. L’hegemonie social-democrate n’a pas d’autre sens. Mais, en meme temps, l’imperialisme a pousse sur le devant de la scene une nouvelle force anticapitaliste, celle des nations de la peripherie, dont le combat est devenu le moteur de l’histoire. Une lutte gigantesque s’engage au cours de laquelle s’affrontent la bourgeoisie et le proletariat de ces nations, lutte dont l’issue est decisive pour le socialisme. Comme la liberation nationale ne peut etre achevee sous la direction de la bourgeoisie, elle doit se poursuivre d’une etape a l’autre du developpement du systeme imperialiste, jusqu’au moment ou, le proletariat etant parvenu a lui en arracher la direction, la liberation nationale achevee pose les problemes nouveaux de la transition socialiste.

C’est ainsi que le socialisme se fraie sa voie, une voie qui ne pouvait pas etre prevue a l’avance.

Il resulte de cette situation que l’analyse des contradictions du capitalisme contemporain doit prendre d’emblee tout le systeme mondial comme champ d’apprehension. En rappelant indefiniment la preeminence de l’analyse de Sexploitation capitaliste a sa source, dans les rapports de production capitalistes, on remplira des manuels elementaires, quelquefois des theses academiques, mais on n’avancera pas d’un pouce. Tout marxiste qui considere que l’analyse des contradictions a l’echelle mondiale est un exercice decoratif, tout marxiste qui, en consequence, considere que la lutte anti-imperialiste releve de l’accessoire, pour ne pas dire de la charite, se prive du moyen d’agir pour la transformation de la realite. Est-il d’ailleurs vraiment marxiste ?

Mais affirmer d’un autre cote que l’analyse de l’accumulation a l’echelle mondiale doit etre conduite a l’echelle mondiale et non a partir de la seule peripherie seulement, c’est exprimer un souhait qui restera vain tant qu’on n’aura pas abandonne radicalement la vision occidentalocentrique qui fait deriver, au mepris de toute dialectique, les transformations de la peripherie de celles du centre. Etant donne que quatre-vingt-dix-neuf pour cent des analyses de l’accumulation ignorent le champ mondial pour se fixer exclusivement sur les centres — comme quatre-vingt-dix-neuf pour cent des analyses de la transition au capitalisme ignorent la peripherie mercantiliste — et que ces analyses sont, non seulement incompletes mais procedent d’une erreur fondamentale, il faut bien commencer par l’autre bout. Ainsi creera-t-on les conditions d’une analyse d’ensemble correcte.

a - La liberation nationale et le socialisme

1)    Nous aborderons donc le probleme sous l’angle le plus large, celui du debat marxiste sur l’imperialisme, pour tenter de definir la strategie de la transformation socialiste a l’echelle mondiale et les rapports entre les differentes forces politiques et sociales qui reuvrent a des degres differents, au sein de contextes differents, dans cette direction. Il existe sur ce point deux visions fondamentalement differentes. Chacun se pretend marxiste et pretend que l’autre ne l’est pas.

2)    La premiere considere que l’imperialisme constitue une coupure qualitative essentielle dans l’histoire du capitalisme : celle qui resulte, a la

fin du xixe siecle, du passage du capitalisme classique concurrentiel (pour lui donner un nom, mais sans illusions sur la nature de cette concurrence) au capitalisme imperialiste. Selon qu’on est avant et apres l’imperialisme, tous les problemes se posent d’une maniere differente.

L’imperialisme n’est pas seulement, ni meme principalement, une transformation de type economique a l’interieur des centres imperialistes, un passage du quantitatif au qualitatif dans la centralisation, la concentration du capital, reperee, avant meme les revolutionnaires comme Lenine, par les social-democrates. Certes, il y a maintenant centralisation, concentration, monopoles, interpenetration du capital bancaire et du capital industriels, etc., et, concomitamment, soumission a ces imperialismes de l’ensemble des societes non capitalistes. Mais les racines de cette soumission sont anterieures et le capitalisme n’a pas attendu la fin

du xixe siecle pour acquerir un caractere mondial. L’accumulation primitive elle-meme, avant la revolution industrielle, a deja une telle dimension. La manifestation de ces phenomenes politiques, et meme le phenomene colonial, dans certaines regions et sous certains aspects, sont anterieurs a l’imperialisme.

Si celui-ci constitue neanmoins une coupure qualitative, c’est parce que la centralisation-concentration du capital des monopoles fait apparaitre la possibilite d’exporter le mode de production capitaliste par l’investissement de ce capital a l’exterieur des centres d’origine. L’implantation de segments du processus productif en dehors de la nation d’origine, dans des conditions sociales tres differentes, devient possible. Les processus d’integration et de soumission des societes a mode de production d’origine precapitaliste prennent ainsi une dimension tout a fait nouvelle et, meme si cette implantation est quantitativement encore sporadique, elle est determinante. Plus tard, l’expansion a l’echelle mondiale du capitalisme dans la phase imperialiste provoque des transformations fondamentales. C’est la le point crucial du debat : celui de la place des differentes classes sociales au centre et a la peripherie. On ne peut saisir ces transformations dans les rapports entre les classes sociales, a l’interieur du centre, de la peripherie et a l’echelle mondiale, et la place des differentes classes sociales dans la lutte des classes, en isolant les pays, qu’ils soient imperialistes ou domines par l’imperialisme; on ne peut les saisir que dans leurs rapports mondiaux, dans une strategie globale.

Certes, la contradiction fondamentale du mode de production capitaliste, et donc du systeme capitaliste mondial, est celle qui oppose la bourgeoisie et le proletariat. Mais, une fois qu’on a enonce cette banalite, on n’a en rien decide de la strategie, c’est-a-dire des rapports entre les differents proletariats, entre les differentes bourgeoisies et les autres classes — notamment, a la peripherie, en relation avec les modes de production precapitalistes — soumis a l’imperialisme, et la fagon dont ils se situent, dans une strategie revolutionnaire d’ensemble, les uns par rapport aux autres.

Avec l’entree du capitalisme dans la phase imperialiste, il se produit des transformations importantes que l’on peut resumer comme suit.

Le centre de gravite de l’exploitation capitaliste se deplace, en relation avec le fait que la masse relative de la plus-value centralisee au profit des monopoles des pays imperialistes grandit, en termes relatifs et absolus. Elle provient de plus en plus de l’exploitation des peuples de la peripherie. Il s’agit soit d’une plus-value generee directement par le proletariat de la peripherie, soit, et c’est plus important encore en volume, de surplus genere dans des modes de production varies, provenant de classes exploitees, circulant a travers des intermediates locaux sous des formes particulieres, transformes en plus-value au benefice des monopoles par la soumission formelle de ces modes de production precapitalistes paysans, feodaux, etc., et l’exploitation de larges masses paysannes.

Que le centre de gravite se deplace de cette maniere ne resulte pas de la mesure quantitative de la masse de la plus-value generee ici ou la et a l’interieur de l’ensemble du systeme; sur le plan quantitatif, la masse de la plus-value reste surtout generee au centre; mais le centre de gravite, le point sensible, se deplace vers l’exploitation de la peripherie.

Le capitalisme des monopoles a ainsi fourni une base objective a l’hegemonie de la social-democratie dans les classes ouvrieres de

l’Occident. Cette hegemonie, visible et indiscutable dans la IIe Internationale, est denoncee par Lenine, en relation precisement avec le phenomene imperialiste. Complementairement, l’extension du capitalisme imperialiste a l’echelle de la planete tarit la voie d’expansion du capitalisme par des revolutions bourgeoises dans les pays arrieres.

La bourgeoisie ne se developpe plus a la periphery que dans le sillage de l’imperialisme et n’est plus capable de mener une revolution bourgeoise plus ou moins radicale. Ce qui ne signifie evidemment pas que le capitalisme ne se developpe plus; il se developpe, mais dans le cadre imperialiste. Et, au contraire, le mouvement paysan qui, historiquement, a ete au centre partie integrante de la revolution bourgeoise, devient partie de la revolution socialiste. Les revendications paysannes ne peuvent donc pas conduire a des revolutions bourgeoises, mais doivent, objectivement, s’integrer a la revolution socialiste a l’echelle mondiale. Ce qui ne veut pas dire qu’elles y conduisent automatiquement : il faut pour cela qu’il existe une direction proletarienne et une perspective dans ce sens. Autrement dit, le developpement du capitalisme a la peripherie, dans le sillage de l’imperialisme, et la montee du mouvement de liberation nationale, ne s’inscrivent pas dans la perspective de developpement du capitalisme et de la bourgeoisie, mais dans la perspective de sa crise.

Pour definir les grands camps des forces sociales et determiner ensuite ce qui est principal et secondaire selon cette these, il ne suffit pas de rappeler que du cote des forces du socialisme il y a les proletariats du centre (meme s’il y a hegemonie de la social-democratie) et de la peripherie et, pour simplifier, la paysannerie exploitee de la peripherie, et que de l’autre cote, dans le camp des forces du capitalisme, il y a le capital des monopoles et toutes les bourgeoisies dependantes et les classes exploiteuses alliees de la peripherie. Car, dans cette alliance de classes a l’echelle internationale, le fer de lance des forces du socialisme s’est deplace du proletariat de l’Occident vers les noyaux proletaries de la peripherie, en rapport avec le phenomene imperialiste, d’ou l’hegemonie social-democrate dans le proletariat de l’Occident et la possibilite d’une alliance revolutionnaire ouvriers-paysans dans la peripherie.

L’argument de ceux qui rappellent constamment la contradiction fondamentale bourgeoisie/proletariat ne fait guere avancer le debat; le proletariat existe a l’echelle mondiale ici et la. Or, a un moment donne de l’histoire, certains secteurs du proletariat sont plus avances que d’autres. Les citations a coups de Marx ne permettent pas d’expliquer cette situation, puisque le phenomene imperialiste lui est posterieur; a coups de Lenine, peut-etre un peu plus, puisque c’est Lenine qui a analyse le premier d’une fagon decisive l’imperialisme. Mais enfin, il est mort en 1924; le systeme a continue, les luttes se sont developpees, les choses se sont transformees et Lenine etait d’abord preoccupe par la lutte a

l’interieur de la IIe Internationale contre le revisionnisme et la preparation de la revolution russe; il l’a situe dans un cadre correct, qui est celui de l’imperialisme, mais il n’a pas donne de reponse a tout ce qui s’est passe de son temps, et a fortiori apres.

En fait, il apparait que les revolutions socialistes n’ont eu lieu qu’a la peripherie du systeme (Chine, Vietnam, Coree, Cambodge, Laos, Cuba), qu’en depit du developpement du capitalisme a la peripherie et de l’absence de perspectives immediates les masses populaires ouvrieres et paysannes y sont rarement placees sous la domination ideologique de la bourgeoisie et de l’imperialisme et que, de ce fait, le potentiel revolutionnaire y est enorme. Il y a donc de fortes chances que le mouvement continue dans le meme sens. Par contre, les classes ouvrieres d’Occident sont, jusqu’a present, dominees par l’hegemonie social-democrate ou revisionniste (qui devient de plus en plus clairement la meme), ce qui n’empeche ni des luttes de classes ni des combats parfois violents, mais privent ceux-ci de la perspective socialiste.

Cependant, ces faits peuvent toujours etre discutes, dans la mesure ou ce qui est vrai un jour ne l’est pas necessairement le lendemain; en outre, les revolutions dites socialistes dans la peripherie posent une serie de problemes apres leur realisation : il ne s’agit pas d’une transition paisible, sans probleme, vers le communisme, c’est-a-dire vers l’abolition des classes sociales, des rapports marchands, de la division du travail, etc. L’objectif final est lointain, extremement lointain encore. Tous les arguments, qu’il s’agisse de citations de Marx ou de Lenine, ou les faits memes, laissent le debat ouvert : il faut observer les luttes reelles, analyser comment elles s’articulent et leur signification.

Evitons ici un malentendu supplementaire : il n’existe aucune prophetie possible sur le deroulement de l’histoire. Nous devons simplement mettre l’accent sur un rapport dialectique entre les luttes au centre et celles de la peripherie. Dans telle situation datee, lesquelles sont les principales, lesquelles sont secondaires ? Autrement dit, quelles luttes agissent qualitativement sur les autres ?

Dans la mesure ou l’imperialisme peut reporter Sexploitation sur la

Peripherie, peut approfondir cette exploitation, il acquiert les moyens objectifs de renforcer l’ideologie social-democrate au centre et, par consequent, il parvient a diviser la classe ouvriere, a lui enlever sa perspective politique autonome et a integrer ses luttes dans des projets qu’il continue a maitriser.

Dans la mesure ou la peripherie resiste, a des degres divers — le plus avance etant la liberation, c’est-a-dire la sortie du systeme imperialiste —, dans la mesure ou le mouvement de liberation nationale dirige par le proletariat s’etend, entrainant la grande masse des paysans exploites, il existe la possibilite d’une coupure qualitative. Celle-ci n’est pas le socialisme, mais seulement une coupure vers le socialisme, le point final a l’exploitation imperialiste mais pas necessairement au developpement des forces capitalistes autochtones. C’est la la signification du degre maximal de resistance a l’exploitation imperialiste. Le degre minimal est celui des bourgeoisies dependantes qui, dans une conjoncture donnee, dirigent le mouvement de liberation nationale et, de facto, a travers ces luttes, arrachent un nouveau partage plus favorable pour elles qui, par la meme, limite les profits du capital des monopoles. Dans la mesure donc ou la peripherie resiste, a ces degres divers, le capital imperialiste est oblige de reporter la contradiction a l’interieur des metropoles, reduisant par consequent la base objective de la social-democratie et renforgant les tendances a une reprise revolutionnaire.

Jusqu’a present (c’est-a-dire entre 1870 et 1979), la tendance principale a ete que les luttes de liberation nationale, a des degres divers — du plus fort, prise en main par le proletariat et rupture avec l’imperialisme, au plus faible, direction par la bourgeoisie arrachant des concessions recuperees par le reajustement du systeme imperialiste —, sont le moteur de l’histoire contemporaine. Ainsi, l’elargissement ou le retrecissement de la base objective de la social-democratie au centre a dependu pour l’essentiel de ces luttes de liberation a l’echelle d’un siecle, avec des hauts et des bas, bien entendu, puisque ces resistances et ces luttes ne se sont pas developpees de fagon lineaire, mais en accumulant tantot des victoires, tantot des defaites, que celles-ci soient dirigees par le proletariat ou par la bourgeoisie.

3) Le mouvement de liberation nationale est-il ce que nous affirmons : le moteur de l’histoire et la force principale d’emergence du socialisme ? Si

l’on reduit ce mouvement a celui de la lutte pour l’independance nationale politique de l’Asie et de l’Afrique, on est tente de conclure qu’il n’occupe qu’une phase relativement breve de l’histoire contemporaine : de 1945 a 1965-70, peut-etre. Mais retournons donc au deroulement de l’histoire contemporaine. Depuis 1880, le fait imperialiste commande tous les evenements importants, pese sur tous les affrontements et en determine les solutions. Simultanement, depuis 1880, la lutte de liberation nationale ne cesse de s’amplifier.

Dans une premiere phase, de 1880 a 1914, cette lutte n’est pas encore le moteur immediat de l’histoire; mais la revolte des classes ouvrieres au centre du systeme a cesse de l’etre. C’est pourquoi cette phase est l’age d’or de l’imperialisme. Les classes ouvrieres sont deja subordonnees a leurs bourgeoisies imperialistes et, s’il faudra attendre 1914 pour en

mesurer la portee, la IIe Internationale apparait bien, avec le recul du temps, comme l’instrument de cette subordination. Les mouvements de liberation commencent seulement a se constituer, mais ils ne sont pas encore sortis de l’age precapitaliste; ils se proposent plus de resister a l’agression que de liberer quoi que ce soit. C’est pourquoi, durant cette phase, les contradictions inter-imperialistes occupent le devant de la scene : c’est la Belle Epoque ou la diplomatie des Puissances est le moteur immediat de l’histoire. Cette phase se clot par la Grande Guerre, la revolution russe, le mouvement du 4 mai en Chine, Kemal Ataturk, le Wafd egyptien et le Congres indien.

De 1918 a 1945, le devant de la scene n’est plus occupe exclusivement par les contradictions inter-imperialistes, qui subsistent pourtant encore et opposent vainqueurs et vaincus de 1918. Parallelement, l’epoque voit la montee de la revolution russe, puis ses pietinements et ses reculs, la montee de la revolution chinoise, la montee des mouvements de liberation sur les trois continents : populisme latino-americain, revoltes et revolutions independantistes modernes reprimees en Asie et en Afrique. Ce complexe des forces montantes accuse a nouveau les contradictions internes dans les centres et les crises d’apres la premiere guerre, puis de 1930, mettent en lumiere ces contradictions sociales. La periode se clot par la seconde guerre mondiale, qui marque la fin de la remontee du mouvement ouvrier occidental, tandis que se poursuit le developpement des autres forces, celles de l’Union sovietique comme celles de la liberation nationale.

A partir de 1945 s’ouvre une troisieme periode, au cours de laquelle s’affirme la predominance du mouvement de liberation nationale. Les contradictions inter-imperialistes sont attenuees par l’hegemonie americaine, au point que la these economiste du super-imperialisme parait confirmee : l’Etat deviendrait l’instrument passif des multinationals, qui fagonneraient le monde a leur image. On constate en meme temps que le mouvement ouvrier occidental ne se remet pas de la defaite des annees 30 et 40 : avec le recul du temps, il apparait tout autant subordonne qu’il l’etait avant 1914. L’Union sovietique, confinee dans les frontieres de la zone d’influence, n’apparait sur la scene mondiale qu’en relation avec le mouvement de liberation; c’est par les alliances qu’elle noue avec ce mouvement qu’elle prend une dimension mondiale. Pendant ce quart de siecle, la liberation nationale s’acheve en Asie orientale et a Cuba en ouvrant des transitions socialistes possibles, tandis qu’ailleurs le mouvement atteint son premier objectif, l’independance politique, sans avoir ouvert de telles transitions.

L’achevement de cette phase va-t-il mettre un terme au mouvement de liberation nationale et a ses potentialites de transformation socialiste ? C’est la these de Gerard Chaliand (77e-1). Elle semble confirmee par les faits immediats des dernieres annees. Et pourtant elle est fausse, car elle reduit l’objectif de la liberation nationale a l’independance. Or celle-ci ne resout pas les contradictions du capitalisme peripherique. Sans doute cree-t-elle des conditions nouvelles, d’ou la pause. Le depassement de la phase du capitalisme peripherique embryonnaire, « le mode de production colonial », comme l’appelle Rey (10-6, 73b-1), par la reproduction spontanee du capitalisme dependant (le mode de production neocolonial), a travers l’hegemonie de la bourgeoisie locale et par les mecanismes economiques memes du systeme capitaliste, modifie la nature des objectifs, les methodes de lutte et le dispositif des camps. Chaliand propose donc de considerer close l’ere du mouvement de liberation et d’appeler lutte interne des classes l’epoque qui s’ouvre dans le tiers monde. Or, cette lutte des classes continue en realite a operer dans le cadre de la liberation nationale, qui reste inachevee. Les bourgeoisies du tiers monde tentent de poursuivre cette lutte en en conservant la direction. Les classes populaires ne doivent pas plus l’ignorer qu’elles ne devaient ignorer hier l’objectif de l’independance. Grace a l’autonomie de leur mouvement, elles doivent imposer leur direction et ouvrir par ce moyen la transition socialiste. Oui, la liberation nationale continue a occuper le devant de la scene. L’histoire, et l’histoire seulement — pas la theorie —, dira si elle coincidera avec une nouvelle emergence du mouvement ouvrier en Occident.

4) Replaces dans ce cadre, qui est celui de la revolution ininterrompue et par etapes, les debats concernant la strategie de la nouvelle phase de liberation nationale prennent une portee pratique. Ce sont la des debats veritables a l’interieur du mouvement et de la lutte, dont la portee reelle tranche avec la gratuite des theories. Le caractere contradictoire de la liberation nationale s’exprime dans cette double realite que d’une part chaque victoire partielle cree les conditions d’un nouvel approfondissement du developpement du capitalisme, mais que d’autre part ce developpement, etant celui du capitalisme peripherique dependant, n’attenue pas les contradictions entre les masses populaires, l’imperialisme et ses allies, mais au contraire les aggrave.

Est-il possible que ce mouvement se prolonge indefiniment, franchissant des etapes successives sans que jamais s’opere la rupture qualitative qui ouvre la transition socialiste ? Dans ce cas, n’arrivera-t-on pas finalement a l’achevement du processus de developpement capitaliste, c’est-a-dire a la disparition de la contradiction centre/peripherie ? Marx avait exprime cette possibilite que l’Europe, grosse de la revolution socialiste, ait a faire face au capitalisme montant sorti de ce « petit coin du monde ». Mais il ecrivait cela avant l’imperialisme et faisait donc la double supposition de la poursuite de la radicalisation du mouvement ouvrier europeen et du caractere non dependant du developpement capitaliste en Asie.

Depuis, l’hypothese d’un developpement acheve du capitalisme dans les peripheries soumises a l’imperialisme ne s’est pas realisee. Et la nouvelle phase de l’imperialisme qui se dessine, fondee sur les forces sociales reelles du capitalisme contemporain, ne va pas dans la direction d’un achevement du capitalisme (l’objectif d’independance economique proclame par les bourgeoisies du tiers monde ne peut en effet pas etre atteint par les strategies qu’elles proposent), mais prolonge la ligne du developpement dependant, inacheve.

Bien entendu, si les forces populaires n’agissent pas a la peripherie et si done le processus se poursuivait au-dela de cette nouvelle phase, c’est-a-dire si le capitalisme survit encore, disons mille ans, il finira bien par trouver une solution a ses contradictions. Dans cette hypothese de science-fiction, l’imperialisme aurait disparu, ayant epuise son role historique, qui aurait ete de transferer le capitalisme de ce « petit coin d’Europe » a l’ensemble du monde. L’imperialisme n’aurait pas ete le stade supreme du capitalisme, mais seulement une modalite transitoire de son deploiement. Meme dans cette hypothese, dont l’examen est sans interet politique, la question du communisme resterait posee. Dans un monde totalement homogeneise, ou le capitalisme aurait deja supprime nations et inegalites nationales, la lutte des classes acquerait enfin la purete revee par certains. A moins que dans ce monde de science-fiction il ne soit deja trop tard, que le regime de l’« Homme unidimensionnel » n’y rende caduques les lois decouvertes par le materialisme historique. Si l’on s’autorise un cadre de raisonnement de cette nature, il faut aller jusqu’au bout, abandonner le terrain solide des luttes effectives entre des forces reelles operant dans un monde non moins reel, pour combiner librement toutes les hypotheses.

5) Que la contradiction centre/peripherie continue a etre l’aspect principal par lequel se manifeste l’ensemble des contradictions (fondamentales et secondaires) du systeme, nous en voulons pour preuve supplementaire la crise actuelle. On constate en effet qu’une serie de victoires des mouvements de liberation nationale a caracterise la derniere phase; les plus spectaculaires ont ete celles des peuples d’Asie orientale; plus modestes sont celles des bourgeoisies du petrole, qui ont obtenu un nouveau partage des profits en utilisant les contradictions inter-imperialistes a un moment donne. Tout cela a joue un role decisif dans la crise actuelle de l’imperialisme, c’est-a-dire dans l’obligation ou il est de se reajuster a cette resistance de la peripherie.

La consequence en est, de fagon evidente, une recrudescence des luttes au centre, que ce soit sur le plan ideologique ou economique, car la liaison entre les deux reste tres forte. Sans la revolution culturelle chinoise, on comprendrait mal beaucoup des choses qui se passent en Occident. La critique du revisionnisme y est nee de petits groupes en liaison avec les luttes anti-imperialistes (Algerie, Vietnam, Palestine); meme a ce niveau, l’effet est decisif.

A un autre niveau, la resistance victorieuse de la peripherie a entraine l’acceleration de la chute du taux de profit au centre, partiellement masquee par les mecanismes de la « stagflation », le report de la contradiction sur les classes ouvrieres du centre, la tentative d’une politique economique destinee a recreer la, au moins partiellement, une armee de reserve. Simultanement, l’imperialisme a choisi de resserrer les rangs : les bourgeoisies imperialistes des metropoles subalternes se rangent a nouveau sous la direction de la fraction dominante americaine, pour constituer un front commun qui leur permette de limiter au maximum les victoires des mouvements de liberation nationale de la peripherie et d’attenuer ainsi les contradictions au centre. L’echec tant de

la 4e conference de la CNUCED que du « dialogue Nord-Sud » temoignent de ce refus de l’imperialisme de faire des concessions aux bourgeoisies de la peripherie.

Si, sur un siecle, la tendance principale a fait apparaitre la lutte de liberation nationale comme le moteur de l’histoire, si toutes les luttes, y compris au centre, se sont determinees par rapport a cette lutte principale dans le systeme capitaliste mondial, il faut cependant rappeler qu’une lutte a cette echelle ne doit pas etre comprise comme une juxtaposition de luttes de classes dans des pays differents, des modes de production differents, qui n’entretiendraient que des relations episodiques ou de hasard. Elles sont organisees par rapport a une alliance des classes a l’echelle mondiale, et par rapport a la position des differentes fractions de classes dans cette alliance mondiale qui determine quelles sont les fractions d’avant-garde, le gros des troupes, l’ennemi principal, etc.

6) Mais il existe une seconde vision, diametralement opposee, affirmant que la contradiction qui oppose le proletariat a la bourgeoisie au centre du systeme demeure la contradiction principale du systeme tout entier. Cette these considere aussi que le mouvement de liberation nationale fait partie integrante de la revolution mondiale bourgeoise. Predominante non

seulement ouvertement dans les courants ouvriers issus de la IIe Internationale mais aussi dans ceux du communisme revisionniste et meme, implicitement, dans l’opposition de gauche en Occident, elle temoigne de l’hegemonie ideologique social-democrate. C’est grace a

cette these que la IIe Internationale justifiait son ralliement a l’ideologie imperialiste. On aurait pu croire que Lenine en avait debarrasse les mouvements situes a gauche de la social-democratie. Pas du tout. Ses adeptes continueront de s’obnubiler sur le developpement du capitalisme a la peripherie. Mais ils ne voient pas — puisque leur these nie l’imperialisme — qu’il s’agit d’un capitalisme dependant, incapable de realiser l’objectif de la liberation nationale, laissant par consequent intactes toutes les potentialites d’une revolution socialiste. En revanche, s’agissant de l’hegemonie social-democrate en Occident, ils persisteront a l’attribuer a des facteurs subjectifs et circonstanciels. C’est pourquoi nous pretendons que cette seconde vision developpe une variante de l’ideologie imperialiste.

7) L’opposition entre ces deux visions se retrouve naturellement toujours et partout, ouverte ou en filigrane. A cet egard, le debat concernant l’echange inegal a ete revelateur, ou l’on a vu les positions se cristalliser progressivement en fonction des appartenances ideologiques a chacun des deux camps. Mais un autre exemple de l’opposition des deux visions est celui des debats concernant la crise actuelle. Les uns y voient en premier lieu une crise de l’imperialisme, c’est-a-dire de la division internationale du travail et des alliances de classes mondiales qui la commandent; on en situe l’origine dans les reculs de l’imperialisme en Orient, qui ont modifie les conditions objectives de la lutte des classes aux centres comme ils ont modifie le cadre objectif des contradictions inter-imperialistes. Les autres refusent de qualifier la crise de crise de l’imperialisme; ils assurent que ce sont les luttes de classes au centre qui en sont la cause fondamentale et que ce sont ces luttes qui determinent le cadre objectif de l’accumulation a l’echelle mondiale.

b - A propos, encore, de l’occidentalocentrisme

1) L’occidentalocentrisme est le produit du capitalisme, et particulierement de sa phase imperialiste, a partir de laquelle il penetre le mouvement ouvrier et souvent jusqu’a la pensee qui se reclame du marxisme. Sa manifestation immediate est l’absence d’interet pour les societes non occidentales, laquelle implique fatalement une grave deformation de l’histoire de l’Occident lui-meme. Car l’Occident ne peut pas se comprendre sans l’Orient, pas plus hier, a l’epoque mercantiliste, qu’aujourd’hui, a l’epoque imperialiste. Les benefices (plein emploi, croissance des salaires reels, etc.) que les peuples d’Occident tirent, dans le cadre imperialiste, de l’exploitation de la peripherie constituent la base objective de la penetration de l’occidentalocentrisme dans le mouvement ouvrier, permettant ainsi a l’ideologie de la bourgeoisie de devenir celle de toute la societe, ce qu’elle n’etait encore qu’a moitie avant l’imperialisme.

Cette situation aura des effets importants au plan de la transition socialiste dans les centres developpes. Les peuples de l’Occident seront-ils disposes a renoncer a l’imperialisme et a affronter une longue transition necessaire avant que les avantages de leur liberation du capitalisme ne compensent les difficultes de la reconversion, s’ils ne sont pas contraints a celle-ci par la liberation de la peripherie ? Le moins qu’on puisse dire est que l’occidentalocentrisme a pour effet de cacher cette realite cruelle aux peuples d’Occident. C’est precisement la que les bourgeoisies imperialistes attendent la gauche.

Un exemple : les nations occidentales sont de plus en plus des nations de petites bourgeoisies, au sens que s’y concentrent les couches medianes dont les fonctions ne se comprennent qu’a l’echelle du fonctionnement du systeme mondial, comme l’a montre Poulantzas (81 a-1). L’hypertrophie du tertiaire devenu improductif, la concentration possible du quaternaire dans l’hypothese d’une nouvelle division international releguant certaines industries a la peripherie, ont pour contrepartie la concentration de la generation de la plus-value a la peripherie, par l’exploitation directe a des taux de la plus-value plus eleves, la domination formelle sur les secteurs precapitalistes, le pillage des ressources naturelles, etc. La reconversion que la transition socialiste impliquerait pour les societes centrales creera, dans ces conditions, des difficultes considerables.

Les ambiguites des mouvements populaires et ouvriers d’Occident trahissent le recul opportuniste devant ces problemes. On le voit bien aujourd’hui, a propos de la bataille que les pays du tiers monde livrent pour leur independance economique et le relevement des prix des matieres premieres. La question est en effet de savoir qui supportera en definitive les surprofits des monopoles : les classes ouvrieres des centres ou les peuples (y compris les bourgeoisies) des peripheries ? Or, on voit la gauche occidentale se ranger sans hesiter aux cotes de l’imperialisme : invoquer un alibi (le fait que cette bataille est conduite par les Etats, donc les bourgeoisies, du tiers monde) pour eluder sa responsabilite. La bourgeoisie a su parfaitement exploiter cette faiblesse; elle est parvenue sans difficulty a expliquer que les nations d’Occident avaient droit aux richesses naturelles du tiers monde et que les peuples des pays avances ne devaient pas faire les frais des appetits des cheikhs et des bureaucrates de la peripherie. A court terme deja, ce theme imperialiste a donne quelques longueurs d’avance a la droite, comme en temoignent les changements de regime recents en Europe. Et une fraction importante de l’extreme-gauche suit, precedes par les dirigeants des pays de l’Est europeen.

2) L’occidentalocentrisme impose une deformation systematique du marxisme. D’un instrument revolutionnaire d’action, il est parvenu, a force de rigidite dogmatique, a faire presque une discipline academique.

Le debat sur l’echange inegal nous a convaincu que l’invocation de la « preeminence de la production sur la circulation » n’est en fait qu’un alibi ideologique. Car, enfin, ce debat a conduit a formuler les problemes en termes de rapports de production, de generation du surplus a l’echelle mondiale et de circulation mondiale du surplus commandee par les rapports de production capitalistes fonctionnant a l’echelle mondiale. C’est dans ces termes qu’on est parvenu a etablir que les taux de plus-value plus eleves a la peripherie, la plus-value absolue obtenue a travers la domination formelle, les rentes reduites ou supprimees, sont masques derriere les apparences des « prix relatifs ». Il s’agit bien de generation de surplus et, en meme temps, de la distribution qui decoule du processus meme de sa generation. Celle-ci a son tour commande les formes de l’accumulation : l’hypertrophie improductive a un pole, la loi absolue de la pauperisation a l’autre.

L’argument anticirculationiste cache donc une intention, qui est de refuser d’analyser la generation du surplus a l’echelle mondiale pour la confiner aux seuls centres. Parce qu’on a decrete a priori que la plus-value est produite seulement dans les centres et qu’il serait genant qu’elle le soit de plus en plus a la peripherie. Kay (72c-4) non seulement ignore les arguments du debat mais avoue naivement son intention : prouver que la misere du tiers monde est due au fait qu’elle n’est pas trop, mais pas assez exploitee par le capital. La loi de l’accumulation capitaliste, c’est l’elevation du niveau de vie des masses. La preuve : l’histoire de l’Occident. Preuve supplementaire : la misere de la peripherie. Kay ne se pose jamais la question de savoir si la misere du tiers monde et l’opulence de l’Occident n’entretiendraient pas quelque relation. La stabilite relative de la part des salaires dans le revenu national en Occident signifie au moins que le taux de la plus-value y est constant, en depit de l’hypertrophie des fonctions improductives, qui ne generent pas de plus-value mais la redistribuent. A la peripherie, en revanche, le taux et la masse de la plus-value sont toujours croissants : la croissance de la productivite y est beaucoup plus rapide que celle de la remuneration du travail. Cet enorme fait aveuglant, qu’on pourrait croire etre devenu une evidence depuis Lenine, echappe totalement a notre marxiste dont la these — qui ramene a Rostow, ignorant que sous-developpement et developpement sont les deux faces de la meme medaille — serait fort apprecie par la Fondation Ford.

A l’oppose, Michalet (71a-3), dont la problematique est la notre (le systeme mondial envisage d’emblee comme cadre de la generation de la plus-value), ecrit que la multinationalisation « permet la reproduction elargie par le deplacement du lieu d’exploitation vers des zones a taux de plus-value plus eleves avec une composition organique identique », « s’accompagne d’une structure integree des spheres de la production et de la circulation sur une base mondiale », ou « ne signifie pas la disparition des lois immanentes du capitalisme mais bientot plutot leur etalement a l’echelle mondiale ».

3) Ayant une fois pour toutes renonce a s’interesser au vrai champ d’operation du capitalisme, le systeme mondial, les marxistes occidentalocentriques sont contraints de se refugier dans la marxologie. Le theoricisme et les lectures du Capital se substituent a l’analyse de la realite. Comme dit Michel Beaud (82-15), on risque de faire indefiniment « deriver la theorie de la theorie ». Les super-specialisations, contraires a l’esprit du marxisme, flattent les tendances academiques. Politiquement, on est toujours revisionniste de droite ou de gauche; on est toujours insensible au probleme de l’imperialisme, reserve a la specialite d’autres chercheurs, ou aux acces de fievre tiers-mondiste, ou a l’attrait de l’exotisme ethnographique, ou a l’epanchement de l’esprit charitable. Quand on est historien dans cet esprit, on est preoccupe d’illustrer l’histoire merveilleuse de l’Occident, et de prouver « scientifiquement » que seule l’Europe pouvait faire progresser l’Humanite. Quelle meilleure preuve que l’ideologie de la classe dominante est devenue l’ideologie de la societe !

4) Rien ne predisposait la pensee de Marx a une telle mesaventure. Marx n’avait jamais voulu etre pris pour un prophete. Heureusement, il ne fut qu’un homme, qui ne se situait ni hors de l’espace ni hors du temps. Mais l’esprit religieux des hommes a libere son heritage de cette modestie. On a oublie qu’il n’avait fait que jeter les fondements du materialisme historique et decouvert les lois essentielles du capitalisme. On a oublie qu’il n’avait pas eu d’autres ambitions, notamment pas celle de priver ses successeurs de faire avancer la lutte dans des conditions nouvelles qu’il ne se souciait guere d’imaginer a l’avance. Les meilleurs de ses successeurs, Lenine et Mao, ne s’en sont du reste pas prives.

Pour nous, l’apport du leninisme consiste avant tout dans son application de la methode marxiste aux conditions de l’epoque imperialiste nouvelle. Ce

cadre a permis a Lenine d’analyser correctement le revisionnisme de la IIe Internationale, en le rapportant a sa base objective et, a partir de la, de formuler la strategie de la revolution socialiste dans les conditions nouvelles du developpement inegal au sein du systeme imperialiste. Quant a l’apport du maoisme, il consiste avant tout dans l’utilisation de la methode marxiste pour l’analyse des conditions de la lutte des classes dans la periode de transition.

Marx est apparu entre 1840 et 1880, c’est-a-dire au moment ou la revolution bourgeoise se generalise a l’Europe, sort de son petit coin anglais d’origine. Au moment ou cet essor marque la fin de la premiere accumulation primitive et met un terme au role que la peripherie ancienne y a joue. Au moment ou cette premiere soumission a deja bloque et meme fait reculer l’Amerique latine, l’Asie et l’Afrique par ses genocides d’Amerindiens, sa traite negriere, ses destructions de l’industrie indienne, egyptienne, son trafic d’opium impose a la Chine, etc. Au moment ou le mouvement de redemarrage de ces continents n’a pas encore repris, sous l’effet de leur integration comme peripherie de l’epoque imperialiste. Vouloir ignorer cela, pour transformer des morceaux de phrases, souvent tirees de brouillons que Marx n’a pas juge utile de publier, en autant de « revelations », c’est, en verite, lui infliger la pire des trahisons : l’embaumement.

II - La nature contradictoire de la transition socialiste

1) L’experience sovietique nous apprend que la transition socialiste ne conduit pas necessairement au communisme. Le debat concernant la nature et les lois de la societe sovietique est maintenant ouvert. Nous avons soutenu que cette societe de classes etait d’un type nouveau, du fait que la centralisation etatique du capital constitue un saut qualitatif. Elle supprime certaines des lois essentielles du capitalisme, decoulant de la parcellisation de son controle, et particulierement la dominance de l’instance economique, qui lui est liee. Elle etablit donc de nouveaux rapports entre la base economique et la superstructure, a nouveau dominante. C’est pourquoi on a cru utile de donner un nom a ce nouveau mode de classe. Les maoistes chinois le qualifient de capitalisme monopoliste d’Etat et sa classe dirigeante de bourgeoisie monopoliste d’Etat, en reservant a l’Occident le qualificatif de capitalisme monopoliste tout court. Ils parlent, sur cette base, de « restauration du capitalisme ».

Mais l’experience sovietique n’est pas isolee. La revendication politique exprimee par les courants qui dominent la classe ouvriere d’Occident est analogue : le glissement progressif au mode etatique, ou au capitalisme monopoliste d’Etat (au sens veritable, non a celui utilise par les partis revisionnistes). Les social-democrates serieux, par exemple en Suede, ne s’en cachent pas : la propriete d’Etat doit succeder a la propriete parcellisee du capital. Les partis communistes occidentaux sont du meme avis. Ainsi que les trotskistes. Tous partagent le meme culte de la determination unilaterale par les forces productives. Le courant autogestionnaire, lui, n’a pas encore repondu a la serie des questions fondamentales qu’une transition socialiste poserait en Occident. Enfin, l’experience des pays du tiers monde semble aussi montrer que, lorsque la bourgeoisie est une classe montante, c’est toujours sous la forme d’une bourgeoisie d’Etat.

Doit-on tirer de ces rapprochements la conclusion que le mode etatique serait un successeur possible du capitalisme ? Dans ce cas, les luttes de classes opposant exploites a exploiteurs opereraient au benefice d’un troisieme larron, une nouvelle classe en formation, emergeant en partie du sein meme de la classe exploitee (bureaucraties de partis et d’organisations, cadres techniques de l’aristocratie ouvriere, etc.), en partie parallelement a elle (technocrates).

2) L’apport specifique du maoisme au marxisme-leniniste consiste a avoir developpe la theorie des contradictions de la transition. Cet apport, certes, a ete formule dans les conditions specifiques de la Chine, mais a partir aussi d’une ^appreciation de l’histoire sovietique, qui sortait de l’orniere de la fausse theorie de la degenerescence attribuee par le trotskisme au caractere paysan de la Russie. En definissant positivement les conditions necessaries de l’alliance ouvriere-paysanne, le maoisme a une portee universelle.

Cette portee depasse certainement les seules experiences a venir de transition a partir du capitalisme peripherique. Car les problemes de la transition eventuelle a partir du capitalisme central ne seront ni moins serieux ni fondamentalement differents. Les memes forces qui operent en direction d’une restauration ou de l’emergence du mode etatique au sein des situations peripheriques agiront au sein des situations centrales : elles trouvent leur origine dans la perpetuation des rapports marchands, de l’infrastructure de l’organisation technique et de la division du travail au cours de la transition. Sans parler des difficultes specifiques de la transition centrale en rapport avec la liquidation de l’imperialisme. Mais il n’existe encore aucune experience sociale de cette transition, la Commune de Paris n’ayant pas eu le temps de s’y confronter. Aussi limiterons-nous nos observations de la transition peripherique.

3) Nous ne reviendrons pas sur la discussion du sens a donner au developpement autocentre, independant et populaire, a la strategie de mise de l’industrie au service du developpement agricole, aux « trois revolutions » des rapports de production, de la technique, de la culture, deja evoques plus haut ou ailleurs. Cependant, des questions vitales restent a elucider, par la pratique certes d’abord, mais aussi par la reflexion theorique : entre autres, la question de l’autarcie pour les petits pays socialistes et de la cooperation entre pays socialistes, la question meme de l’amorce de cette cooperation entre pays deja avances dans leur liberation nationale.

Ces problemes ont donne lieu a l’expression d’opinions contradictoires et a des pratiques egalement contradictoires, comme a des debats positifs, conduisant a des formulations plus nuancees. Il en a ete ainsi par exemple des discussions concernant l’organisation sociale du monde rural (cooperatives ou renforcement de la petite production marchande), les modalites de l’articulation entre la grande et la petite industrie au service direct des collectivites, notamment rurales, de celle qui a mis un terme au mythe du suicide de la petite bourgeoisie, des controverses concernant les avantages et les difficultes de l’autarcie, la « neutrality » des techniques importees, etc. Mais les deux questions essentielles par lesquelles s’expriment les contradictions de la transition sont la question de l’Etat et la question nationale.

4) La contradiction de la transition socialiste reside dans cette alternative que, de la lutte des classes au sein de la transition, emerge soit une societe sans classe, soit une nouvelle societe de classes.

Nouvelle societe de classes ou tout simplement restauration du capitalisme ? S’il s’agit d’un nouveau mode de production, la societe de classes etatique risque fort de se stabiliser pour une periode historique importante, d’autant qu’il s’agirait d’un mode permettant un nouveau bond dans le developpement des forces productives, donc d’un mode progressif. La classe dominante de ce mode serait alors une classe montante. S’il s’agit en revanche d’une simple restauration, le mode etatique serait un mode transitoire, instable, non progressif, et l’hegemonie de la classe dominante l’expression de l’ultime sursaut de la bourgeoisie decadente.

En faveur de laquelle de ces deux theses les faits plaident-ils ? On connait encore mal la societe sovietique, l’analyse de ses lois fondamentales ayant ete jusqu’ici deformee par la volonte d’y retrouver a priori soit l’expression des lois du socialisme, soit celle des lois du capitalisme : on y recherchera par exemple l’expression de la loi de la baisse tendancielle du taux du profit. Mais cette societe parait assez stable, malgre ses difficultes propres : liberalisation impossible, retard persistant de l’agriculture, contrastes nationaux, etc. De meme, en Europe de l’Est, la Roumanie parait solidement installee dans le mode etatique. Mais, en sens inverse, les apparences au moins n’indiquent pas que la Pologne, la Hongrie, la Tchecoslovaquie, la Yougoslavie ou Cuba soient parvenus a un point d’equilibre stable. En Egypte, pays du tiers monde ayant realise une forme d’organisation inspiree du meme modele, quoique dans une version faible et dependante, l’experience semble montrer que le mode etatique — qui n’a jamais pris ici, il est vrai, sa forme achevee — ne serait qu’une etape du developpement capitaliste.

L’analyse de ces problemes exigera non seulement que l’on examine de pres le fonctionnement des lois economiques propres aux systemes, mais encore que l’on integre celles-ci dans une comprehension globale des rapports entre

la base economique et les instances super-structurelles, politiques et

ideologiques qui les caracterisent.

a - La nature sociale de la societe sovietique

1)    Dans l’analyse des relations entre rapports de production et forces productives, on a soutenu parfois que, le developpement de la technique en U. R. S. S. etant en tout point analogue a celui de l’Occident, par le type de division du travail et d’organisation qu’il commande, il fallait considerer que le mode de production qui prevaut dans la societe sovietique est le capitalisme.

Mais on doit alors poser deux questions. La premiere concerne les effets de la centralisation du capital sur le fonctionnement du systeme. Une telle centralisation ne gomme-t-elle pas cette caracteristique propre au capital qu’est sa parcellisation et ne rend-elle pas compte du fonctionnement dominant de l’ideologie en U. R. S. S. ? La seconde concerne la possibilite d’un developpement superieur des forces productives sur la base de cette centralisation : en permettant d’aller au-dela des limites imposees par la concurrence des capitaux, le mode sovietique n’est-il pas nouveau, et superieur ?

Boukharine (70b-5) avait envisage ce type de capitalisme monopoliste d’Etat. Que l’Union sovietique, encore tres attardee, n’ait pas mis a l’epreuve des faits cette potentialite ne nous parait pas necessairement convaincant. Un mode nouveau part de plus bas pour aller plus haut. Si ce mode permettait de depasser la contradiction centre/peripherie, immanente au capitalisme, ne serait-il pas de ce seul fait superieur ?

2)    L’analyse des debats concernant la planification sovietique doit donc s’articuler sur celle de la nature sociale et sur l’analyse de la lutte des classes en U. R. S. S.

Les resultats de son essor economique, inegaux, plus lents que prevus, non conformes aux perspectives des plans, doivent-ils etre attribues a la deformation bureaucratique d’un Etat qui demeure fondamentalement ouvrier, selon la these du trotskisme ? Ou bien refletent-ils la resistance des classes exploitees ? Si en U. R. S. S. comme ailleurs c’est la lutte des classes qui determine le rythme et les orientations du developpement economique, l’hypothese est que, la bourgeoisie d’Etat n’etant pas soumise a la concurrence des capitaux qu’elle controle collectivement, les prix sont determines par les couts au lieu de s’imposer a elle par les lois du marche. Dans ces conditions, la resistance des travailleurs a l’intensification du travail, fondement de l’extorsion d’une plus-value relative croissante, est plus aisee qu’en Occident. Le droit au travail, conquete d’Octobre, constitue une arme dans la lutte des classes que le regime n’a pu que contourner partiellement par la multiplication des mesures de contrainte administrative. Sera-t-il capable d’aller plus loin, de supprimer ce droit pour retablir, par la gestion du volant de chomage, les conditions normales de la vente de la force de travail ? Si la Yougoslavie a surmonte cet obstacle, elle en a annule largement les effets par la reconnaissance simultanee de la gestion ouvriere.

3) Cette these concernant la transparence des rapports d’exploitation dans le systeme sovietique de propriete d’Etat generalisee du capital, et ses effets sur les rapports entre la base economique et la superstructure ideologique, appelle a une reflexion plus systematique sur les fonctions de l’ideologie nationaliste. Avangons l’hypothese que le nationalisme est le ciment principal de cette societe. En Occident, la dominance economique reduit l’ideologie a celle de la consommation et de la science et la technique comme ideologie, les effets de cette reduction sont desormais visibles : crise de la societe, des valeurs et de la jeunesse, etc. En U. R. S. S., le ciment nationaliste evitera-t-il cette crise ?

Il resterait a preciser de quel nationalisme il s’agit. A l’origine, la tentative fut celle d’un nationalisme sovietique transcendant celui des nationalites russes, slaves et asiatiques. Se justifiant par une mission liberatrice a l’echelle de l’humanite, ce nationalisme rejoignait la dimension slavophile de l’ideologie traditionnelle. Nicolas Berdiaev et Alexandre Koyre en avaient pressenti la fonction. Progressivement, ce nationalisme s’est russifie. Il s’oppose donc de plus en plus a la resurgence des nationalismes turco-musulmans de l’Asie centrale, a ceux de la Caucasie et de l’Ukraine. Or la population grand-russe, qui n’est deja plus majoritaire, est condamnee par la demographie a etre de plus en plus minoritaire. La centralisation etatique considerable de l’Union, en depit de ses formes federales, permet jusqu’ici d’eviter les heurts nationalistes les plus sanglants. Mais jusqu’a quand ? Et comment l’Etat russe reagira-t-il a ces contradictions ? Par des concessions, voire l’abandon de l’Asie et sa promotion a des independances neocoloniales comme les ideologues occidentalistes l’appellent de leurs vreux ? Ou au contraire par un

expansionnisme et la fuite en avant, l’agression exterieure ?

b - Technocratie et aristocratie ouvriere en U. R. S. S. et en Occident

1)    L’evolution de l’U. R. S. S. invite a reflechir sur la question du capitalisme d’Etat et des forces objectives qui reuvrent dans le sens d’un depassement non socialiste des contradictions du capitalisme contemporain. La question est de savoir si le mode etatique doit necessairement revetir la forme sovietique, et donc pratiquement etre seulement l’issue d’une revolution socialiste recuperee par les insuffisances de la lutte des classes qui lui succede. Ou bien le capitalisme d’Etat pourrait se constituer progressivement a partir du capitalisme des monopoles, sous l’effet de la concentration progressive du capital et de sa fusion avec l’Etat. La these du super-imperialisme supposait explicitement cette possibilite, et l’appelait meme comme une etape necessaire sur le chemin d’une evolution pacifique au socialisme. Rizzi, puis a sa suite Burnham, ont repris cette these de Kautsky et Hilferding pour l’associer a la « montee des technocrates » (80e).

2)    Une reponse a cette question exige une analyse beaucoup plus systematique que celle dont on dispose actuellement sur les rapports entre la technocratie et l’aristocratie ouvriere des pays capitalistes developpes.

La tendance social-democrate dans le mouvement ouvrier d’Occident reflete la constitution progressive d’une aristocratie ouvriere, greffee sur l’exploitation imperialiste, qui a la direction effective du mouvement ouvrier. L’histoire du travaillisme anglais en temoigne, comme celle de la social-democratie allemande. Cependant, a mesure que se constituait la nouvelle petite bourgeoisie, la social-democratie a commence a representer aussi la forme alienee des interets de la nouvelle technocratie, couche superieure de ce proletariat aise de cols blancs et de cadres techniciens. La tentative du capital des monopoles de faire remplir a cette nouvelle couche le role que les paysans avaient tenu a une etape anterieure, celui de reserve anti-ouvriere, n’a pas toujours donne les resultats escomptes, notamment en Europe du Sud et en Scandinavie, par opposition a l’Angleterre et a l’Allemagne contemporaines. Un clivage s’est opere de ce fait entre une social-democratie de droite, domestiquee par les monopoles, encadrant une classe ouvriere soumise a la direction conjointe de la technocratie et de l’aristocratie ouvriere, dont les contradictions sont reduites, et un mouvement plus ambigu, conservant ses distances a l’egard des monopoles. Tantot ce mouvement revet une forme social-democrate, comme en Suede, ou l’aristocratie ouvriere parait l’emporter, entrainant derriere elle la technocratie; tantot il revet une forme conflictuelle, le mouvement etant partage entre des partis communistes a preponderance aristocratique ouvriere et des partis socialistes nouveau style, a clientele technocratique, comme en Europe latine.

3)    Peut-on, sur ces bases, proposer une distinction entre un projet propre au communisme europeen de capitalisme d’Etat autonome vis-a-vis de Moscou, fonde sur l’hegemonie de l’aristocratie ouvriere au sein d’un bloc ralliant la technocratie nationale, et le projet plus traditionnel de la social-democratie, fonde sur le compromis entre les monopoles, la technocratie et l’aristocratie ouvriere ? Autrement dit, faut-il distinguer le revisionnisme nouveau du communisme europeen de l’ancien

revisionnisme herite par la social-democratie de la IIe Internationale ? L’eurocommunisme en gestation, encore mal defini, traduit-il cette tendance nouvelle, ou n’est-il rien de plus que le masque d’un glissement social-democrate encore difficile a avouer (81a) ? En tout cas, la transposition mecanique des lemons d’Octobre, deja refusee par Rosa Luxemburg et Gramsci, peut moins que jamais satisfaire ceux qui souhaitent agir pour une Europe socialiste et sortir des ghettos groupusculaires.

4)    Une etape importante dans l’analyse des tendances du systeme parait avoir ete franchie avec la proposition de Robert Fossaert (82-1) d’un concept de « valeur de developpement ». La valeur d’echange caracterise l’etape du developpement capitaliste fondee sur la parcellisation du capital et l’autonomie de l’unite de production; elle implique que cette unite, aux frontieres precises, definit le travailleur collectif dont le travail est la source de la valeur creee, et que le temps de travail socialement necessaire est celui que le capital paie a ce travailleur collectif. Le developpement des forces productives entraine l’emergence d’une nouvelle forme de la valeur, parce que la productivite du travail depend desormais largement de depenses sociales globales non affectables, les depenses de recherche et de formation qui commandent le niveau de la science et de la technologie. Le travail socialement necessaire est alors celui qui est depense dans l’ensemble du corps social et les frontieres de l’aire qui definit le travailleur collectif reculent pour se fondre avec celles de la nation, peut-etre meme du systeme mondial.

Fossaert met en reuvre ce concept de valeur de developpement qu’il propose pour analyser l’articulation des transferts de valeur a chacune des etapes du developpement capitaliste, d’une part dans le systeme impot/depense publique (ou il montre que, lorsque les transferts occasionnes par ce systeme atteignent un niveau tres eleve, 40 % du produit national, l’impot est devenu moyen de gestion economique, et on passe de ce fait d’une gestion par la valeur d’echange a une gestion par la valeur de developpement), et d’autre part dans le systeme monnaie/credit (ou il note que ce passage est signale par l’interconnexion et l’etatisation du systeme de credit).

L’emergence de la valeur de developpement reflete la contradiction entre le niveau atteint par les forces productives et la persistance de rapports de production devenus inadequats. Cette contradiction, deja visible, est surmontee, au moins en partie, dans le nouveau mode en cours de constitution en Occident que Fossaert qualifie de capitaliste-etatiste. Mais la valeur de developpement opere egalement dans le mode socialiste-etatiste, qui constitue une seconde voie (historiquement, la voie sovietique) de depassement de la contradiction sans abolition des classes.

Il y a, dans cette analyse, un progres qui parait tres fecond.

Le concept de valeur de developpement precise la reponse a la question du travailleur collectif, dans le sens esquisse par La loi de la valeur et le materialisme historique : l’eclatement des frontieres de l’unite de production. Fossaert prolonge egalement l’analyse qui concerne la reproduction elargie dans le capitalisme avance : nous avions situe dans ce cadre l’introduction necessaire d’un « departement III » d’absorption du surplus, pour repondre au developpement des forces productives sans abolir les rapports d’exploitation, par les effets de la concurrence monopolistique (couts de vente, etc.) et par les depenses d’Etat, en relation avec les exigences du developpement de la science et de la technologie.

Mais il faut aller plus loin. La persistance de la forme valeur, fut-ce sous des aspects nouveaux, n’accompagne-t-elle pas necessairement celle de la division du travail et de l’Etat, fondements et champs d’expression des antagonismes de classes ? La forme nouvelle de la valeur, qui accompagne l’abolition, non du capital, mais de sa parcellisation, n’entraine-t-elle pas la transparence des rapports d’exploitation ? S’il en est ainsi, les modes capitaliste-etatiste et socialiste-etatiste doivent tendre a retablir la dominance de l’ideologie dans la reproduction. Les separations Etat/societe civile, pouvoir politique/pouvoir economique sont propres au seul mode capitaliste vrai, fonde sur l’emiettement du pouvoir economique et l’ideologie economiste du marche generalise. La democratie en Occident n’est pas concomitante du capitalisme par hasard. Le depassement de la parcellisation du capital par la valeur de developpement abolit les separations Etat/societe civile, pouvoir politique/pouvoir economique; c’est-a-dire qu’il abolit la democratie et retablit l’absolutisme ideologique, que ce soit sous la forme de l’Homme unidimensionnel de l’Occident ou sous celle de l’ideologie nationaliste-pseudo-socialiste de l’Est. Cette analyse, inauguree par l’ecole de Francfort a partir, non seulement du totalitarisme hitlerien, et du stalinisme, mais aussi du totalitarisme interiorise de la societe occidentale avancee, vient a propos pour rappeler que l’autre issue de l’alternative — l’abolition de la valeur, de la division du travail, de l’Etat, donc des classes — etend au contraire et approfondit la societe civile, donc la democratie, qui devient anarchie au sens etymologique. Il faut situer a partir de la le retour en arriere, amorce au sein meme de l’ecole de Francfort, notamment par Hannah Arendt, reduisant cette analyse riche de l’emergence de l’absolutisme ideologique en rapport avec devolution de la base economique au schema politiciste du totalitarisme, coupe de la dialectique base/superstructure. Cette reduction, qui evacue le probleme de l’absolutisme ideologique dans l’Occident avance, a fini, de degradations en degradations, par s’abaisser au niveau de l’ideologie bourgeoise telle qu’elle est formulee, en France, chez Raymond Aron et ses eleves, lesquels reprennent eux-memes a leur compte la politicologie americaine.

III - La these des trois mondes et la rehabilitation du phenomene

national

1) La these des « trois mondes » classe les pays du systeme mondial en trois groupes : le premier monde (les deux superpuissances, Etats-Unis et U. R. S. S.), le second monde (les puissances moyennes : imperialismes secondaires d’Europe occidentale et Japon, pays de l’Europe de l’Est), et le tiers monde (pays d’Asie, d’Afrique et d’Amerique latine).

Ce classement pretend se substituer a l’ancienne division jdanovienne en deux camps, qui situait les pays au double plan de leur nature sociale (capitaliste ou socialiste) et de leur politique exterieure (alignement americain ou sovietique) en pretendant ces deux plans indissolublement lies. Lorsque s’est constitue le groupe des non-alignes, a l’initiative de Tito, Nasser et Nehru, la meme logique a ete etendue a ces pays. On a voulu relier leur politique exterieure neutraliste a des particularites de leurs regimes sociaux, qualifies de democratie nationale, de « voie non capitaliste ». L’elargissement du groupe des non-alignes a pratiquement tous les pays d’Asie et d’Afrique a vide de son contenu cette pretention d’analyse.

Ces theses sovietiques sont erronees et nous pretendons : 1) que les societes dites socialistes ne le sont pas, mais constituent un nouveau groupe de societes de classes, fondees sur le mode etatiste 2) que les rapports U. R. S. S. democraties populaires sont des rapports inegaux; 3) que les societes dites de democratie nationale sont des societes capitalistes peripheriques; 4) que, s’il y a une relation entre la structure sociale d’un pays, envisagee dans toutes ses nuances, et sa politique exterieure, cette relation ne saurait etre reduite a une determination lineaire simple selon laquelle une attitude pro ou antisovietique correspond a un certain degre de socialisme; 5) qu’en fait cette serie de theses sert a masquer la politique de superpuissance de l’U. R. S. S.; 6) qu’enfin l’alignement a laquelle elles invitent (alignement total ou tempere, non-alignement considere comme une transition) constitue un facteur de blocage de la dynamique de la lutte des classes internes et de la lutte anti-imperialiste; en forgant toutes les forces sociales et politiques a choisir entre le commandement americain ou celui de l’U. R. S. S., elles ont soumis les luttes sociales aux imperatifs des alignements exterieurs, reduisant ainsi la portee anticapitaliste qu’elles pouvaient acquerir.

2) Le reclassement propose par la these chinoise des trois mondes (cf. 75-2, 75-3) tord peut-etre le baton dans l’autre sens. Il est fonde en effet exclusivement sur le facteur national, reduit en l’occurrence a la taille et a la place des nations dans le systeme. Il y a les deux superpuissances, seules capables d’action directe et indirecte partout dans le monde. Il y a les societes developpees, economiquement independantes (dans l’interdependance inegale), parce que fagonnees historiquement comme

des societes autocentrees (capitalistes ou capitalistes d’Etat), mais qui ne sont plus capables d’intervenir a l’echelle mondiale au plan politique. Il y a les societes sous-developpees, economiquement dependantes, parce que fagonnees historiquement comme peripheries soumises et extraverties, politiquement et militairement faibles et instables. La these n’avance rien en ce qui concerne la nature sociale exacte des regimes, sauf qu’ils ne sont pas socialistes. Une exception est faite pour la Chine (hors classement ou tiers monde ?), les pays socialistes asiatiques (Coree, Vietnam, Cambodge, Laos) et, peut-etre, Cuba, consideres comme a la fois tiers monde et socialistes. En ce qui concerne tous les autres pays, juges non socialistes, la these n’exclut aucune nuance de qualification concernant la nature du bloc hegemonique particulier a chacun d’entre eux.

Une telle rehabilitation du fait national est confirmee partout par l’experience. Le facteur national subsiste meme au cours de la construction socialiste : pensons aux relations Chine-Vietnam-Cambodge, par exemple, ou Yougoslavie-Albanie. D’autres textes (La lettre en vingt-cinq points et Des defenseurs du neo-colonialisme, entre autres) precisent notamment le sens de la formule : « Les Etats veulent l’independance, les nations la liberation, les peuples la revolution. »

Les peuples sont definis par les blocs des classes anticapitalistes, differents au centre et a la peripherie du systeme imperialiste. Les nations constituent l’unite historique des classes antagonistes. De ce fait, ce que l’on appelle l’interet national n’est rien d’autre que le reflet des modalites que le caractere mondial du capitalisme impose aux blocs hegemoniques locaux qui doivent s’integrer dans des systemes d’oppositions et d’alliances de classes a l’echelle mondiale. Ces nations operent par le moyen d’Etats qui, plus ou moins nationaux, sont les instruments de la politique, c’est-a-dire des alliances internes et internationales.

3) Mais la these des trois mondes perd de sa pertinence si l’on reduit toute la realite au facteur national. On aboutit alors a une theorie unilaterale, non marxiste, qui substitue les nations aux classes et amene a se dispenser de faire l’analyse des contrastes et alliances de classes internes et externes par lesquels le systeme opere, se reproduit et se transforme.

L’U. R. S. S. et les Etats-Unis sont bien deux superpuissances, et deux societes de classes. Mais elles n’ont pas la meme histoire et n’occupent pas des positions symetriques dans le systeme mondial. Les Etats-Unis sont la superpuissance imperialiste qui herite de la constitution progressive de l’imperialisme au cours du dernier siecle comme de l’effacement partiel des imperialistes secondaires comme puissances mondiales. Ils operent dans l’ensemble des mondes non socialistes et non sovietiques conformement aux lois economiques de l’imperialisme (investissements de capitaux, extraction de surtravail, etc.). L’U. R. S. S. s’est constitue en societe de classe nouvelle a partir d’une revolution socialiste, apres avoir ete confinee dans ses frontieres, puis celles d’une zone d’influence precise. Son mode d’organisation interne et les interventions externes que chacune d’elles pratique sont specifiques.

L’Europe de l’Ouest et le Japon d’une part, l’Europe de l’Est de l’autre, ne sont pas non plus dans des positions analogues. Elles different au plan de leurs structures internes comme au plan de leur position international.

Les differents Etats du second et du tiers monde ne luttent pas pour l’independance de la meme maniere, ni pour la meme independance. Les differentes nations du tiers monde ne luttent pas pour la liberation de la meme maniere. Quant aux blocs populaires de classes revolutionnaires, ils sont evidemment differents d’un pays a l’autre. Les ennemis de ces independances, de ces liberations a contenus differents, comme ceux des differentes revolutions a l’ordre du jour, ne sont ni les memes partout, ni organises en blocs de la meme fagon. L’ennemi principal n’est pas le meme en Angola et en Tchecoslovaquie.

La politique exterieure ne constitue donc en aucune maniere un domaine qui serait parfaitement coherent avec la nature de classes des differentes nations. Il suffit de voir comment se font et se defont les alliances (exemple : l’Ethiopie et la Somalie) pour le comprendre. Un bloc populaire autonome qui conduit fermement la lutte selon ses interets propres peut conclure des alliances tres larges, internes et externes (exemple : le Vietnam); mais, si elles se substituent aux carences du bloc populaire, les alliances font des forces populaires le jouet des superpuissances.

4) L’analyse du fonctionnement du reseau economique, politique et ideologique du monde capitaliste est aujourd’hui assez avancee. On ne peut malheureusement pas en dire autant du reseau sovietique. Les travaux concernant le fonctionnement economique de la division du travail au sein du Comecon sont encore superficiels et generalement inspires par des ideologues du revisionnisme. Quant aux critiques, ils sont encore trop tentes de plaquer sur cette realite nouvelle les resultats de l’analyse du systeme occidental.

5) La these chinoise du social-imperialisme et de l’expansionnisme sovietique a l’avantage de proposer une integration de la politique sovietique dans un cadre de reference d’ensemble, qui definit la situation internationale nouvelle, a partir du milieu des annees 60, d’une maniere concrete. Selon cette these, on aurait assiste, apres la deuxieme guerre mondiale, a une etape de l’imperialisme dotee d’un certain nombre de caracteristiques comme l’hegemonie americaine sur l’ensemble du systeme imperialiste, la reclusion du monde sovietique enferme sur lui-meme et l’isolement de la Chine. Cette periode se terminerait et l’on entrerait dans une phase ou les rapports se modifient. En effet, l’hegemonie americaine sur l’ensemble du systeme est remise en cause : d’abord, par les luttes de liberation nationale (echecs en Asie, en Chine et au Vietnam) et, subsidiairement, par les modifications des rapports inter-imperialistes entre la fraction hegemonique americaine et les fractions subalternes europeenne et japonaise. Dans ce cadre, la resurgence des luttes dans les centres faibles (l’Europe du Sud) s’articulerait sur l’essor du mouvement de liberation nationale, tout comme les bourgeoisies de la peripherie tenteraient de se donner un second souffle en imposant un nouveau partage moins defavorable de la plus-value mondiale.

Cette remise en cause de l’hegemonie et de l’equilibre mondial aurait conduit l’Union sovietique a envisager d’exploiter le declin americain en vue de la constitution d’un nouvel empire sur une zone plus importante. Pendant toute la periode passee, l’U. R. S. S. avait ete enfermee dans les frontieres de son glacis, avec ses zones de dependance directe mais sans bases avancees, les partis revisionnistes etant eux-memes isoles dans leur vie politique locale. L’imperialisme americain jouissait de son hegemonie sur un systeme vaste et organise, s’appuyant sur le double relais des bourgeoisies imperialistes subalternes europeenne et japonaise et des classes exploiteuses du tiers monde, dans des alliances de classes diverses.

L’analyse suppose une vision de devolution de l’Union sovietique a partir d’une revolution, socialiste a l’origine, qui degenere de la construction du socialisme vers une societe de classes. Celle-ci ne dispose pas, a l’heure actuelle, d’un empire a l’echelle de ses appetits. Les pays de l’Europe de l’Est, qui peuvent etre classes dans le second monde par leur niveau de developpement, restent de petits pays. Mais le probleme majeur est que l’U. R. S. S. n’a pas de bases dans le tiers monde. Il n’y existe pas de systeme qui soit greffe solidement dans une alliance de classes avec le systeme sovietique. L’U. R. S. S. a beneficie d’alliances sporadiques avec les bourgeoisies dirigeantes des mouvements de liberation nationale a un moment ou un autre, entendant par la les arracher a l’hegemonie americaine et y parvenant temporairement; mais le cas egyptien a montre la fragilite de ces alliances. L’U. R. S. S. tenterait donc d’exploiter le declin americain pour constituer cet empire a travers la recherche de positions cette fois serieuses dans le second et dans le tiers monde. Elle chercherait en particulier a transformer a son profit les anciens imperialismes subalternes en social-imperialismes subalternes.

L’U. R. S. S. poursuivait des objectifs a peu pres analogues a ceux de l’imperialisme classique : recherche des sources d’exploitation exterieures permettant le renforcement de l’alliance revisionniste (soumission de sa classe ouvriere a sa classe dominante dans le cadre de l’hegemonie d’une ideologie nationaliste) qui prendrait la succession de l’alliance social-democrate. Bien entendu, cette recherche doit adopter des formes specifiques adaptees a la conjoncture. Par exemple, la recherche de matieres premieres est peut-etre secondaire, compte tenu du developpement historique autarcique dont elles beneficieraient dans le cadre d’un pays tres vaste fagonne au depart par une revolution socialiste : la soumission de pays industrialises avances permettant de fournir une technologie plus efficace repondrait peut-etre mieux aux besoins sovietiques. Il faudrait aussi distinguer, dans cette perspective, les objectifs strategiques des moyens tactiques. La recherche de bases lointaines peut n’etre qu’un moyen tactique, dans la lutte contre l’imperialisme concurrent majeur, pour imposer un nouveau partage plus satisfaisant ailleurs. Les mondes arabe, indien et africain, « ventres mous » de la peripherie — par opposition a l’Amerique latine, infiniment plus soumise a l’hegemonie nord-americaine, ou se confrontent mouvements de liberation nationale, interets de l’imperialisme hegemonique, interets des imperialismes seconds, conflits locaux importants — peuvent, de ce fait, etre les champs principaux du « conflit du siecle » sans etre necessairement leur objectif final reel.

Il reste a savoir si cette analyse correspond aux visees veritables de ceux que les Chinois appellent les « nouveaux tsars ». Des ecrits comme ceux d’Amalrik (80d-3), s’ils n’ont aucune valeur scientifique, ont au moins l’avantage de rappeler que des courants ideologiques existent en U. R. S. S. qui envisagent la fuite en avant dans le bellicisme antichinois comme moyen de surmonter la crise interne et notamment la revolte des peuples asiatiques opprimes de l’Union.

Chapitre VIII

La theorie de l’imperialisme et sa crise contemporaine

Les huit theses qui suivent resument nos conclusions.

A) La theorie de l’imperialisme est synonyme de theorie de l’accumulation du capital a l’echelle mondiale, theorie de l’articulation des divers modes d’extorsion du surtravail fondes sur les modalites specifiques du developpement inegal de notre epoque. La loi fondamentale qui regit l’accumulation a l’echelle mondiale est done l’expression de la loi de la valeur operant a l’echelle du systeme imperialiste dans son ensemble.

1)    La theorie du mode de production capitaliste est en effet construite dans Le capital a partir de l’elaboration de la loi de la valeur (cf. La loi de la valeur et le materialisme historique). Celle-ci ne rend pas compte seulement du caractere du produit social dans le mode capitaliste, sa nature marchande; elle ne revele pas seulement l’origine du profit, la plus-value; elle permet de comprendre les lois de l’accumulation qui commandent la reproduction et l’expansion du mode capitaliste. Ces lois, qui s’expriment a travers les equilibres-desequilibres entre les deux departements de la production capitaliste (production de moyens de production et production de moyens de consommation), donnent a la valeur de la force de travail un statut objectif, dans la mesure ou les lois de l’accumulation etablissent la relation entre la valeur de la force de travail et le niveau de developpement des forces productives.

L’unite du marche des marchandises, des capitaux et de la force de travail, c’est-a-dire l’existence coextensive d’un Etat bourgeois, d’une bourgeoisie et d’une classe ouvriere nationales, constitue le cadre necessaire qui donne sa signification a la loi de la valeur.

2)    L’hypothese sous-jacente correspondant a l’analyse du Capital est que cette loi opere dans le cadre de chacun des espaces nationaux capitalistes, l’Angleterre, la France, l’Allemagne, les Etats-Unis, etc. Elle correspond effectivement a la realite du milieu du siecle dernier qui fait l’objet de l’analyse de Marx. Mais elle ne lui correspond plus, car le capital circule et se reproduit a l’echelle mondiale, les marchandises et la classe ouvriere elle-meme tendent a devenir mondiales. Aucun espace national, meme celui des Etats-Unis, ne constitue un cadre suffisant a l’interieur duquel puissent se reproduire les conditions de l’accumulation.

3) La theorie de l’imperialisme doit donc etre construite sur la base infrastructurelle de la theorie de la valeur operant a l’echelle mondiale, et la loi de la valeur doit rendre compte des niveaux differents du prix de vente de la force de travail dans les differents segments du systeme imperialiste.

Notre these ici est : a) que les marchandises, parce qu’elles sont mondiales, ont une seule valeur mondiale; b) que le capital, parce qu’il est mondial, tend a s’aligner sur un taux de remuneration moyen, ou une gamme precise de taux structures en fonction de celui-ci; c) que le marche de la force de travail demeure segmente, et que, de ce fait, les conditions locales de la lutte des classes permettent des taux de plus-value inegaux.

Il n’y a pas d’autres explications possibles aux differences de prix de la force de travail. Ceux qui renoncent a la relation objective entre la valeur de la force de travail et le developpement des forces productives sont contraints de faire du salaire reel une categorie empirique, soit determinee par la biologie (les « subsistances ») et de substituer ainsi a la loi de l’accumulation une loi de la population, soit totalement indeterminee.

Mais, si la relation doit etre etablie entre valeur de la force de travail et developpement des forces productives, il faut preciser auparavant de quelles forces productives on parle : sectorielles, nationales ou mondiales.

A l’interieur d’un espace national, les forces productives sont inegalement developpees d’une branche a l’autre; pourtant, la force de travail a la meme valeur. Le discours reliant ces salaires aux productivites sectorielles est un discours necessairement marginaliste et tautologique, car on ne peut pas comparer la productivite d’une branche a l’autre. L’unite du marche des marchandises, des capitaux et du travail d’une part, la determination des equilibres de l’accumulation au sein de ce marche d’autre part, imposent de conclure que la valeur de la force de travail est reliee objectivement au niveau national (« moyen ») de developpement des forces productives.

Mais alors, si d’une part le marche des marchandises et celui du capital, et si d’autre part l’espace au sein duquel se realisent les equilibres de l’accumulation sont devenus mondiaux, la valeur de la force de travail a l’echelle du systeme mondial est reliee au niveau mondial « moyen » de developpement des forces productives. Les differences nationales entre les prix de la force de travail ne s’expliquent plus par les differents niveaux de developpement nationaux moyens, mais par la segmentation de la classe ouvriere. L’element Etat-politique-lutte de classes est ainsi necessairement reintroduit dans la theorie de l’imperialisme.

4)    Les prix differents de la valeur de la force de travail, s’ils s’expliquent par les conditions concretes de la lutte des classes, posent la question de la reproduction de la force de travail.

Il n’est pas dit que ces conditions permettent partout et necessairement la reproduction de chacun des segments de la force de travail. On oublie, par exemple, que l’Irlande avait une population egale a celle de l’Angleterre au moment de sa conquete par celle-ci, aux debuts du mercantilisme et de la transition au capitalisme : la nation et le peuple irlandais ont ete detruits par le meme processus qui a permis l’expansion anglaise. Il n’est pas dit qu’a notre epoque des phenomenes semblables de destruction de la force de travail ne caracterisent pas le systeme imperialiste.

5)    Traiter du systeme imperialiste, c’est traiter d’un systeme de formations et non du mode capitaliste etendu au monde. Dans ce systeme de formations, tous les modes non capitalistes sont soumis a la domination du capital et, de ce fait, du surtravail est arrache aux producteurs non proletarises pour etre transforme en profit du capital. Cette domination formelle agit sur les conditions de la reproduction de la force de travail non proletarisee.

6)    Le prix de la force de travail dans les centres imperialistes n’est pas independant du prix pratique dans les peripheries dominees, puisque le prix moyen de l’ensemble de la force de travail doit correspondre a sa valeur, en relation avec le developpement des forces productives a l’echelle globale. De fait, le prix de la force de travail au centre est indissolublement lie au caractere imperialiste du systeme d’exploitation capitaliste.

7)    L’echange inegal qui apparait au niveau des prix des marchandises ne resulte donc pas de phenomenes situes au plan de la circulation, mais reflete les conditions de la genese et de la repartition du surtravail dans le systeme imperialiste.

8)    Les societes capitalistes ne sont pas seulement constituees de la classe ouvriere et de la bourgeoisie. Dans les centres dominants, des classes et couches nombreuses participent a la production ou remplissent des fonctions improductives. Or, la repartition des fonctions et des occupations n’est pas independante de la division du travail a l’echelle mondiale. Qui produit de la valeur, qui en consomme ?

9)    Le type de developpement resultant des lois de l’accumulation operant a l’echelle mondiale a des effets d’ensemble qui depassent la seule question des prix de la force de travail. Par exemple, la concentration au centre de la consommation des ressources naturelles produites dans la peripherie modifie les conditions d’un developpement ulterieur des forces productives.

10)    La question de savoir si la classe ouvriere d’Occident « profite » ou non de l’imperialisme entraine de ce fait des polemiques steriles. Le jeu de mots qui consiste a rapprocher la categorie du profit de l’emploi trivial du verbe « profiter » pour eluder le probleme en constitue un exemple classique.

Il est certain que les travailleurs au centre du systeme imperialiste sont exploites par le capital, encore qu’il n’existe pas d’analyse exhaustive des effets de parasitisme inherents au systeme imperialiste. Mais il est certain aussi que la destruction du systeme imperialiste impliquerait la suppression du transfert de valeur generee a la peripherie. Cette suppression ne serait compatible avec l’amelioration des conditions de vie des travailleurs au centre que si les rapports capitalistes sont renverses. Ce qui, a son tour, impliquerait un tout autre modele de developpement que celui qui decoule des lois de l’accumulation capitaliste en general et, a fortiori, de l’accumulation imperialiste.

B) Toute crise dans le systeme capitaliste est l’expression d’un

disfonctionnement de la loi de la valeur sous l’effet de la lutte des classes.

Elle se manifeste par des desequilibres qui rendent la realisation de la valeur impossible et, en consequence, entrainent la chute du taux de profit. En ce sens, toute crise est une crise des rapports de production capitalistes.

Cette proposition generale ne suffit pas pour caracteriser une crise

particuliere, a une etape donnee de devolution du systeme. Au xixe siecle, par exemple, la loi de la valeur operant sur la base des espaces nationaux, la crise est une crise nationale, bien qu’elle puisse etre transmise du centre hegemonique de l’epoque (l’Angleterre) aux autres pays.

Si, aujourd’hui, l’espace sur la base duquel opere la loi de la valeur est celui de l’ensemble du systeme imperialiste, la crise doit etre saisie d’abord a ce niveau, c’est-a-dire refletant l’impossibilite d’assurer la circulation mondiale du capital et la realisation mondiale de la valeur. Cette impossibilite resulte a son tour de la lutte des classes a l’echelle mondiale. C’est la raison pour laquelle la dimension principale dans laquelle s’exprime la crise actuelle est situee dans le champ de la division internationale du travail.

C) La theorie de l’imperialisme et de sa crise implique necessairement une theorie de l’Etat a l’epoque imperialiste.

1) Cette theorie ne saurait se contenter de generalites. Il n’est pas suffisant de considerer l’Etat comme l’instrument des interets economiques dominants, hier des bourgeoisies nationales, aujourd’hui des monopoles. De quels monopoles les Etats contemporains seraient les representants : des monopoles nationaux ou des multinationals, americaines principalement ? Quelle place sera faite dans ces conditions aux alliances de classes nationales hegemoniques concretes ? Les conditions historiques particulieres a chaque pays ne commandent-elles pas en permanence la composition-dislocation-recomposition de ces blocs hegemoniques dont les composantes se modifient sous l’effet des luttes de classes et de l’accumulation du capital ? A la peripherie du systeme, ces blocs successifs ne sont-ils pas visiblement en relation avec les modalites de la division internationale du travail et ne refletent-ils pas le contenu de l’alliance de classes internationale hegemonique qui assure la circulation mondiale du capital ? En definitive, les contradictions qui traversent ces divers blocs hegemoniques sous l’effet des luttes de classes internes se manifestent au plan mondial par les contradictions qui opposent les Etats.

2)    Le proces meme de l’accumulation a modifie progressivement le rapport entre l’Etat et le capital.

Au xixe siecle, les Etats capitalistes nationaux europeens sont deja constitues depuis l’epoque mercantiliste (Angleterre, France) ou se constituent en meme temps que se developpe le capitalisme industriel (Allemagne, Italie). A cette epoque, il y a coincidence entre l’espace etatique (national, en general) et le triple marche capitaliste des marchandises, du capital et de la force de travail. Les alliances de classes hegemoniques sont des alliances nationales, en relation avec les conditions historiques particulieres de la revolution bourgeoise. L’hegemonie mondiale britannique implique toutefois des alliances transnationales, par exemple avec les classes latifundiaires dominantes de l’Amerique latine, les classes « feodales » de l’Orient et de l’Inde, etc. Cette hegemonie economique est acceptee par les pays europeens apres 1815 et notamment par le concurrent de l’Angleterre a l’epoque mercantiliste, la France. Elle institue la coexistence d’un marche mondial embryonnaire (limite a certaines marchandises) et de marches nationaux (au triple sens indique ci-dessus) pleinement constitues. Elle organise un equilibre politique et militaire correspondant, « l’equilibre europeen ».

Au cours des trois dernieres decennies du siecle, la concurrence aigue, durant la « grande crise » des annees 1873-96, conduit a un nouveau stade de la centralisation et de la concentration du capital, le stade imperialiste. Les monopoles se forment sur la base des marches nationaux deja constitues. Us conservent ce caractere jusqu’au lendemain de la seconde guerre mondiale.

3)    Nous devons a Giovanni Arrighi (71b-5) l’analyse la plus poussee des effets de ces changements dans les rapports entre l’Etat et le marche — synonyme ici de capital, monopoles, economie. Selon lui, c’est l’adequation entre l’espace etatique national et les monopoles de la fin du XIXe siecle a 1945 qui rend compte des aspects essentiels de la vie sociale pour toute la periode.

Elle explique le transfert du lieu de la concurrence entre monopoles, du terrain proprement economique a celui de la lutte entre les Etats imperialistes et, par la, le caractere militariste de la periode et la constitution de deux coalitions qui confronteront leurs forces dans deux guerres mondiales. La periode 1914-1945 apparaitra ainsi comme une « guerre de Trente ans » entre l’Allemagne et les Etats-Unis pour la succession a l’hegemonie britannique declinante, guerre qui s’est soldee en 1945 par la superiorite definitive et acceptee de la puissance nord-americaine.

Elle explique le caractere des luttes de classes renouvelees de 1903 a

1907. La concurrence au xixe siecle avait opere dans une ambiance economique impliquant une baisse tendancielle des prix resultant de l’amelioration de la productivite. Les formes nouvelles de la concurrence entre monopoles impliquant au contraire une tendance a la hausse des prix, les salaires perdent leur « protection naturelle » resultant de la baisse des prix et, de ce fait, les luttes des salaries pour obtenir des augmentations s’avivent. L’attitude ambigue du mouvement ouvrier a l’egard de la question coloniale et des imperialismes concurrents entrainera l’effacement de ces luttes devant la preparation de la guerre mondiale.

L’analyse d’Arrighi explique encore la nature des alliances de classes hegemoniques retrogrades qui s’etablissent durant la periode. Les bourgeoisies monopolistes concurrentes ont besoin en effet de renforcer l’unite nationale par des politiques d’alliance avec des couches moyennes en voie de destruction sous l’effet precisement du developpement monopoliste (paysannerie, petites entreprises, etc.). Des fascismes aux fronts populaires et au New Deal, ces types d’alliance s’emploient a proteger les secteurs nationaux qui ont perdu leur competitivite (l’agriculture) ou qui ne l’ont pas encore acquise (la siderurgie).

On comprend alors les caracteres des luttes de classes de l’entre-deux-guerres. La vague des annees 20, qui suit la revolution russe, est la plus politisee des vagues successives de luttes en Occident. Le mouvement ouvrier aspire alors au pouvoir d’Etat et a la suppression de la propriete privee du capital au benefice d’une appropriation nationale. L’echec de cette vague et le caractere des alliances hegemoniques renforcees pour soutenir son assaut rend compte de la gravite de la crise de 1930. La nouvelle vague de luttes, celle des annees 30, se place d’emblee sur un terrain defensif : le mouvement aspire au plein emploi dans une economie capitaliste, puis accepte la perspective de la marche a la guerre.

Arrighi oppose ces caracteres de la periode 1880-1945 a ceux de la periode suivante. L’hegemonie incontestee des Etats-Unis au sortir de la seconde guerre permet alors le retablissement d’un marche mondial. Celui-ci est d’ailleurs beaucoup plus developpe que son homologue du

xixe siecle : il englobe desormais un volume decisif de la production marchande (notamment des produits de base, tous mondialises) comme du capital. La mobilite sectorielle et internationale retablie ouvre la voie a l’expansion mondiale des monopoles americains et a une croissance economique forte du systeme dans son ensemble, qui contraste avec la stagnation relative de l’entre-deux-guerres. Mais il n’y a plus maintenant adequation entre l’espace des Etats et l’espace economique : la loi de la valeur est devenue mondiale.

Ce second apres-guerre differe fondamentalement du precedent : les luttes sont desormais limitees pratiquement a l’ltalie et a la France, ou elles apparaissent plus comme la queue de la periode precedente que comme annonciatrices d’une vague nouvelle. L’epicentre des revolutions politiques est deja transfere hors d’Europe.

La croissance economique forte renforce le poids economique de la classe ouvriere, dont les luttes, particulierement la vague des annees 60, sont generalement couronnees de succes au plan economique, reduisant la flexibilite du systeme, d’autant que les partis ouvriers sont desormais au centre de la vie politique en Europe occidentale. La strategie du capital est double. D’une part, elle s’efforce de renouveler ses alliances en les modernisant : en substituant aux anciennes des couches nouvelles (technocraties, aristocraties ouvrieres) qui s’inscrivent mieux dans les exigences de l’accumulation. D’autre part, elle vise a diviser a nouveau la classe ouvriere en opposant l’ouvrier-masse dequalifie (souvent immigre, minoritaire, jeune ou femme) a l’ouvrier d’encadrement a statut. La premiere operation, si elle semble avoir reussi aux Etats-Unis et en Europe du Nord, parait s’etre heurte a des obstacles en France et en Italie, qui contraignent peut-etre le capital a tenter de revenir a des alliances retrogrades ou a accepter des positions subalternes dans la division industrielle du travail (vis-a-vis de l’Allemagne). La seconde operation parait, elle, couronnee de succes dans l’ensemble de l’Occident, du moins a l’etape actuelle. Cela explique les caracteres des luttes des annees 60 : il s’agit d’une vague depolitisee, les revendications politiques (notamment en 1968) etant exprimees plutot par des couches exterieures a la classe ouvriere. La crise actuelle eclate sur cette toile de fond. Le mouvement ouvrier est donc sur la defensive. La moitie privilegiee de la classe ouvriere, moins touchee par le chomage que par l’inflation, ne pourrait-elle pas s’assigner l’objectif tres bourgeois de la stabilite monetaire dans un marche mondial restructure en fonction des exigences nouvelles de l’accumulation ? L’evolution du mouvement ouvrier allemand est a cet egard significative.

4)    La phase coloniale de la division du travail centre/peripherie s’articule logiquement sur la premiere phase imperialiste. Les zones coloniales et semi-coloniales dependantes sont confinees dans le role de fournisseurs de matieres premieres au profit des ensembles industriels monopolistes des metropoles concurrentes et dans celui de debouches pour les industries non competitives soutenant les alliances retrogrades dans les metropoles. Les metropoles qui beneficient d’avantages historiques (la Grande-Bretagne et la France) voient leurs positions convoitees par celles qui, venues plus tard, manquent d’« espace vital ». La crise de l’entre-deux-guerres accentue ces « repliements imperiaux ».

La phase neocoloniale s’articule sur la reconstruction du marche mondial et l’expansion des multinationals. L’industrialisation de substitution d’importation est le resultat de la premiere vague de liberation nationale, qui a impose un renouvellement des alliances de classes internationales.

La crise actuelle revele le caractere decisif des contradictions situees a ce niveau. En effet, l’obstacle principal au retablissement de la circulation mondiale du capital est situe precisement dans l’epuisement du potentiel d’accumulation fonde sur la division du travail qui a sous-tendu l’industrialisation de substitution d’importation. D’ou la convergence de la revendication des bourgeoisies du tiers monde d’un ordre nouveau fonde sur l’industrie d’exportation et de la strategie de redeploiement des monopoles.

5)    La these du marche mondial reconstitue dans le cadre de l’hegemonie americaine n’est pas celle du super-imperialisme kautskyste. Celle-ci ignore en effet l’Etat, reduit au role de conseil d’administration des monopoles. Son economisme se retrouve dans les theses radicales, non marxistes, qui font des multinationals les seuls maitres du monde. Notre these au contraire part de la contradiction Etat/monopoles, reflet des contradictions de classes au sein des societes nationales tant au centre qu’a la peripherie.

L’analyse des strategies des forces sociales en lutte et donc des issues possibles a la crise actuelle implique un approfondissement de la reflexion sur l’Etat. Au centre, cette reflexion s’articule sur toutes les questions a l’ordre du jour, telles celle de la construction europeenne et celle des regionalismes. A la peripherie, elle pose la question du contenu de la liberation nationale dans la periode actuelle.

D) La definition du rapport evolutif Etat/capital constitue le cadre correct pour l’analyse de la portee de la hierarchie contemporaine des imperialismes et de la question actuelle de la construction europeenne.

1) Les Etats nationaux demeurent la seule instance politique supreme du systeme contemporain. Il n’y a pas d’Etat supranational. Au niveau international, des institutions comme le Fonds monetaire international n’en constituent meme pas l’embryon; elles ne sont que le prolongement du systeme de l’hegemonie americaine organisee sur la base du marche mondial durant la phase 1945-70. Au niveau europeen, il y a bien un debut d’organisation paraetatique. Mais, dans la mesure ou le cadre au sein duquel se deroule la lutte des classes et se nouent les alliances hegemoniques demeure strictement national, on doit continuer a parler des imperialismes au pluriel.

En dernier ressort, la hierarchie depend de la place assignee aux systemes productifs des monopoles industriels dans la division du travail. A ce titre, les imperialistes les plus puissants sont ceux des Etats-Unis, du Japon et de l’Allemagne. Les avantages economiques herites des empires coloniaux, comme les inegalites au plan des positions politiques, ideologiques et militaires ne constituent que des moyens pour les imperialismes seconds de negocier les termes de leur alignement sur ces imperialismes principaux.

La these d’un retour a l’imperialisme financier, de la restauration de la suprematie de la finance sur l’industrie, se fonde sur le recul relatif de l’investissement direct dans le tiers monde au benefice d’un endettement, notamment des Etats, aupres de consortiums financiers prives. Mais ce recul pourrait bien n’etre que conjoncturel, et associe a la crise structurelle de la division international du travail : l’analyse de la dette montre en effet que celle-ci resulte en partie du report de la crise sur le tiers monde, en partie des exigences de l’insertion de celui-ci dans la circulation mondiale du capital (renflouement des balances de paiement, consolidation des bourgeoisies, etc.).

2)    S’il existe un imperialisme europeen en formation, celui-ci ne s’est pas encore situe par rapport a l’imperialisme americain. Pour le moment, la construction europeenne en cours est seulement utilisee par les imperialismes seconds pour pallier leurs insuffisances. La question reste donc entiere de savoir si le systeme tendra vers l’eclatement du marche mondial, la fin de l’hegemonie americaine et la reconstitution d’une adequation Etat/capital portee eventuellement au niveau europeen, ou si l’Europe et les Etats qui la composent conserveront leurs positions actuelles de relais dans le systeme du marche mondial unifie sous la houlette des monopoles, essentiellement americains.

En principe, une situation de crise comme celle que traverse le systeme conduit soit a une aggravation des contradictions inter-imperialistes, soit, a l’oppose, a un alignement des plus faibles sur les plus forts. Si, en 1930, la crise a appele la premiere solution, c’est a cause de l’adequation Etat-monopoles qui caracterisait l’epoque, tandis que la transnationalisation explique le realignement en cours, apres quelques velleites d’autonomie au moment de la crise de 1973.

3)    La these la plus communement admise par la gauche europeenne est celle du ralliement a l’Europe, quitte a opposer l’« Europe des travailleurs » a celle des monopoles. Il y a dans cette position, implicitement, un recul economiste devant les « exigences objectives du developpement des forces productives ». La formation de l’Etat europeen est en effet consideree comme un prealable a la transformation socialiste des rapports de production, des lors repoussee aux calendes. Accepter cette etape comme necessaire pourrait alors etre suivie d’un second aggiornamento, fonde sur la construction d’un Etat planetaire, conformement aux exigences des forces productives. C’est par la meme renoncer a croire encore possible la constitution de breches socialistes a partir des effets du developpement inegal sur les conditions politiques des luttes des classes. Notre these est qu’au contraire la strategie leniniste de la rupture demeure valable, qui pose la question du desengagement a l’egard du systeme international.

E) Le rapport de l’Etat avec le capital dans la crise actuelle doit egalement

etre examine a la peripherie du systeme.

1) Le developpement du capitalisme peripherique, loin de constituer des nations comme au centre, ici les desagrege. Le caractere extraverti de ce developpement et ses effets de distorsion reduisent la portee de la formation du marche local; la domination du capital etranger rend impossible la constitution d’un marche local des capitaux; enfin, la persistance des formes de la soumission formelle limite la portee de la formation d’un marche du travail.

L’Etat ne serait-il ici qu’une excroissance administrative de l’appareil des Etats imperialistes ? En partie. Mais il est aussi, et surtout, l’expression d’une alliance hegemonique locale, articulee sur l’alliance imperialiste. De la la double fragilite des Etats peripheriques.

D’abord, la fragilite de l’alliance hegemonique, traversee des contradictions qui refletent celle qui l’oppose aux masses populaires. Cette fragilite decoule directement du rejet vers la peripherie des contradictions de l’accumulation du capital a l’echelle mondiale. Les alliances les plus faibles, fondees sur la predominance d’une bureaucratie compradore pratiquement sans bourgeoisie locale, rapprochent alors l’Etat local de l’excroissance administrative etrangere et ouvrent le pays aux interventions exterieures permanentes. Mais meme les alliances d’apparence plus solides, comme celles qui sont fondees sur une bourgeoisie industrielle et un Etat national, demeurent instables, ainsi qu’en ont temoigne en 1979 les evenements d’lran.

Ensuite, la fragilite nationale. L’integration au systeme imperialiste a souvent opere sur un substrat anterieur d’ethnies, groupes et communautes plus ou moins heteroclites. Dans ce cas, l’Etat national parvient d’autant plus difficilement a se cristalliser que les contradictions au sein du peuple sont largement exploitees, tant par les differents segments de l’alliance hegemonique locale que par les forces exterieures. On a affaire ici a un mouvement de liberation nationale sans nation. S’il ne parvient pas a resoudre correctement les contradictions au sein du peuple, il demeure faible, et sa faiblesse fait la force relative des blocs hegemoniques qui assurent l’integration imperialiste. Lorsqu’au contraire le mouvement de liberation coincide avec une nation precapitaliste (Asie orientale), cette conjoncture revele en retour la fragilite de l’alliance exploiteuse locale.

2) Dans l’abstrait, le « nouvel ordre », fonde sur une industrialisation acceleree de la peripherie s’inscrivant dans la division international du travail, repond aux exigences objectives de l’accumulation : relevement du taux de la plus-value et, par la, du profit a l’echelle mondiale.

Mais il ne s’agit la que d’une abstraction, puisque l’objet de la lutte en cours est precisement le partage de cette plus-value entre les differents segments du capital. Or, ici, l’interet du capital dominant, celui des multinationales, se heurte a celui des bourgeoisies de la peripherie. Le redeploiement correspond a la strategie des premieres; il suppose des Etats peripheriques affaiblis. Le « nouvel ordre » correspond a celles des secondes; il suppose des Etats peripheriques renforces, capables de s’organiser en cartels d’exportateurs pour imposer le relevement des prix des produits de base et d’exercer un controle national des ressources naturelles, de retenir le benefice des relevements de prix par la nationalisation et la fiscalite, de controler l’investissement de ces surplus afin de structurer, au moins partiellement, les systemes productifs, pour leur donner plus d’autonomie, etc.

A l’heure actuelle, les luttes de classes violentes qui secouent les societes de la peripherie permettent d’envisager l’effondrement de certains blocs hegemoniques garants de l’equilibre actuel, comme cela a ete le cas en Iran. Le succes meme du redeploiement, marque par des taux de croissance exceptionnels, loin d’attenuer les contradictions, les a rendues plus explosives. Car la classe ouvriere en formation est en quelque sorte conduite ineluctablement a la lutte politique. Peu importe les drapeaux ideologiques derriere lesquels les masses se revoltent : c’est pour beaucoup le resultat de conditions circonstancielles et subjectives, la consequence previsible de la strategie de la « voie non capitaliste ». L’essentiel est qu’elles se revoltent contre l’expansion du capital.

3) Dans les conditions de cette lutte, peut-on entrevoir l’emergence de nouveaux Etats nationaux capitalistes acheves ? Dans l’abstrait, le processus de l’accumulation du capital, s’il pouvait se poursuivre indefiniment, finirait certes par imposer a l’ensemble des societes du monde les rapports de production capitalistes, supprimant toutes les autres formes de rapports de production, et donc homogeneisant sur cette base l’ensemble de la planete.

Mais, jusqu’ici, a chaque etape du developpement du systeme imperialiste, les rapports centre/peripherie sont restes fondes sur une division inegale du travail. L’analyse economique des industries d’exportation proposees a certains pays de la peripherie, fondees sur la main-d’reuvre a bon marche ou des ressources naturelles abondantes, comme l’analyse politique d’ensemble de l’insertion de ces pays dans le systeme mondial (alliances hegemoniques locales et alliances internationales dominantes, caracteres et role de l’Etat, systemes de l’ideologie et de la vie politique, etc.) interdisent de prevoir le renversement de cette tendance.

La these adverse donne toujours en exemple les pays du tiers monde les plus avances dans la voie de ^industrialisation (le Bresil, la Coree du Sud, Taiwan, l’lran, etc.), pour revenir a une theorie simple des « etapes » du developpement. Que ce soit dans sa version conventionnelle (celle de la Banque mondiale) ou dans des versions d’apparence marxiste, cette these substitue toujours a l’analyse en termes de materialisme historique une analyse economiste reduite a la mesure quantitative de la production industrielle.

F) L’etude des contradictions du systeme a une etape precise de son developpement et l’articulation de ces contradictions doivent toujours etre situees dans le cadre de la conjoncture politique international concrete de la periode.

1) Sans doute notre epoque peut-elle etre interpretee comme celle de la confrontation entre le capitalisme declinant et le socialisme naissant. Mais on ne saurait se limiter a cette proposition generale. L’affrontement est seulement implicite, cache derriere des affrontements visibles qui sont d’une autre nature. Ainsi, dans les affrontements de classes au centre du systeme, l’objectif actuel du mouvement ouvrier n’est pas le socialisme : cet objectif demeure economique (plein emploi, sauvegarde du pouvoir d’achat ronge par l’inflation, etc.). Les percees dans le domaine de la vie sociale se situent generalement ailleurs que dans ces confrontations. A la peripherie, les affrontements operent silencieusement au sein du mouvement de liberation nationale, sans meme toujours avoir une conscience claire des objectifs, d’ou certaines formes populistes. Dans l’ensemble, les affrontements qui occupent le devant de la scene sont ceux qui opposent les Etats : le Nord au Sud, l’Ouest a l’Est.

2)    L’affrontement Est-Ouest a ete confondu longtemps avec celui qui oppose le socialisme au capitalisme. La these jdanovienne opere la confusion entre la pretendue nature sociale des regimes (socialistes ou capitalistes) et les politiques exterieures des Etats (alignement sur l’U. R. S. S. ou sur les Etats-Unis). C’est dans le cadre de cette these qu’il s’est revele necessaire, tactiquement, de creer une categorie « intermediate » : les regimes « progressistes », la « voie non capitaliste » ou la « democratie nationale ».

3) La methode marxiste impose qu’on renverse les termes du raisonnement : il faut partir du contenu de classes reel des regimes. Aucune consideration de nature tactique n’autorise a evacuer la question fondamentale de la nature de classes des pays de l’Est et, par la, des objectifs reels de leur politique internationale.

Dans cette optique rectifiee, si l’U. R. S. S. n’est pas socialiste, elle est une puissance qu’il reste a qualifier. Superpuissance sans doute, puisqu’elle seule peut aspirer a une hegemonie mondiale ou au partage du globe avec les Etats-Unis, son seul concurrent militaire. Mais il reste a mieux connaitre les lois et les exigences de son expansion, qui ne sauraient etre necessairement empruntees a ce que nous connaissons des lois du capitalisme, puisqu’il s’agit d’une societe de classe de type nouveau.

4)    La these jdanovienne, qui reste le fondement des theses sovietiques successivement produites au gre des conjonctures de guerre froide, de degel, de coexistence ou de durcissement, remplit des fonctions ideologiques. Elle permet de soumettre les luttes de classes et les luttes anti-imperialistes aux objectifs propres de l’U. R. S. S. Elle aide a confondre dans le conglomerat des « forces progressistes » les forces populaires authentiques et les forces bourgeoises ou neobourgeoises (etatistes) ralliees conjoncturellement aux premieres. En recourant a des concepts elastiques (« socialisme », « forces progressistes »), comparables a ceux utilises par l’adversaire (« liberte », « droits de l’homme »), elle abroge toute strategie au benefice de la seule tactique.

5) Dans la confrontation Nord-Sud, la variete des situations a la peripherie, allant des bureaucraties compradores aux alliances paysannes revolutionnaires, interdit des jugements de type global. Dans la strategie de la revolution ininterrompue par etapes, l’essentiel est la capacite pour les classes exploitees ouvrieres et paysannes de s’exprimer d’une fagon autonome. Alors seulement les exigences tactiques d’alliances internes et externes pourront etre soumises a l’objectif strategique de la transition socialiste. Autrement, les forces populaires resteront l’enjeu des forces reactionnaires locales et des forces exterieures.

G) Il faut toujours replacer l’imperialisme au centre de la reflexion sur le capitalisme contemporain si l’on veut determiner les obstacles qui se dressent actuellement devant le socialisme.

1)    Or, l’obstacle essentiel, c’est la difficulte d’un desengagement, condition necessaire d’un developpement des forces productives a la peripherie. Mais, fagonnees autour du surplus imperialiste, les societes du centre, dans leur composition sociale comme dans les avantages tires de leur acces aux ressources naturelles du globe, congoivent mal la necessite d’une restructuration globale. En temoignent les experiences recentes du Portugal et de l’ltalie.

2)    Le processus de depassement des rapports capitalistes par rupture du niveau de centralisation du surplus correspondant aux forces productives les plus avancees engendre naturellement une serie de difficultes connues : possibilites de regressions partielles, de restaurations, etc. Mais il est necessaire aussi d’offrir une issue alternative definie en termes internationaux, pour briser les impasses des isolements nationaux et rendre possible une transition socialiste a partir des maillons faibles de la chaine imperialiste centrale. Cette solution devrait aussi accelerer le developpement de rapports socialistes dans les zones de la peripherie sorties du systeme et faciliter la constitution d’une premiere etape anti-imperialiste de la transition pour des regions de la peripherie qui n’ont pas encore brise leurs liens de dependance.

La strategie de l’alliance socialiste Europe du Sud-monde arabe-Afrique s’inscrit dans cette perspective (91-1, 91-2). Malheureusement il s’agit la d’un projet mal compris par les uns et les autres. A l’heure actuelle, apres les timides velleites ambigues des annees 1970-75, la bourgeoisie de l’Europe du Sud a choisi au contraire le ralliement a l’Europe germano-americaine.

H) L’analyse du systeme imperialiste et de sa crise que nous avons proposee

appelle quelques derniers commentaires en forme de questions.

1) La sous-estimation systematique, quand ce n’est pas l’oubli pur et simple, de la dimension imperialiste du capitalisme reduit le mouvement ouvrier et socialiste a l’impuissance. C’est cette impuissance que tente de compenser le discours ouvrieriste. On clame que seules les classes ouvrieres « mures » seraient porteuses de l’avenir socialiste, oubliant les enseignements les plus clairs de l’histoire : les trois grands moments de l’histoire revolutionnaire de notre epoque — la Commune de Paris, 1917, la revolution culturelle — sont en effet l’reuvre de classes ouvrieres en formation. S’il cesse d’etre simplement demagogique, ce discours risque de devenir simplement gauchiste — avec la connotation que Lenine donne a ce mot — quand il est repris par les representants les plus avances de la classe ouvriere occidentale, l ’operaismo (92) italien.

Ignorer ou sous-estimer l’imperialisme, c’est finalement substituer une vision etapiste du developpement du capitalisme a celle du developpement inegal. C’est refuser la possibilite historique d’une strategie de revolution ininterrompue par etapes. C’est s’obnubiler sur le developpement du capitalisme a la peripherie, en oubliant son caractere peripherique. Et, logiquement, cet oubli doit conduire a attendre l’achevement du developpement du capitalisme a l’echelle mondiale pour poser la question du socialisme. Derriere cette erreur se profile la reduction du marxisme aux dimensions d’une ideologie ouvriere, alors qu’il est la science de la revolution des exploites et de la liberation de l’homme. Sans doute sa decouverte eut-elle ete impossible sans le capitalisme et le monde ouvrier. Mais il a permis de renouer avec la tradition revolutionnaire de tous les temps, devenant ainsi l’outil, a l’epoque imperialiste, de l’alliance ouvriere et paysanne.

2)    L’experience historique de la lutte des classes montre que des rapports de production qui sont devenus une entrave au developpement des forces productives se desagregent sous les coups de la revolte des classes opprimees. Mais ces coups peuvent faire le jeu d’une nouvelle classe montante, qui met en place les rapports de production nouveaux, s’empare de l’Etat et se substitue a l’ancienne classe exploiteuse. C’est ainsi que la lutte des paysans contre les feodaux a fait le jeu de la bourgeoisie.

L’experience sovietique confirme cette possibilite : les coups portes par la classe ouvriere a la bourgeoisie y ont fait le jeu d’une classe nouvelle bureaucratique-technocratique, classe dominante du nouveau mode de production etatique. En Occident, les nouvelles couches issues de la differentiation au sein du proletariat — aristocratie ouvriere et technocratie — ne nourrissent-elles pas egalement le projet d’un mode etatique ? La social-democratie n’en est-elle pas l’illustration partielle ? Et l’eurocommunisme, conglomerat encore mal defini de tendances partiellement contradictoires, ne contient-il pas deja une tendance social-democrate ancienne (gestion du capital avec le soutien de l’aristocratie ouvriere) et une tendance social-democrate nouvelle, « a la suedoise » (substitution de l’aristocratie ouvriere et de la technocratie a la bourgeoisie), conduisant au mode etatique ? Seule peut-etre une tendance autogestionnaire, remontant aux sources anciennes de l’anarcho-syndicalisme, y exprime veritablement la revolte des travailleurs.

Il resterait a savoir quelles sont les lois du developpement de ce nouveau mode et ses contradictions specifiques. Si devolution, possible, vers un mode etatique implique la desagregation du systeme du marche mondial caracteristique des trente dernieres annees, il semble impliquer aussi le renforcement de tendances nationales plus ou moins autarciques. Devra-t-on interpreter cette contradiction comme entrainant un retour vers des modeles comparables, en plus structures et plus « etatistes-ouvriers », a ceux de l’entre-deux-guerres ? Ou faut-il interpreter cette tendance comme progressiste ? De la meme maniere pour les pays du centre que pour ceux de la peripherie ?

3)    La question de l’affrontement capitalisme/socialisme apparait dans toute sa complexite reelle, porteuse d’issues tres differentes. Mais il ne faut jamais cesser de distinguer la contradiction fondamentale d’un systeme (aujourd’hui, la contradiction capital/travail) de la contradiction principale dans laquelle elle s’exprime et qui peut etre celle qui oppose, a un moment donne, des nations ou des Etats. Seule l’analyse concrete de la situation permet a chaque moment de caracteriser la periode.

Conclusion

Revolution ou decadence ? Quelques reflexions sur la transition d’un mode de production a un autre

Le mouvement ouvrier et socialiste a vecu sur une vision de la transition socialiste qu’une serie de revolutions dans les pays capitalistes avances devait inaugurer. Des critiques faites par Marx et Engels aux programmes de la social-democratie allemande jusqu’aux conclusions que le bolchevisme a tirees de l’experience de la revolution russe, le mouvement ouvrier et socialiste n’a jamais envisage autrement la question de la transition socialiste a l’echelle mondiale.

Or, depuis trois quarts de siecle, la transformation du monde a emprunte d’autres voies. La perspective revolutionnaire a disparu des horizons de l’Occident avance, tandis que les revolutions socialistes, exclusivement cantonnees a la peripherie du systeme, ouvraient la voie a des developpements suffisamment ambigus pour que certains y voient seulement une etape de l’expansion capitaliste a l’echelle mondiale. L’analyse du systeme en termes de developpement inegal proposee ici s’efforce de donner une reponse differente. Partie du systeme imperialiste contemporain, elle nous a amenes a envisager aussi la nature et la signification du developpement inegal dans les etapes historiques anterieures.

L’histoire comparative des transitions d’un mode de production a un autre invite a poser la question du mode de transition en termes generaux et theoriques. Ainsi, certaines similitudes entre la situation contemporaine et l’epoque de la fin de l’empire romain ont amene certains historiens qui ne se reclament pas du materialisme historique a dresser des paralleles entre les deux situations. En revanche, une certaine interpretation dogmatique du marxisme a occulte la reflexion sur le theme dans les termes du materialisme historique. On parle ainsi de la « decadence de Rome » dans les manuels d’histoire sovietiques, tandis que l’on continue a parler de la « revolution socialiste » comme forme exclusive de la substitution de rapports de production nouveaux aux rapports capitalistes.

Le rapprochement qui suit pretend se situer sur le terrain de l’analyse comparative du contenu et des formes de la crise des rapports de production antiques et capitalistes. Les differences entre ces deux crises justifient-elles leur analyse, l’une en termes de « decadence » et l’autre en termes de « revolution » ?

A) Notre these centrale est qu’il existe un parallelisme certain entre les deux crises. Dans les deux cas, le systeme entre en crise parce que la centralisation du surplus qu’il organise est excessive, c’est-a-dire en avance sur les rapports de production qui le sous-tendent. Le developpement des forces productives a la peripherie du systeme passe alors par l’eclatement de celui-ci et la substitution d’un systeme decentralise de collecte et d’utilisation du surplus.

1) La these la plus repandue au sein du materialisme historique est celle de la succession de trois modes de production dominants : le mode esclavagiste, le mode feodal et le mode capitaliste. Dans ce cadre, la decadence de Rome ne serait que l’expression du passage de l’esclavage au servage. Il resterait a expliquer pourquoi on ne parle pas ici de « revolution feodale », comme on parle de revolution bourgeoise et de revolution socialiste.

Nous avons rejete cette these, que nous estimons occidentalocentrique, au sens qu’elle generalise abusivement les caracteres specifiques de l’histoire de l’Occident, rejetant l’histoire des autres peuples dans la particularite. En choisissant de faire deriver les lois du materialisme historique de l’experience universelle, nous lui avons oppose la these d’un mode precapitaliste unique, le mode tributaire, vers lequel tendent toutes les societes de classes. L’histoire de l’Occident — la construction romaine antique, sa desagregation, la constitution de l’Europe feodale, enfin la cristallisation des Etats absolutistes de l’epoque mercantiliste — traduit ainsi, dans ses particularites, la meme tendance fondamentale qui s’exprime ailleurs dans la construction moins discontinue des Etats tributaires acheves, dont la Chine est l’expression la plus forte. Dans notre these, d’une part, le mode esclavagiste n’a pas de statut universel comme le mode tributaire et le mode capitaliste : il est particulier et apparait en relation etroite avec l’extension de rapports marchands; d’autre part, le mode feodal est une forme primitive, inachevee, du mode tributaire.

La construction romaine, puis sa desagregation, apparaissent dans cette hypothese comme une tentative trop precoce de construction tributaire. Le niveau de developpement des forces productives n’exigeait pas une centralisation tributaire a l’echelle de l’empire romain. Cette premiere tentative avortee allait donc etre suivie d’un passage force par la phase de l’emiettement feodal, a partir duquel devait se reconstituer une centralisation dans le cadre des monarchies absolutistes de l’Occident. Alors seulement le mode de production en Occident approchera le modele tributaire acheve. C’est d’ailleurs uniquement a partir de ce stade que le niveau de developpement des forces productives en Occident atteindra celui du mode tributaire acheve de la Chine imperiale, et cette coincidence n’est sans doute pas fortuite.

Le retard de l’Occident, qui s’exprime par l’avortement romain et l’emiettement feodal, a constitue en definitive son avantage historique. C’est en effet la combinaison specifique d’elements du mode tributaire antique et des modes communautaires barbares qui caracterise le feodalisme et lui a donne sa flexibilite. Celle-ci rend compte de la rapidite avec laquelle l’Europe traverse la phase tributaire achevee, depassant vite le niveau de developpement des forces productives de l’Orient qu’elle venait de rattraper, et debouchant sur le capitalisme. Cette flexibilite et cette rapidite contrastent avec la rigidite et la lenteur relatives de devolution dans les modes tributaires acheves de l’Orient.

2) Le cas romain-occidental n’est sans doute pas le seul exemple d’avortement de la construction tributaire. Dans des conditions specifiques differentes, nous croyons reperer au moins trois autres cas de ce type : le cas byzantin-arabe-ottoman, le cas indien, le cas mongol. Chaque fois, les tentatives de mise en place de systemes de centralisation tributaire ont trop largement precede les exigences du developpement des forces productives pour pouvoir s’installer durablement. Sans doute les formes de ces centralisations ont-elles ete dans chaque cas des combinaisons specifiques differentes de moyens etatiques, para-feodaux et marchands : dans l’Etat islamique, par exemple, c’est la centralisation marchande qui a joue le role decisif; les avortements indiens successifs sont a mettre en relation avec le contenu de l’ideologie hindouiste, que nous avons opposee au confucianisme; quant a la centralisation de l’empire de Gengis Khan, elle fut, comme on sait, de tres courte duree.

3) Le systeme imperialiste contemporain est, lui aussi, un systeme de centralisation du surplus, a l’echelle mondiale. Cette centralisation opere sur la base des lois fondamentales du mode capitaliste et dans les conditions de sa domination sur les modes precapitalistes de la peripherie soumise. Nous avons formule la loi de l’accumulation du capital a l’echelle mondiale comme forme d’expression de la loi de la valeur operant a cette echelle. Le systeme imperialiste de centralisation de la valeur se caracterise par l’acceleration de l’accumulation et du developpement des forces productives au centre du systeme, tandis qu’a sa peripherie ceux-ci sont handicapes et deformes. Developpement et sous-developpement sont l’endroit et l’envers de la meme medaille.

On comprend alors que le developpement ulterieur des forces productives a la peripherie doive passer par l’eclatement du systeme imperialiste de centralisation du surplus. Une phase necessaire de decentralisation, la construction de la transition socialiste nationale, doit preceder la reunification a un niveau plus eleve de developpement que constituerait la societe planetaire sans classes.

B) Cette these centrale entraine plusieurs consequences concernant la theorie

et la strategie de la transition socialiste.

1) La transition socialiste a la peripherie se confond avec la liberation nationale. Celle-ci s’est revelee impossible sous la direction de la bourgeoisie locale. Elle devient donc une etape democratique du processus de la revolution ininterrompue par etapes sous la direction des masses ouvrieres et paysannes. Cette fusion des objectifs de liberation nationale et du socialisme engendre a son tour une serie de problemes nouveaux dont il faut prendre la mesure. Car l’accent est mis tantot sur l’un tantot sur l’autre des deux aspects; et, de ce fait, le mouvement reel de la societe comporte des alternances de progres et de reculs, des ambivalences et des alienations, notamment nationalistes. La encore le parallele peut etre fait avec l’attitude des Barbares a l’egard de l’empire romain, qui comportait elle aussi ses ambiguites, et notamment l’imitation formelle, parfois servile, du modele romain contre lequel on s’insurgeait.

Parallelement, le caractere parasitaire de la societe centrale s’accentue. A Rome, le tribut imperial corrompt la plebe et paralyse sa revolte. Dans les societes du centre imperialiste, une fraction croissante de la population beneficie d’emplois improductifs et de positions privilegiees concentres ici par les effets de la division international inegale du travail. La perspective d’un desengagement a l’egard du systeme imperialiste et la formation d’une alliance anti-imperialiste capable de renverser l’alliance hegemonique et d’amorcer la transition socialiste sont, de ce fait, rendues plus difficiles.

2)    L’amorce de rapports de production nouveaux apparait plus aisement a la peripherie qu’au centre du systeme. Dans l’empire romain, les rapports feodaux se fraient leur chemin en Gaule et en Germanie, alors qu’ils pietinent en Italie et en Orient. C’est Rome qui invente le colonat, lequel se substitue a l’esclavage. Mais la seigneurie se developpe ailleurs et, en Italie meme, les rapports feodaux ne s’epanouiront veritablement jamais.

Aujourd’hui, le sentiment de revolte latente contre les rapports capitalistes est tres fort au centre; mais il est impuissant. On veut « changer la vie », mais on ne parvient meme pas a changer le gouvernement. Aussi les avancees se font-elles dans le domaine de la vie sociale plus que dans ceux qui concernent l’organisation de la production et de l’Etat. La revolution silencieuse des mreurs, l’eclatement de la famille, l’effondrement des valeurs bourgeoises, temoignent de cet aspect contradictoire du processus. A la peripherie, les mreurs et les idees sont souvent beaucoup moins avancees, mais on parvient neanmoins a mettre en place des Etats socialistes.

3)    La tradition du marxisme vulgaire a opere une reduction mecaniste de la dialectique du changement social. La revolution — dont le contenu objectif est l’abolition des rapports de production anciens et l’etablissement de rapports nouveaux, condition d’un developpement ulterieur des forces productives — est assimilee a une loi naturelle : l’application dans le domaine de la societe de la loi du passage de la quantite a la qualite. La lutte des classes est le revelateur de cette necessite objective : seule l’avant-garde — le Parti — est au-dessus de la melee, fait et domine l’histoire, est desalienee; le moment politique qui definit l’instant revolutionnaire est celui par lequel cette avant-garde s’empare de l’Etat. Le leninisme lui-meme ne s’est pas totalement

departi de cette reduction positiviste du marxisme de la IIe Internationale.

Cette theorie qui separe l’avant-garde de la classe n’est pas transposable aux revolutions du passe. La revolution bourgeoise elle-meme n’a pas revetu cette forme : ici, la bourgeoisie a capte a son profit la lutte des paysans contre les feodaux. L’ideologie qui lui a permis de le faire, loin d’etre un moyen de manipulation, etait elle-meme alienante. Dans ce sens, il n’y a pas eu de « revolution bourgeoise » — le terme est lui-meme un produit de l’ideologie bourgeoise — mais seulement une lutte de classes dirigee par la bourgeoisie, a la rigueur, parfois, une revolution paysanne captee par la bourgeoisie. On peut encore moins parler de « revolution feodale »; le passage ici s’est fait dans l’inconscience.

La revolution socialiste serait d’un autre type, supposant la conscience desalienee, parce qu’elle viserait pour la premiere fois l’abolition de toute exploitation et non la substitution de formes nouvelles aux formes anciennes de Sexploitation. Mais cela n’est possible que si l’ideologie dont elle se nourrit parvient a etre autre chose que la conscience des exigences du developpement des forces productives. Il n’est pas dit en effet que le mode de production etatique, comme forme nouvelle de rapports d’exploitation, n’est pas une reponse possible aux exigences de ce developpement.

Ce sont les hommes qui font leur histoire. Ni les animaux ni les etres inanimes ne font leur evolution; ils la subissent. Le concept de praxis est propre a la societe, comme expression de la synthese du determinisme et de l’intervention humaine. La relation dialectique infrastructure/superstructure lui est egalement propre et n’a pas de correspondant dans la nature. Cette relation n’est pas unilaterale : la superstructure n’est pas le reflet des exigences de l’infrastructure. S’il en etait ainsi, la societe serait toujours alienee et on ne voit pas comment elle pourrait parvenir a se liberer.

C’est pourquoi nous proposons de distinguer deux types qualitativement differents de transition d’un mode a un autre. Lorsque le passage se fait dans l’inconscience, ou par la conscience alienee, c’est-a-dire lorsque l’ideologie qui agit les classes ne permet pas de maitriser le processus du changement, celui-ci apparait comme operant d’une maniere analogue a un changement naturel, l’ideologie faisant partie de cette nature. A ce type de passage nous reservons l’expression de « modele de decadence ». En revanche, si l’ideologie parvient a donner la dimension totale et reelle du changement voulu, et alors seulement, on peut parler de revolution.

4) La transition socialiste dans laquelle notre epoque est deja engagee estelle du type decadent ou revolutionnaire ?

Il est sans doute encore impossible de repondre a cette question d’une maniere definitive. Par certains de ses aspects, la transformation du monde contemporain revet incontestablement un caractere revolutionnaire au sens defini ci-dessus. La Commune de Paris, 1917, la revolution chinoise (et particulierement la revolution culturelle) ont ete des moments d’intense conscience sociale desalienee.

Mais ne sommes-nous pas engages dans un autre type de transition ? Les difficultes qui rendent le desengagement des pays imperialistes presque impossible a penser aujourd’hui, et ses effets negatifs sur les pays de la peripherie engages dans la voie socialiste (restaurations capitalistes possibles, evolutions vers un mode etatique, regressions, alienations nationalistes, etc.) remettent en question le vieux modele bolchevique.

Les uns en prennent leur parti et considerent que notre epoque n’est pas celle de la transition socialiste mais de l’expansion mondiale du capitalisme, qui parti de ce « petit coin d’Europe », commencerait seulement a s’etendre vers le sud et l’est. Au terme de ce transfert, la phase imperialiste apparaitrait, non comme le dernier stade, le stade supreme, du capitalisme, mais comme une phase de transition vers le capitalisme universel. Et meme si l’on continue a penser que la these leniniste de l’imperialisme reste vraie et que la liberation nationale fait partie de la revolution socialiste et non bourgeoise, des exceptions, c’est-a-dire l’apparition de nouveaux centres capitalistes, seraient-elles possibles ? Cette these met aussi l’accent sur les restaurations ou les evolutions vers le mode etatique dans les pays de l’Est pour qualifier de processus objectifs d’expansion capitaliste ce qui n’aurait ete que des pseudo-revolutions socialistes : le marxisme apparaitrait ici comme une ideologie alienante masquant le caractere vrai de ces developpements.

Pour ceux qui se rangent a cette opinion, il faudra donc attendre qu’on ait atteint un niveau de developpement des forces productives generalisant a l’ensemble du monde le niveau entrevu dans les centres actuels pour que la question de l’abolition des classes soit vraiment a l’ordre du jour. Les Europeens devraient done laisser se faire l’Europe supranationale, de maniere a voir la superstructure etatique ajustee aux forces productives. Puis il faudra sans doute attendre de voir l’Etat planetaire constitue, correspondant au niveau des forces productives homogeneise au plan mondial, pour voir les conditions objectives de son depassement enfin reunies...

D’autres, et nous sommes de ceux-la, voient les choses differemment. La revolution ininterrompue par etapes est toujours a l’ordre du jour pour la peripherie. Les restaurations ne sont pas fatales au cours de la transition socialiste. Et les ruptures du front imperialiste ne sont pas a exclure au niveau des maillons faibles du centre.

Orientations bibliographiques

La bibliographie qui suit n’a pas la pretention d’etre exhaustive. Elle vise

seulement a aider le lecteur a retrouver les ouvrages dont il lui serait utile de

garder les theses presentes a l’esprit en lisant ce livre.

1 - Les formations communautaires 10 - Ouvrages fondamentaux

1)    K. Marx, Grundisse, 2 bis. Supplement au chapitre du « Capital » : Formes anterieures a la production capitaliste, 10-18, 1974.

2)    F. Engels, L'origine de la famille, de la propriete privee et de l’Etat, Editions Sociales.

3)    Lewis H. Morgan, La societe archaique, Anthropos.

4)    Francois Pouillon et autres, L‘anthropologie economique, Maspero, 1976, notamment chap. 3, 4 et 5 : F. Pouillon, Alain Marie et Roger Meunier.

5)    Claude Meillassoux, Terrains et theories, Anthropos, 1977 (« L’essai d’interpretation du phenomene economique dans les societes traditionnelles d’autosubsistance » repris ici resume l’experience tiree par l’auteur de son Anthropologie economique des Gouro de Cote-d’Ivoire, Mouton, 1964).

6)    Pierre Philippe Rey, Les alliances de classes, Maspero, 1973; Colonialisme, neo-colonialisme et transition au capitalisme, Maspero, 1971; « Le transfert de surtravail de la paysannerie vers le capitalisme », L’Homme et la societe, 1977.

7)    Emmanuel Terray, Le marxisme face aux societes « primitives », Maspero,

1969.

8)    Catherine Coquery-Vidrovitch, « Recherches sur un mode de production africain », C. E. R. M, 1974.

9)    Karl Polanyi et autres, Les systemes economiques dans l’histoire et la theorie, Larousse, 1975.

10)    A. V. Chayanov, The Theory of Peasant Economy, presentation de D.

Thorner, Illinois, 1960.

11)    Ester Boserup, Evolution agraire et pression demographique, Flammarion, 1970.

12)    Lawrence Krader, The Ethnological Notebooks of Karl Marx, Van Gorcum, 1974.

13)    C. Bennetti, J. Cartelier, C. Berthomien, Economie classique, economie vulgaire, Maspero, 1975.

11 - La these du mode de production domestique

1)    Marshall Sahlins, Age de pierre, age d’abondance, Paris, 1976 (premiere edition anglaise, 1965-72).

2)    Claude Meillassoux, Femmes, greniers et capitaux, Maspero, 1975.

3)    S. Amin, I. Eynard, B. Stuckey, « Feminisme et lutte de classes », Minuit 7, 1974.

12 - L’esclavage dans les formations communautaires

1)    L’esclavage en Afrique precoloniale (Dix-sept etudes presentees par C. Meillassoux), Maspero, 1975.

2)    Samir Amin, Imperialisme et sous-developpement en Afrique, Anthropos, 1977.

13 - Autres lectures et sources

1)    Les africanistes frangais, notamment Gerard Althabe, Marc Auge, Jean Copans, Georges Dupre, Henri Raulin (bibliographie in F. Pouillon, op. cit.).

2)    L’anthropologie non marxiste : Georges Balandier, Paul Bohannan, George Dalton, Raymond Firth, Melville Herskovits, Claude Levi-Strauss, Lucy Mair, Bronislav Malinowski, Metraux et Radcliffe-Brown (bibliographie in F. Pouillon, op. cit.).

3)    La nouvelle ecole d’anthropologie marxiste anglaise, en voie de constitution. Barry Hindess et Paul Hirst, Precapitalist Modes of Production, Londres, 1975, et les travaux publies dans Economy and Society.

4)    Les historiens des societes africaines precoloniales et contemporaines : Abir et Levi (domaine ethiopien), Bovill (commerce transsaharien), Crowder (Afrique de l’Ouest), Coquery (Afrique centrale), Ranger (Afrique australe), Oliver (Afrique orientale), Gray et Birmingham (commerce a longue distance). Et les sociologues : Dike (delta du Niger), Nicolas (Haoussa) et Vansina (Congo).

Voir la bibliographie du Developpement inegal, notamment pp. 356-357. Voir egalement L’agriculture africaine et le capitalisme, textes presentes par S. Amin, Anthropos, 1974, notamment les etudes de Founou, de la Tour, Weber, etc.

5)    Gordon Childe, La naissance de la civilisation, Gonthier, 1964.

6)    Sur la domination formelle du capital, Claude Faure, Servolin et autres, P. P. Rey et Founou. Voir la bibliographie in Samir Amin, « La structures de classes du systeme imperialiste », L’homme et la societe, 1977. Voir egalement plus loin rubrique 73.

2 - Antiquite classique et esclavage

20    - Grece antique

1)    Umberto Melotti, Marx sul mondo antico, Milan, 1970.

2)    Jean-Pierre Vernant, Les origines de la pensee grecque, P. U. F. 1962.

3)    P. Vidal-Naquet et M. Austin, Economies et Societes en Grece ancienne, Armand Colin, 1972.

4)    Victor Ehrenberg, L’Etatgrec, Maspero, 1975.

5)    Moses Finley, Les premiers temps de la Grece, Maspero, 1973.

6)    Moses Finley, L’economie antique, Minuit, 1973.

21    - Rome antique

1)    Jean Gage, Les classes sociales dans l’Empire romain, Payot, 1971.

2)    Paul Petit, Histoire generale de l’Empire romain, Seuil, 1974.

3)    Canto Mazzarino, La fin du monde antique, Gallimard, 1973.

22 - Autres lectures

1)    Recherches internationales, Formes d’exploitation du travail dans l'antiquite classique (contributions sovietiques et Est-europeennes), n° 84,

1970.

2)    Eugene Genovese, L’economiepolitique de l’esclavage, Maspero, 1968.

3 - Les societes tributaires, le mode de production asiatique

30 - Le debat sur le « mode de production asiatique »

1)    Karl Wittfogel, Le despotisme oriental, Minuit, 1965, introduction de Pierre Vidal-Naquet, retiree de l’edition suivante a la demande de Wittfogel.

2)    Ferenc Tokei, Sur le mode de production asiatique, Budapest, Akademiai Kiado, 1966.

3)    C. E. R. M., Sur les societes precapitalistes, Ed. Sociales, 1975, textes de Marx, Engels, Lenine; presentation de Maurice Godelier.

4)    C. E. R. M., Sur le mode de production asiatique, Ed. Sociales, 1974, textes de Jean Chesneaux, Maurice Godelier, Jean Suret-Canale, Pierre Boileau, Charles Parain, Helene Antoniadis-Bibicar, G. A. Melekechvili, Ion Banu, Catherine Coquery, etc.

5)    C. E. R. M., Sur le feodalisme, Ed. Sociales, 1974, seconde partie, textes sur le Maghreb de Rene Galissot, Andre Nouschi, Jean Poncet, Andre Prenant, Lucette Valensi et Charles Parain.

6)    Recherches internationales, Les premieres societes de classes et le mode de production asiatique, n° 57-58, 1967.

7)    K. Marx, Formen... Presentation de Eric Hobsbawn (ed. anglaise); egalement: Anonyme, Succession des formes de production et de societe dans la theorie marxiste, le Fil du temps, juin 1974, EDI. Ce texte, dont l’edition italienne est parue en 1957, est a l’origine de l’inspiration de Tokei.

8)    Gianni Sofri, Il modo di produzione asiatico, Einaudi, 1969.

9)    Lawrence Krader, The Asiatic Mode of Production, Van Gorcum, 1975.

31 - Les societes tributaires non europeennes, les domaines chinois et

indien

1)    Marx et la Chine, Recueil de textes, 10-18.

2)    Etienne Balaczs, La bureaucratie celeste, Gallimard, 1969.

3)    Chi Chaoting, Le zone economiche chiave nella storia della Cina, Einaudi,

1972.

4)    Boris Vladimirstsov, La feodalite nomade (Obchtchestvennyi Stroy Mongolov, Leningrad, 1934); Gengis-Khan, Maisonneuve, 1948.

5)    Chantai Lemercier-Quelquejay, La paix mongole, Questions d’histoire, Flammarion, n° 13.

6)    Le Thank Khoi, Le Viet-nam, Histoire et civilisation, Minuit, 1955.

7)    Jean Chesneaux, Mouvements populaires et societes secretes en Chine aux XIXe et XXe siecles, Maspero, 1970; Le mouvement paysan chinois, Seuil,

1976.

8)    Jacques Gernet, Le monde chinois, Armand Colin, 1972.

9)    Damodar Kosambi, Culture et civilisation de l’Inde ancienne, Maspero,

1968.

10)    Louis Dumont, Homo hierarchicus, Gallimard, 1967.

11)    C. Meillassoux, « Y a-t-il des castes aux Indes », in Terrains et theories, Anthropos, 1977.

32 - Les domaines byzantin, arabe et ottoman

1)    Louis Brehier, Les institutions de l’empire byzantin, Albin Michel, 1969.

2)    Kostas Vergopoulos, Le capitalisme difforme et la nouvelle question agraire, Maspero, 1977.

3)    Maurice Lombard, L’islam dans sa premiere grandeur, VIIe-XIe siecles, Flammarion, 1971.

4)    Xavier de Planhol, Les fondements geographiques de l’histoire de l’islam, Flammarion, 1968.

5)    Claude Cahen, L’islam des origines aux debuts de l’empire ottoman, Bordas, 1970.

6)    Andre Miguel, L'islam et sa civilisation, Armand Colin, 1968.

7)    Maxime Rodinson, Mahomet, Seuil, 1968.

8)    S. Amin, La nation arabe, Minuit, 1977.

9)    Yves Lacoste, Ibn Khaldoun, Maspero, 1965 (et Ibn Khaldoun, Al Muqaddima, Centre pedagogique maghrebin, Hachette, 1965.

10)    Charles Issawi (ed.), The Economic Hisory of the Middle East, 18001914, Chicago University Press, 1966.

11)    M. A. Cook (ed.), Studies in the Economic History of the Middle East, Oxford University Press, 1970.

12)    C. E. R. M. Sur le feodalisme, Ed. Sociales, 1974, 2e partie (contributions de Galissot, Poncet, Nouschi, Valensi et Prenant).

13)    Abdellatif Benachenhou, La formation du sous-developpement en Algerie, O. P. U., Alger, 1976.

14)    Abdallah Laroui, Histoire du Maghreb, Maspero, 1970.

15)    Abdallah Laroui, L’ideologie arabe contemporaine, Maspero, 1965.

16)    Mostafa Lacheraf, Algerie, nation et societe, Maspero, 1965.

17)    Lucette Valensi, Le Maghreb avant la prise d’Alger, Flammarion, 1969.

18)    Marx et l’Algerie, textes presentes par Galissot, 10-18.

19)    Hassan Ahmad Ibrahim, Mohamad Ali fil Sudan, Khartoum, 1975.

20)    Sobhi Wahida, Fi Ugul Al Masala al Migriya, Le Caire, 1950.

21)    Gamal Hamdam, Shakhsiya Migr, Le Caire, 1970.

33 - Autres domaines et divers

1)    Vittorio Lanternari, Les mouvements religieux des peuples opprimes, Maspero, 1973.

2)    Voir aussi les bibliographies du Developpement inegal et de La nation arabe.

4 - Le feodalisme europeen

1)    Perry Anderson, Passages de l’antiquite au feodalisme, Maspero, 1977.

2)    C. E. R. M., Sur le feodalisme, premiere partie, contributions de Parrain, Vilar, Goblot, Hincker, Cardoso, Soboul, Lemarchand, Ed. Sociales, 1974.

3)    Georges Duby, L’economie rurale et la vie des campagnes dans l’Occident medieval, Flammarion, 1977.

4)    Georges Duby, Guerriers etpaysans, Gallimard, 1973.

5)    Marc Bloch, Les caracteres originaux de I’histoire rurale frangaise, Armand Colin, 1968.

6)    Marc Bloch, La societe feodale, Albin Michel, 1968.

7)    Recherches internationales, Le deuxieme servage en Europe centrale et orientale, n° 63-64, 1970.

8)    P. Dockes et B. Rosier, Questions aux historiens, Cahiers n° 11, 1977, Analyse, epistemologie, histoire, Universite de Lyon.

9)    Lynn-White, Medieval Technology and Social Change, Oxford University Press, 1962.

10)    Jacques Le Gofi, Le millenarisme, Flammarion.

11)    Maurice Dommanget, La Jacquerie, Maspero, 1972.

12)    E. J. Hobsbawn, Les bandits, Maspero, 1972.

13)    Georges Duby, L’an mil, Archives, Julliard.

5 - La transition mercantiliste et la revolution bourgeoise 50 - Ouvrages fondamentaux

1)    Perry Anderson, Lineages of the Absolutist State, Londres, 1975.

2)    M. Dobb et P. Sweezy, Du feodalisme au capitalisme : problemes de la transition, Maspero, 1977.

3)    Maurice Dobb, Etudes sur le developpement du capitalisme, Maspero,

1969.

4)    Immanuel Wallerstein, The Modem World System, New York, 1973.

5)    Fernand Braudel, La Mediterranee et le monde mediterraneen a l’epoque de Philippe II, Armand Colin, 1949.

6)    Pierre Vilar, Or et monnaie dans l’histoire, Flammarion, 1974.

7)    Witold Kula, Theorie economique du systeme feodal, Mouton, 1970.

8)    Frederic Mauro, L’expansion europeenne 1600-1870; Le XVIe siecle europeen, Clio, 1964.

9)    Christopher Hill, Le monde a l’envers, Payot, 1977.

10)    Andre Gunder Frank, L’accumulation mondiale 1700-1800, Calmann-Levy, 1977.

11)    Oliver Cox, Capitalism as a System, New York, 1964.

12)    Eric Williams, Capitalisme et esclavage, Presence africaine, 1968.

13)    Pierre Chaunu, L ’Amerique et les Ameriques, Armand Colin, 1964.

14)    T. S. Ashton, La revolution industrielle, Plon, 1955.

15)    Pierre Dockes, L’espace dans lapensee economique, Flammarion, 1977.

16)    Philippe Joutard, Les Camisards, Archives, Julliard.

17)    Yves Marie Berci, Croquants et Nus-pieds, Archives, Julliard.

18)    John Merrington, in Rodney Hilton (ed.), The Transition from Feudalism to Capitalism, N. L. B., 1976.

51 - La revolution frangaise

1)    Albert Soboul, Precis d’histoire de la revolution frangaise, Ed. Sociales, 1962.

2)    Albert Mathiez, La revolution frangaise.

3)    Daniel Guerin, La lutte des classes sous la premiere republique 1793-97, Gallimard, 1969.

4)    Florence Gauthier, La voie paysanne dans la revolution frangaise, Maspero, 1975; Du feodalisme au capitalisme, la paysannerie frangaise a la veille de la Revolution, l’exemple Picard, Maspero, 1977.

5)    Albert Soboul, Problemes paysans de la revolution 1789-1848, Maspero,

1976.

6)    Eric Hobsbawn, The Age of Revolution, Europe 1789-1848, Londres, 1974.

7)    Marcel Lidove, Les Vendeens de 93, Seuil.

6 - La question nationale en Europe, 1840-1914

60 - Austro-marxistes et travaux les concernant, histoire europeenne

1)    Miklos Molnar, Marx, Engels et la politique internationale, Idees, Gallimard, 1975.

2)    Yvon Bourdet, Otto Bauer et la revolution, E. D. I., 1968.

3)    G. Haupt, M. Lowy, C. Weill, Les marxistes et la question nationale 18481914, Maspero, 1974; textes de Kautsky, Luxembourg, Renner, Otto Bauer, Josef Strasser, Pannekoek.

4)    Josef Strasser, Anton Pannekoek, Nation et lutte de classes, 10-18, 1977.

5)    Histoire du marxisme contemporain, 4 vols., Institut Feltrinelli, 10-18, 1976, article d’Agnelli.

6)    Salomon F. Bloom, The World of Nations, A Study of the National Implications in the Work of K. Marx, Columbia University Press, 1941.

7)    Horace B. Davis, Nationalism and Socialism, M. Press 1967.

8)    Eric Hobsbawn, The Age of Capital, 1848-1875, Londres, 1976.

9)    Voir egalement les bibliographies in Pierre Souyri, Le marxisme apres Marx, Flammarion, 1970, et Kostas Papaioannou, Marx et les marxistes, Flammarion, 1972.

61 - L’unite italienne

1)    Gramsci, La questione meridionale, Einaudi.

2)    E. Sereni, Il capitalismo nelle campagne 1860-1900, Turin, 1968.

3)    Rosario Romeo, Risorgimento e capitalismo, Bari, 1968.

4)    Sergio Romano, Histoire de l’ltalie du Risorgimento a nos jours, Seuil,

1977.

5)    Nicola Zitara, L’unita d’ltalia, Nascita di una colonia, Jaca, 1970; Il proletariato esterno, Jaca, 1972.

6)    Capecelatroe Carlo, Contro la questione meridionale, Savelli, 1972.

7)    Benedetto Croce, Histoire de l'Europe au XIXe siecle, Idees, Gallimard,

1973.

62 - Autres aspects de la question nationale dans les centres developpes

1) Yannick Guin, Histoire de la Bretagne de 1789 a nos jours, Maspero,

2)    Marcel Lidove, Les Vendeens de 93, Le Temps qui court n° 41.

3)    Maurice Goldring, L’Irlande, ideologie d’une revolution nationaliste, Ed. Sociales, 1975.

4)    Pierre Vilar, Catalogne et regionalisme en Espagne, Flammarion, 1969.

5)    Gerald Brenan, Le labyrinthe espagnol, Ruedo Iberico, Paris, 1962.

6)    Elise Marienstras, Les mythes fondateurs de la nation americaine, Maspero, 1975.

7)    F. et C. Masnata, Pouvoir, societe et politique aux Etats-Unis, Payot, 1970.

8)    Ertel, Fabre et Marienstras, En marge, les minorites aux Etats-Unis, Maspero, 1971.

7 - L'imperialisme et la liberation nationale 70 - L’imperialisme : theorie generale et concepts fondamentaux

a - Bref rappel des ecrits de Marx et Engels sur les societes colonisees

1)    Umberto Melotti, Marx sul Terzo Mondo, Milan, 1971.

2)    Shlomo Avneri, Karl Marx on Colonialism and Modernization, Anchor, 1969.

3)    Voir aussi la bibliographie du Developpement inegal.

b - Ouvrages de base « classiques », sources et presentations de vulgarisation

1)    J. A. Hobson, The Evolution of Modem Capitalism, Londres, 1894.

2)    R. Hilferding, Le capital financier, Minuit.

3)    Lenine, L’imperialisme, stade supreme du capitalisme.

4)    R. Luxemburg, L’accumulation du capital, Maspero.

5)    Nicolas Boukharine, L’imperialisme et l’accumulation du capital; L’economie mondiale et l’imperialisme, Anthropos, 1977.

6)    J. Valier, Sur l’imperialisme, Maspero.

7)    J. Rosen et J. R. Kurth, Testing theories of Economic Imperialism, Toronto, 1974. Egalement les ouvrages principaux du courant trotskiste et

trotskisant predominant dans la litterature anglaise : T. Kemp, Barrat-Brown, R. Owen, B. Sutcliffe, G. Kay, M. Kidron, etc.; par exemple : R. Owen & B. Sutcliffe (ed. ), Studies in the Theory of Imperialism, Londres, 1972; M. Barrat-Brown, The Economics of Imperialism, Penguin, 1974.

c - Le mouvement ouvrier et la question coloniale

1)    J. Staline, La question nationale et coloniale.

2)    G. Haupt et autres, La IIe Internationale et l'Orient, Cujas, 1957.

3)    E. Colotti Pischel et C. Robertazzi, L’Internationale communiste et les problemes coloniaux 1919-65, Mouton, 1968.

4) Manifestes, theses et resolutions des quatre premiers congres de l'lnternationale communiste, 1919-23, Maspero, 1975; Le premier congres des peuples d’Orient, Bakou, 1920, Maspero, 1971.

5)    M. Carrere d’Encausse et S. Schramm, Le marxisme et l'Asie, 1853-1964, Armand Colin, 1975.

6)    Gregoire Madjarian, La question coloniale et la politique du P. C. F., 1944-47, Maspero, 1977.

7)    Bibliographies in Souyri et Papaioannou (op. cit.).

d - Pour un resume de nos positions, voir :

S. Amin, « A propos de la critique » (L’Homme et la societe n° 39-40, 1976);

« La strategie de la revolution socialiste dans le tiers monde » in

Connaissance du tiers monde, 10-18, 1977.

71 - Le systeme mondial et l’imperialisme aujourd’hui

a - Ouvrages generaux

1)    Harry Magdoff, L’age de l’imperialisme, Maspero, 1970.

2)    Paul Sweezy, Le capitalisme moderne, Seuil, 1976.

3)    C. A. Michalet, Le capitalisme mondial, P. U. F., 1976.

4)    P. Baran, L’economiepolitique de la croissance, Maspero, 1964.

5)    P. Baran et P. Sweezy, Le capitalisme monopoliste, Maspero, 1968.

6)    M. Kidron, Le capitalisme occidental depuis la guerre, Paris, 1969.

7)    Ernest Mandel, Le troisieme age du capital, 3 volumes, 10-18, 1976.

8)    Fritz Sternberg, Le conflit du siecle, Paris, 1962.

9)    David Horowitz, De Yalta au Viet-nam, 2 vols, 10-18, 1973.

10)    G. Massiah, in Amin, Faire, Hussein et Massiah, La crise de l’imperialisme, Minuit, 1976.

b - Debat sur les « multinationals », theorie du super-imperialisme (le point

de vue economiste moderne)

1)    Michael Hudson, Superimperialism, The Economic Strategy of the American Empire, New York, 1968.

2)    Stephen Hymer, « The Multinational Corporation and the Law of Uneven Development », in J.-N. Baghwathi (ed.), Economics and the World Order, N. Y. 1972.

3)    R. Vernon, Les entreprises multinationals, Calmann-Levy, 1974.

4)    C. Palloix, L’economie capitaliste mondiale, Maspero, 1972.

5)    Giovanni Arrighi, La geometria del imperialismo, Feltrinelli, 1978; The Class Struggle in the 20th Century Western Europe, roneote, Uppsala, 1978.

72 - La division international inegale du travail, l’echange inegal, la dependance. Les theories du sous-developpement

a - Le debat sur l’echange inegal

1)    Arghiri Emmanuel, L ’echange inegal, Maspero, 1959.

2)    A. Emmanuel, E. Somaini et M. Salvati, Un debat sur l’echange inegal, Maspero, 1975.

3)    Oscar Braun, Comercio internacional e imperialismo, Buenos-Aires, Siglo XXI, 1973.

4)    C. Palloix, Problemes de la croissance en economie ouverte, Maspero, 1969.

5)    S. Amin, L'echange inegal et la loi de la valeur, Anthropos.

b - Le debat sur la dependance.

1)    Andre G. Frank, Capitalisme et sous-developpement en Amerique latine, Maspero, 1968; Le developpement du sous-developpement, Maspero, 1977; Lumpen-bourgeoisie, lumpen-developpement, Maspero, 1971.

2)    F. H. Cardoso et E. Faletto, Dependencia y desarrollo en America latina, Santiago, 1967; Ruy Mauro Marini, Sous-developpement et revolution en Amerique latine, Maspero.

3)    S. Amin, Le developpement inegal, op. cite. Voir aussi dans cet ouvrage la bibliographie concernant les theories de la dependance (travaux de F. H. Cardoso, Ruy Mauro Marini, Teotonio dos Santos, Anibal Quijano, Celso Furtado, Osvaldo Sunkel, Aldo Ferrer, etc.).

c - L’accumulation capitaliste et le sous-developpement.

1)    Carlo Benetti, L ’accumulation dans les pays capitalistes sous-developpes, Anthropos, 1974.

2)    P. Sweezy, The Theory of Capitalist Development, New York, 1942.

3)    Tamas Szentes, The Political Economy of Underdevelopment, Budapest,

1971.

4)    Geoffrey Kay, Development and Underdevelopment, A Marxist analysis, Londres, 1975. Voir notre critique in Insurgent Sociologist, University of Oregon, printemps 1977.

5)    Hosea Jaffe, Processo capitalista e teoria dell ’ accumulazione, Jaca, 1973.

6)    Andre G. Frank, « Desequilibres des echanges multinationaux de marchandises et developpement economique inegal; limitation de l’etendue du marche interne par la division du travail et par les relations de production », in Amin et Frank, L’accumulation dependante, Anthropos, 1978.

73 - Le capitalisme et Sexploitation paysanne

a - Theses relatives a la domination formelle en general et a l’exploitation des

paysans par le capital

1)    Karl Marx, Chapitre VI, inedit, du Capital, 10-18, 1971.

2)    Claude Faure, Agriculture et mode de production capitaliste, Anthropos,

1978.

3)    Gervais, Servolin et Weil, Une France sans paysans, Seuil, 1965.

4)    Bernard Lambert, Les paysans dans la lutte des classes, Seuil, 1970.

5)    Cahiers d’economie politique n° 4, 1976, Petite agriculture et capitalisme.

b - Theses relatives a la domination formelle a la peripherie du systeme

imperialiste et en general

1)    P. P. Rey, « Le transfert de surtravail de la paysannerie vers le capitalisme, L’homme et la societe, 1978.

2)    Bernard Founou, Surexploitation de la force de travail en Afrique, considerations theoriques et etudes de cas, these roneotee, Paris-VIII,

1977.

3)    Bruno Lautier, La soumission formelle du travail au capital, Universite de Vincennes, 1973.

74 - Debats sur la crise du capitalisme contemporain et le nouvel ordre

economique international

a - Pour notre analyse sur la crise et des points de vue voisins

1)    Amin, Faire, Hussein et Massiah, La crise de l’imperialisme, Minuit, 1976.

2)    A. Faire et J. P. Sebord, Le nouveau desequilibre mondial, Grasset, 1973.

3)    A. Farhi, Y. Fitt et S. P. Vigier, La crise de l’imperialisme et la troisieme guerre mondiale, Maspero, 1976.

4)    Cahiers Yenan n° 2, Face a la crise economique, 1977.

5)    Rikard Stajner, La crise, Q. A. S., Belgrade, 1976.

b - Points de vue differents

1)    Wladimir Andreff, Profits et structures du capitalisme mondial, Calmann-Levy, 1976.

2)    La crise mondiale du capitalisme, Colloque de l’ACSES, Universite de Vincennes, 1975.

3)    J. M. Chevalier, Le nouvel enjeu petrolier, Paris, 1973.

c - Le nouvel ordre economique international :

1)    Notre point de vue :

S. Amin, Les perspectives de la localisation internationale des activites industrielles, GRESI, Paris, 1976; After Nairobi, UNCTAD IV and the New Economic International Order, Marga Q. J., Colombo, 1976; S. Amin, Frank, Jaffe, Quale 1984 ? Jaca, 1975.

2)    Le Club de Rome et ses critiques :

Club de Rome, Halte a la croissance, Fayard, 1972.

Jan Tinbergen (co-ordinator), RIO, Reschapring the International Order, New York, 1976.

W. Leontief, 1999, L’expertise de W. Leontief, Dunod, 1977.

Amilcar O. Herrera et autres. Un monde pour tous, P. U. F., 1977.

J. Klatzmann, Nourrir dix milliards d’hommes, P. U. F., 1977.

3)    Voir aussi :

Michel Chatelus, Strategies pour le Moyen-Orient, Calmann-Levy, 1974.

J. Annerstedt et R. Gustavsson, Towards a New International Economic Division of Labour, Stockholm, 1975.

75 - Theses chinoises concernant l’imperialisme aujourd’hui

1)    L’imperialisme aujourd’hui, E 100, traduit du chinois, Paris, 1976.

2)    Debat sur la ligne generale du mouvement communiste international 1963-64, Ed. de Pekin, 1965; La theorie du president Mao sur la division en trois mondes, Renmin Ribao, 1er juillet 1977.

3)    Critique du point de vue chinois, in La theorie et la pratique de la revolution, Zeri i Populit, Tirana, 7 juillet 1977.

76 - La formation historique du sous-developpement

a - Domaine asiatique

1)    F. Clairmonte, Economic liberalism and Underdevelopment, Asia P. House, 1960.

2)    C. Bettelheim, L’Inde independante, Maspero, 1971.

3)    D. Thorner, Peasant Unrest in South East Asia, A. P. H., 1968.

4)    Erich H. Jacoby, Man and Land, Londres, 1971.

5)    D. et A. Thorner, Land and Labour in India, A. P. H., 1962.

6)    K. Gough and H. Sharma, Imperialism and Revolution in South Asia, M. Press, 1972.

7)    Rene Dumont, La Chine surpeuplee, Paysanneries aux abois (Ceylan), Seuil.

b - Domaine arabe et ottoman.

1)    C. Issawi, Egypt since 1800, A Study in Lopsided Development.

2)    Doreen Warriner, Land Reform and Development in the Middle East, Oxford University Press, 1962.

3)    Mahmoud Hussein, La lutte des classes en Egypte, Maspero.

4)    Hassan Riad, L’Egypte nasserienne, Minuit, 1964.

5)    S. Amin, Le Maghreb moderne, Minuit.

6)    S. Amin, La nation arabe, Minuit.

7)    K. Vergopoulos, Le capitalisme difforme et la nouvelle question agraire, Maspero, 1977.

c - Domaine africain

1)    P. Gutkind and I. Wallerstein (ed.), The Political Economy of Contemporary Africa, Sage, 1975.

2)    Arrighi and Saul, Essays on the Political Economy of Africa, M. Press, 1973.

3)    Auteurs divers, Studies on South African Imperialism, Southern Africa Research Group, Peace and Conflict Research, Uppsala, 1977.

4)    Rene Lefort, L’Afrique du Sud, Histoire d'une crise, Maspero, 1977.

5)    Boubacar Barry, Le royaume du Waalo, Maspero, 1972.

6)    S. Amin, L’Afrique de l’Ouest bloquee, Minuit.

7)    S. Amin et C. Coquery, Histoire economique du Congo 1880-1968, Anthropos.

8)    B. Ameillon, La Guinee, bilan d’une independance, Maspero, 1964.

9)    C. Coquery, Le Congo au temps des compagnies concessionnaires 18901930, Mouton, 1973.

10)    R. Merlier, Le Congo de la colonisation belge a l’independance, Maspero, 1965.

11)    S. Amin, Imperialisme et sous-developpement en Afrique, Anthropos,

1976.

12)    H. Wolpe, « Capitalism and Cheap Labour Power in South Africa », Economy and Society, n° 4, 1972.

13)    Rene Dumont, L’Afrique noire est mal partie, Seuil, 1962; Paysanneries aux abois (Le Senegal), Seuil, 1972.

14)    Woungly Massaga, La revolution au Congo, Maspero, 1974.

15)    Yves Benot, Ideologie des independances africaines, Maspero, 1975.

d - Domaine americain

1)    F. H. Cardoso, Politique et developpement dans les societes dependantes, Anthropos, 1971.

2)    F. H. Cardoso, Sociologie du developpement en Amerique latine, Anthropos, 1971.

3)    Celso Furtado, Les Etats-Unis et le sous-developpement de l’Amerique latine, Paris, 1970.

4)    Jesus Silva Herzog, La revolution mexicaine, Maspero, 1968.

5)    Auteurs divers, Aspectos teorico-metodologicos de industriasacion y desarrollo de America Latina, Nueva Ciencia, Caracas, 1977.

e - Divers et general

1)    Michel Gutelman, Structures et reformes agraires, Maspero, 1975.

2)    Robert I. Rhodes (ed.), Imperialism and Underdevelopment, M. Press,

1970.

3)    Rene Dumont, Terres vivantes, Plon, 1961; Nous allons a la famine, Seuil, 1966; Developpement et socialismes, Seuil, 1969; L'utopie ou la mort, Seuil, 1973.

4)    Voir la bibliographie du Developpement inegal pour toute la section 76.

77 - Liberation nationale et questions nationales dans le tiers monde

contemporain

a - Le domaine de l’Asie orientale

1)    M. Bastid, M. C. Bergere et J. Chesneaux, La Chine, Hatier, 1976.

2)    Le Thanh Khoi, Le Viet-nam, Histoire et civilisation, Minuit, 1955.

3)    Le Chau, Le Viet-nam socialiste, une economie de transition, Maspero, 1966.

4)    Nguyen Kien, Le Sud-Viet-nam depuis Dien-Bien-Phu, Maspero, 1963.

5)    Pierre Rousset, Le parti communiste vietnamien, Maspero, 1975.

6)    S. Amin, « La legon du Cambodge », in L’imperialisme et le developpement inegal.

b - Le domaine de l’Asie du Sud et du Sud-est

1)    K. Gough et H. Sharma, Imperialism and Revolution in South Asia, M. Press, 1973.

2)    Robin Blackburn, Explosion in a Subcontinent, Penguin, 1975.

3)    Biplad Dasgupta, The Naxalite Movement, Bombay, 1974.

4)    Visakha Kumari Jayawardena, The Rise of the Labour Movement in Ceylon, Duke University Press, 1972.

5)    Tariq Ali, Pakistan, dictature militaire ou pouvoir populaire ? Maspero, 1971; B. H. Levy, Bangla Desh, Nationalisme dans la revolution, Maspero, 1973.

6)    Articles de Tariq Ali, Amiya Bagdi, Paresh Chattopadhyay, Hamza Alavi, Feroz Ahmed, Ram Krishna Mukherjee et autres dans le Socialist Register et la New Left Review, Londres.

c - Le domaine arabe

1)    Flassan Riad, L’Egypte nasserienne, Minuit, 1964.

2)    Mahmoud Hussein, La lutte des classes en Egypte, Maspero, 1970.

3)    S. Amin, Le Maghreb moderne, Minuit, 1970.

4)    Fred Halliday, Arabia without Sultans, Pelican, 1974.

5)    S. Amin, La nation arabe, Minuit, 1977.

6)    Mohamed Harbi, Aux origines du F. L. N., Paris, 1975.

7)    Andre Nouschi, Naissance du nationalisme algerien, Minuit, 1962.

d - Le domaine africain

1)    Suret-Canale, l’Afrique noire, Ed. Sosiales.

2)    Michael Crowder, West africa under Colonial Rule, Londres, 1968.

3)    Benoit Verhagen, Rebellions au Congo, Bruxelles, 1969.

4)    Richard Gibson, African Liberation Movements, Londres, 1972.

5)    CEDETIM, Angola : la lutte continue, Maspero, 1977.

6)    Rene Lefort, l’Afrique du Sud, Maspero, 1977.

7)    Auteurs divers, Studies on South African Imperialism, Department of Peace and Conflict Research, Uppsala University, 1977.

8)    S. Amin, The Future of Southern Africa, presentation d’un ouvrage a paraitre, Tanzanian P. House.

9)    Anonyme, Nationalities and Class Struggle in Ethiopia, Challenge, New York, 1971.

10)    Yash Tandon, « Whose Capital and Whose State », African Review vol. 7, n° 3; egalement Multinational Corporations and the Future of Southern Africa (IDEP, novembre 1977), a paraitre dans le recueil Amin et autres, op. cit.

11)    Issa Chivji, Class Struggles in Tanzania, Londres, 1975.

e - Autres ouvrages.

1)    Gerard Chaliand, Les mythes revolutionnaires du tiers monde, Seuil, 1975.

2)    Eric Wolf, Les guerres paysannes du XXe siecle, Maspero, 1974.

8 - Capitalisme et socialisme, la transition socialiste 80 - U. R. S. S., Chine, capitalisme d’Etat ou socialisme ?

a - Les debats sovietiques

1)    N. Boukharine, L’economie politique de la periode de transition, E. D. I., 1975.

2)    N. Boukharine, Le socialisme dans un seul pays, 10-18, 1974.

3)    Boukharine, Kamenev, Preobrajensky et Trotsky, La question paysanne en U. R. S. S., Maspero, 1973; Boukharine, Preobrajensky et Trotsky, Le debat sovietique sur la loi de la valeur, Maspero, 1972.

4)    E. Preobrajensky, La nouvelle economique, EDI, 1966.

5)    A. Erlich, The Soviet Industrialization Debate 1924-28, Cambridge, 1960.

b - La planification dans les pays de l’Est.

1)    CES, Les problemes de la planification socialiste, EDI, 1968.

2)    Erik Egnell et Michel Peissik, U. R. S. S., L’entreprise face a l’Etat, Seuil,

1974.

3)    Marie Lavigne, Le Comecon, Cujas, 1973.

4)    W. Brus, Problemes generaux du fonctionnement de l’economie socialiste, Maspero, 1968.

5)    B. Mine, L’economie politique du socialisme, Maspero, 1974.

6)    Branko Horvat, An Essay on Yugoslav Society, New York, 1969.

7)    H. Denis et M. Lavigne, Le probleme des prix en Union sovietique, Cujas, 1965.

8)    Andrea Boltho, Foreign Trade Criteria in Socialist Economies, Cambridge University Press, 1971.

9)    Tibor Kiss, The International Division of labour, with Special Regard to the C. M. E. A., Budapest, 1971.

10)    Rene Dumont, Sovkhozes, kholkhozes et le problematique communisme, Seuil, 1964; Cuba est-il socialiste ?, Seuil, 1970.

c - La critique maoiste

1)    Charles Bettelheim, Calcul economique et formes de la propriete, Maspero, 1971.

2)    Cf. Bettelheim, La lutte des classes en U. R. S. S., 2 vols, Seuil, 1977.

3)    Ch. Bettelheim, Revolution culturelle et industrialisation en Chine,

Maspero, 1975.

4)    C. Bettelheim et P. Sweezy, Lettres sur quelques problemes actuels du socialisme, Maspero, 1970.

5)    Pierre Amon, « Revolution culturelle et dialectique du centre et de la Peripherie », in Sociologie et revolution, 10-18, 1974.

6)    Robert Linhart, Lenine, les paysans, Taylor, Seuil, 1976.

7)    Carmen Claudin Urondo, Lenine et la revolution culturelle, Mouton, 1974.

8)    Marcel Liebman, Le leninisme sous Lenine, Seuil, 1973.

9)    Sigrid Grosskopf, L’alliance ouvriere etpaysanne en U. R. S. S., 1921-28, Maspero, 1976.

10)    Alain Bouc, Mao ou la revolution approfondie, Seuil, 1975; La Chine a la mort de Mao, Seuil, 1976; La rectification, Federop, 1977.

11)    Catherine Quiminal, La politique exterieure de la Chine, Maspero, 1975.

12)    E. Poulain, Le mode d’industrialisation socialiste en Chine, Maspero,

1977.

13)    Ch. Bettelheim, Questions sur la Chine apres la mort de Mao Tse-Tung, Maspero, 1978.

d - Le point de vue de l’ideologie russe et la critique interne en Europe de

l’Est.

1)    Roy Medvedev, Le stalinisme, Seuil, 1972.

2)    Roy et Jaures Medvedev, Khroutchev, Maspero, 1977.

3)    A. Amalrik, L’Union sovietique survivra-t-elle en 1984 ? L. G. F., 1977.

4)    Alexandre Koyre, La philosophie et le probleme national en Russie au debut du XIXe siecle, Idees, Gallimard.

5)    Nicolas Berdiaev, Source et sens du communisme russe, Idees, Gallimard.

6)    Alain Besangon, Les origines intellectuelles du leninisme, Calmann-Levy, 1977.

7)    K. Modzelevski et J. Kuron, Lettre ouverte au parti ouvrier polonais, Maspero, 1969.

8)    Samizdat, XXe siecle, Une opposition socialiste en Union sovietique aujourd’hui, Maspero, 1976.

9) Marc Rakovski, Le marxisme face auxpays de l’Est, Savelli, 1977.

e - Autres points de vue concernant la « bureaucratie »

1)    B. Rizzi, La bureaucratisation du monde, Paris, 1939.

2)    J. Burnham, L’ere des organisateurs, Calmann-Levy, 1952.

3)    Cornelius Castoriadis, L’experience du mouvement ouvrier, 10-18; La societe bureaucratique, 10-18 (apport de la revue Socialisme ou barbarie), L’institution imaginaire de la societe, Seuil, 1975. Egalement : Korsch, Pannekock et autres, La contre-revolution bureaucratique 10-18 (bibliographie in Souyri et Papaioannou, op. cit.).

4)    Voir aussi l’apport de l’ecole de Francfort (Horkheimer, Habermas, Adorno, Marcuse, etc.); bibliographie in Martin Jay, L’imagination dialectique, Payot, 1977.

81 - Le mouvement ouvrier europeen contemporain

a - La structure sociale, l’ideologie, l’Europe contemporaine

1)    Nicos Poulantzas, Les classes sociales dans le capitalisme contemporain, Seuil, 1974.

2)    Serge Christophe Kolm, La transition socialiste, Cerf, 1977.

3)    Il Manifesto, Seuil, 1971.

4)    Mario Tronti, Ouvriers et capital, Bourgeois, 1977.

5)    Yves Benot, L’autre Italie, 1968-76, Maspero, 1977.

6)    PUP, Uscire dalla crisi o dal capitalismo in crisi, Rome, 1975.

7)    Cahiers d’etudes socialistes, L’integration europeenne et le mouvement ouvrier, EDI, 1964.

8)    Fernando Claudin, L’eurocommunisme, Maspero, 1977.

9)    Henri Weber, Le P. C. I. aux sources de l’eurocommunisme, 10-18, 1976.

10)    CEDETIM, L’experienceportugaise, Maspero, 1977.

11)    James Weinstein, The Decline of Socialism in America 1912-27, M. Press, 1967.

12)    Daniel Lindenberg, Le marxisme introuvable, Calmann-Levy.

13)    F. Claudin, La crise du mouvement communiste international, Maspero.

b - Le courant autogestionnaire et ses critiques; le communisme de gauche

1)    Claude Berger, Marx, I’association, l’anti-Lenine, Payot, 1974.

2)    Auteurs divers, Les marxistes contre I’autogestion, Selio, 1974.

3)    Yvon Bourdet, La delivrance de Promethee, Anthropos, 1970.

4)    Yvon Bourdet, Pour l’autogestion, Anthropos, 1973.

5)    Daniel Guerin, Pour un marxisme libertaire, Laffont, 1969.

6)    Pour le communisme de gauche des annees 20 et 30, voir Souyri et Papaioannou, op. cit.

7)    Voir egalement les travaux concernant l’anarcho-syndicalisme, Sorel, etc.; Michel Charzat, Georges Sorel et la revolution au XXe siecle, Hachette, 1977.

82 - Questions generales concernant les modes de production, base et

ideologie, etc.

1)    Robert Fossaert, La societe, Seuil, 1977.

2)    Perry Anderson, Le marxisme occidental, Maspero, 1977.

3)    Pierre Souyri, Le marxisme apres Marx, Flammarion, 1970.

4)    Kostas Papaioannou, Marx et les marxistes, Flammarion, 1970.

5)    Institut Feltrinelli, Le marxisme contemporain, 10-18, 1976.

6)    A. Pelletier et J. P. Goblot, Materialisme historique et histoire des civilisations, Ed. Sociales, 1969.

7)    G. Dhoquois, Pour l’histoire, Anthropos, 1971.

8)    F. Jakubowsky, Les superstructures ideologiques dans la conception materialiste de l’histoire, EDI.

9)    M. Reubel, Marx critique du marxisme, Payot, 1974.

10)    A. Lipietz, L’espace du capital, Maspero, 1977.

11)    Abraham Leon, La conception materialiste de la question juive, EDI, 1968.

12)    Lewis Mumford, La cite a travers I’histoire, Seuil, 1964.

13)    Lewis Mumford, Technique et civilisation, Seuil, 1950.

14)    Martin Jay, L ’imagination dialectique, Payot, 1977.

15)    Beaud, Bellon, Francois, Lire le capitalisme, Anthropos, 1976.

9 - Perspectives 90 - Le debat Nord-Sud

1)    S. Amin, CNUCEDIII, Un Bilan, Bulletin of Peace Proposais, Oslo, 1972.

2)    Amin, UNCTAD IV and the New International Economic Order, Africa Development, 1974

3)    Amin, After Nairobi, Africa Development, 1976.

4)    Amin « The New World Economic Order Reactions of the Developped World », in International Financing of Economic Development, Belgrade,

1978.

5)    Amin, « Developpement autocentre, autonomie collective et Ordre economique international nouveau », in L'Occident en desarroi, Dunod,

1978.

6)    Cheryl Payer, The Debt TrapThe IM. F. and the Third World, M. R. Press, New York, 1974.

91 - Les relations eurafricaines

1)    S. Amin, Perspectives de la localisation internationale des activites industrielles, un point de vue afro-arabe, GRESI, 1976; « L’association eurafricaine, quelques aspects du probleme », Eurafrica, 1975; « A propos de l’Eurafrique » in Imperialisme et sous-developpement en Afrique, Anthropos, 1976

2)    Kwame Amoa, « Les relations economiques internationales et le probleme du sous-developpement : la C. E. E. et l’Afrique », in Amoa, Braun, Echanges internationaux et sous-developpement, Anthropos, 1974.

92 - L’operaismo

1) Mario Tronti, Ouvriers et capital, Bourgois, 1977.

2) Antonio Negri, La classe ouvriere contre I’Etat, Galilee, 1978.

Ce texte fait reference, explicitement parfois, implicitement plus souvent, a nos theses, developpees dans les ouvrages suivants :

-    Le developpement inegal, Minuit, 1973 (DI).

-    L’imperialisme et le developpement inegal, Minuit, 1976 (IDI).

-    L’echange inegal et la loi de la valeur, Anthropos, 1973 (El).

-    La loi de la valeur et le materialisme historique, Minuit, 1976 (LV).

-    La nation arabe, Minuit, 1977 (NA).

-    La crise de l’imperialisme, en collaboration avec Faire, Hussein et Massiah, Minuit, 1976 (CI).

-    Imperialisme et sous-developpement en Afrique, Anthropos, 1976 (ISD). Pour alleger le texte principal, nous avons omis de renvoyer le lecteur trop frequemment a ces ouvrages, dont une analyse synoptique des theses suit :

1)    Modes de production, formations sociales, base et superstructure, ethnies et nations : DI chap. 1.

2)    Les societes precapitalistes et la transition au capitalisme; en general, DI, chap. 1; le cas arabe : NA; egalement Presentation, in K. Vergopoulos, Le capitalisme difforme et la nouvelle question agraire, Maspero, 1976.

3)    Les lois fondamentales du capitalisme :

a)    L’accumulation : DI, chap. 2, El (equilibre en dynamique des departements I et II, salaires et productivite, taux de profit, etc.).

b)    Les fonctions de la monnaie dans l’accumulation : DI, chap. 2; El, LV, chap. 3.

c)    Le cycle et la conjoncture : DI, chap. 2.

d)    L’equilibre exterieur : DI, chap. 2, LV, chap. 3.

4)    La loi de la valeur :

a)    Nature, articulation sur la lutte des classes, problemes de la « transformation » des valeurs en prix : LV, chap. 1, 2, an.

b)    Monnaie, Etat et taux de l’interet : LV, chap. 3; El; DI, chap. 2.

c)    La rente fonciere et l’articulation agriculture-industrie : IDI, chap. 2;

LV, chap. 4.

d)    La rente miniere dans le systeme mondial : LV, chap. 6.

e)    Le systeme imperialiste, l’echange inegal, le commerce international et la division international inegale du travail : DI, chap. 6; IDI, chap. 6; El; LV, chap. 5; ISD, intr.

5)    La formation du systeme mondial et l’imperialisme :

a)    La constitution historique des formations capitalistes peripheries : DI, chap. 5; ISD, parties I, II.

b)    Les caracteres generaux des formations peripheriques : DI, chap. 4; IDI, chap. 7, 9, 10.

c)    L’imperialisme; la lutte des classes a l’echelle mondiale; la tendance pro-imperialiste et la tendance anti-imperialiste dans les marxismes : LV, concl.; egalement Presentation, in Beaud, Bellon et Francois, Lire le capitalisme, Anthropos, 1976; « A propos de la critique », op. cit.

d)    Questions de la liberation nationale : ISD, partie III, IDI, chap. 8.

6)    La crise actuelle de l’imperialisme : CI; IDI, chap. 5; egalement :

Quale 1984 ? et divers in bibl. 74-c.

7)    Capitalisme et socialisme, U. R. S. S. et Chine; economisme et marxisme : DI, chap. 5; IDI, chap. 1, 3, 4.

« Arguments »

Samir Amin, classe et nation.

Kostas Axelos, arguments d’une recherche — contribution a la LOGIQUE — HERACLITE ET LA PHILOSOPHIE - HORIZONS DU MONDE — LE JEU DU MONDE — MARX PENSEUR DE LA TECHNIQUE — POUR UNE ETHIQUE PROBLEMATIQUE — VERS LA PENSEE PLANETAIRE.

Georges Bataille, l’EROTISME.

Jean Beaufret, dialogue avec Heidegger : I. philosophie grecque II. PHILOSOPHIE MODERNE — III. APPROCHE de HEIDEGGER. Ludwig Binswanger, introduction a l’analyse existentielle.

Maurice Blanchot, Lautreamont et sade.

Pierre Broue, le parti bolchevique — revolution en Allemagne (1917-1923).

Pierre Broue et Emile Temine, la revolution et la guerre d’Espagne.

Edward Hallet Carr, la revolution bolchevique (1917-1923) : I. LA FORMATION DE L’U. R. S. S. — II. L’ORDRE ECONOMIQUE — III. LA RUSSIE SOVIETIQUE ET LE MONDE.

Francois Chatelet, la naissance de l’histoire.

Carl von Clausewitz, de la guerre.

Gilles Deleuze, presentation de sacher-masoch. Le froid et le cruel avec le texte integral de La venus a la fourrure — Spinoza et le probleme de l’expression.

Wilfrid Desan, l’homme planetaire.

Eugen Fink, le jeu comme symbole du monde — la philosophie DE NIETZSCHE - DE LA PHENOMENOLOGIE.

Pierre Fougeyrollas, contradiction et totalite.

Joseph Gabel, la fausse conscience. Essai sur la reification.

Maria Carmen Gear et Ernesto Cesar Liendo, semiologie psychanalytique.

Wladimir Granoff, filiations — l’avenir du complexe d’redipe — LA PENSEE ET LE FEMININ.

G. W. F. Hegel, propedeutique philosophique.

Rudolf Hilferding, le capital financier.

Louis Hjelmslev, essais linguistiques — le langage augmente de Degres linguistiques — prolegomenes a une theorie du langage suivi de La structure fondamentale du langage.

Roman Jakobson, essais de linguistique generale : I. les fondations DU LANGAGE - II. RAPPORTS INTERNES ET EXTERNES DU LANGAGE -LANGAGE ENFANTIN ET APHASIE - SIX LEgONS SUR LE SON ET LE SENS.

Ludovic Janvier, pour samuel beckett.

Karl Jaspers, Strindherg et Van Gogh — swedenborg-holderlin, precede d’une etude de Maurice Blanchot, La folie par excellence. Otto Jespersen, la philosophie de la grammaire — la syntaxe ANALYTIQUE.

Flavius Josephe, la guerre des juifs, precede par Du bon usage de la trahison, par Pierre Vidal-Naquet.

Karl Korsch, maxime et philosophie.

Georges Lapasade, l’entree dans la vie. Essai sur l’inachevement de l’homme.

Henri Lefebvre, la fin de l’histoire — introduction a la modernite -METAPHILOSOPHIE.

Moshe Lewin, le dernier combat de lenine.

Rene Lourau, l’analyse institutionnelle — l’Etat-inconscient. Georg Lukacs, histoire et conscience de classe.

Herbert Marcuse, eros et civilisation — Contribution a Freud — l’homme

UNIDIMENTIONNEL — VERS LA LIBERATION — L’ONTOLOGIE DE HEGEL ET LA THEORIE DE L’HISTORICITE.

Edgar Morin, le cinema ou l’homme imaginaire.

Bruce Morrisette, les romans de robbe-grillet.

Novalis, l’encyclopedie.

Karl Reinhardt, eschyle-euripide — Sophocle.

Harold Rosenberg, la tradition du nouveau.

Robert Sasso, Georges bataille : le systeme du non-savoir.

Boris de Schlrezer et Marina Scriabine, problemes de la musique MODERNE.

Leon Trotsky, DE LA REVOLUTION : COURS NOUVEAU — LA REVOLUTION DEFIGUREE — LA REVOLUTION PERMANENTE — LA REVOLUTION TRAHIE — LE MOUVEMENT COMMUNISTE EN FRANCE (1919-1939) — MCMV suivi de Bilan et perspectives — LA REVOLUTION ESPAGNOLE (1930-1940)

Karl Wittfogel, LE DESPOTISME ORIENTAL.

Chapter 7

National Liberation and the Socialist Transition:

Is the Bourgeoisie Still a Rising Class?

The fundamental question of our time, to which all other major and minor questions are related, is whether the bourgeoisie is still a rising class. If so, what would be the determining manifestations of this? Continued development of the productive forces in the hegemonic imperialist centers and its leading role on the world scale in shaping societies in all their aspects? Or the extraordinary development of capitalism in the regions of Latin America, Asia, and Africa that up to the present have only barely been touched by it? Or the emergence (or reemergence) of neocapitalist (or simply capitalist) forms in regions which had broken with capitalism to begin a socialist transition: the USSR and, also, perhaps, countries such as Cuba, China, and Vietnam.

If, on the other hand, one maintains that the bourgeoisie is no longer a rising class, what would be the determining manifestations of the crisis of capitalism? The reevaluation, however purely intellectual and marginal, of the civilization of the advanced centers, together with a crisis of values and the emergence of a new consciousness of self-management? Or the blocking of capitalist development in Latin America, Asia, and Africa and thus the possibility—the necessity—of radicalization based on the national liberation struggle leading to the socialist transition? Or, finally, the blocking of a restoration of capitalism after the socialist break and the progress, despite everything, of the experiences in the socialist transition through successive and unequal advances?

182

In addition, there is still the question of whether capitalism can be transcended only by communism reached via the socialist transition. Could capitalism be followed by a new and still necessary (or at least possible) mode of class production, which would assure a development of the productive forces sufficient to make the abolition of classes an inescapable precondition for further progress?

The elements of immediate reality are sufficiently contradictory to support, if one wishes to, polemical responses on either side. The great classic texts of Marxism—Marx, Engels, Lenin, and Mao—are sufficiently rich so that such responses could be based on Marxology. I have chosen instead to base my argument on a two-pronged systematic way of thinking: on one side, on the history of capitalist development on a world scale, and on the other, on the conceptual tool of Marxism used to understand this history. Once our purpose is to understand in order to act, we can no longer claim, as bourgeois theoreticians do, to separate science from ideology.

I have already started this argument in the preceding section, by proposing (1) an Jristorical and theoretical explanation of the reasons for the appearance and development of capitalism in opposition to the theoretical propositions inspired by West-centered and linear philosophy, and (2) a more developed analysis of the contradictions of the contemporary era, which manifest themselves in the center-periphery conflict within the world capitalist system in the different phases of imperialism. This is the basis on which a correct evaluation of the liberation movement and of its prospects may perhaps be developed.

I will now try to go further, shifting from historical to more general levels: on the one hand, to the ambivalent and contradictory nature of the national liberation movement, and on the other hand, to the ambivalent and contradictory nature of the socialist transition.

I. The contradictory nature of national liberation

1. All West-centered studies put the analysis of the functions of the periphery of the capitalist system in a marginal, decorative place. The West-centered analysis of the transition to capitalism leaves out the decisive role played by the periphery from the beginning, claiming that the internal contradictions of feudalism alone explain the transition. It even makes this position into a Marxist principle. The discussion of the European transition to capitalism is a good example of this. The revisionists of our day, inspired by Tokei’s schemas, use this principle as a basis for their conclusion that only Europe could have invented capitalism, Asia being condemned to stagnate indefinitely in the prior stage.

In reality, internal contradictions are primary and decisive. They are the same for all tributary systems and imply the necessary transition to capitalism in every case. By themselves and without any external impact, they were capable of generating capitalism in Europe and elsewhere. But we must not confuse this general proposition with the concrete explanation of the transition as it really took place. If it began more quickly and sooner in Europe, this is not because Europe alone was capable of inventing capitalism but because of the primitive character of feudalism. In the concrete, historical formation of capitalism, Europe created and subjected a periphery as early as the mercantilist period, the exploitation of which both quickened the pace of its own development and arrested and then distorted that of the subject regions. What the ideologues of imperialism do, even when they pretend to be Marxists, is to confuse fundamental methodological propositions with the real, concrete development of history, thus reducing facts to a mere schema.

If an epidemic had wiped out the entire population of Asia, Africa, and America, European capitalism would still have been established, but without a periphery. Similarly, if an epidemic had wiped out the entire world population except that of China, capitalism would have been created in China. But such an epidemic

did not take place. And capitalism was in fact established through the exploitation of the periphery. Thus we must deal with this fact and not invoke supposedly theoretical discussions in order to avoid this disturbing fact.

A parallel exists in the debate about imperialism. Rosa Luxemburg believed she could show that the mechanism of accumulation could not work, even theoretically, without a periphery. She was wrong. Lenin recalled that the schemas of Volume II of Capital established the possibility of accumulation without an external milieu. But Lenin did not draw the conclusion from this that the periphery did not exist. On the contrary.

2. Moreover, are the “external effects” being denied really external? External to what? If we consider the world capitalist system, center-periphery relations are not external but are certainly internal to the system. The contradictions of capitalism must be apprehended at this level, on the plane of concrete capitalist reality. In order to eliminate the most troubling contradictions, some a priori reduce the capitalist system to a mode of production (in its abstract purity). The innumerable “readings of Capital” are thus substitutes for readings of capitalism; and dogmatic rigidity becomes a basic principle.

The logic of this line leads directly to abandoning Marxism. If we push this separation between internal and external effects to its logical conclusion and disregard any dialectic we must conclude that contradictions cannot be understood even on the level of the national formation but only on the level of the basic unit wherein capitalist exploitation arises, the firm. Is circulation not effectively excluded from this supposedly Marxist, impoverished analysis in favor of unending preoccupation with the genesis of exploitation in the relations of production? Under the pretext that production governs circulation in Marxism, any discussion of circulation is dubbed “circulation” and thus reality is disregarded, thought is sterilized, action is precluded. If the redistribution of surplus value via the circulation of capital (Volume III of Capital), the analysis of the relation between productive and unproductive work, the correct definition of the collective worker, and the analysis of the class alliances of a given formation are all put outside the purview of the study, the political position arrived at can be called anarcho-syndicalism. This encourages workers to take no interest in politics. This theoretical reduction fosters a self-management mode in its naive version.

We must keep a vision of the totality. The latter—the world capitalist system in this case—can be reduced neither to the pure capitalist mode nor even to a constellation of unequal national formations. We must detail the content of this inequality, which takes shape in relation to the totality and not in relation to each of its parts. Inequality, whatever its origins, generates an organized hierarchy which it not only statically reproduces but also dynamically re-creates.

The capitalist system has always been a world system. We cannot understand anything about it if we exclude the interaction between the internal effect of one of its parts and the effects external to this part. For this reason, the contribution of those who have emphasized the role of the periphery in the establishment of capitalism from its beginnings is neither small nor even supplementary. They reestablished history in its true dimension. Thus we cannot criticize them for having “neglected” internal effects: others had already studied this fully and our authors made use of this contribution in a perspective which, by linking internal to so-called external effects, gave to capitalism its full shape. Based on these works, it is necessary to reformulate the questions fundamental to our understanding of capitalism, among others: the interaction between production and circulation (and the problematic of long-distance trade in the precapitalist systems and in the transition to capitalism); the international division of labor and unequal exchange, that is, the organization of the production process on a world scale; and the workings of the political and ideological superstructure—in other words, all the questions the dogmatic reduction of capitalism to the pure capitalist mode attempts to eliminate.

3.    Within this framework, the question of the failure of the transition to capitalism of the most evolved tributary societies and the success of Europe can be scientifically investigated. Historically a hundred attempts precede the decisive breakthrough that leads to a point of no return. I have shown the concrete reasons for which Arab mercantilism was so abortive. The Egyptian mercantilism of Mohammed Ali had begun a capitalist development which was perhaps stopped only by European aggression (76b-6). Even in the West, if we look closely, we discover that before the English breakthrough there were the failures of Italy and Spain. Are we going to confine the European miracle to the area of northern Europe? Start with Marx and end with Max Weber?

There is nothing surprising about this series of failures on the part of non-European societies. In the same way we see that attempts to build socialism fail more frequently than any general theory would suggest. Should we draw the conclusion from the failure of the Paris Commune that the French formation will never be able to create socialism? And what should we say about the failure of English Chartism in the nineteenth century and the radicalization of the workers’ movement in the United States during the twentieth? It is true that some still claim socialism was impossible in Russia (unless a German revolution came to its aid) and is condemned in advance in China, Vietnam, and everywhere else except in Europe and the United States.

4.    If it has always been a world system, the capitalist system has nonetheless gone through several stages. In this progression, the imperialist break was fundamental. In fact, this break marked the end of the rising progression of capitalism on a world scale and the beginning of its crisis. In this sense, it was certainly the “highest stage” of capitalism. Naturally, capitalism continued to develop after 1880 and even more quickly than it had in the past. But this development no longer brought about the emergence of new centers: from that time on, the development of capitalism was simultaneously the development of imperialism and of underdevelopment. It is possible to periodize in turn the imperialist period and even to highlight the controlling lines of a possible new stage of the imperialist system.

The thesis of “absolute limits,” which can be attributed to Rosa Luxemburg, ignores this decisive point, that the development of capitalism in the periphery remains the development of a dependent and incomplete capitalism. And the error of certain attempts at periodization also comes from underestimating the importance of the nature of the imperialist break (cf. 72a).

5. This break inaugurated the period of socialist transition on a world scale in the framework of a model of unequal development. This is the essence of the position I support. For imperialism transferred the center of gravity of the contradictions of capitalism and relegated the major contradictions of yesterday to the rank of secondary contradictions, modified by new contradictions. The class struggle in the centers has ceased to be the prime motive force of history. Cecil Rhodes understood that civil war could be avoided in Europe by transferring the contradictions of capitalism through external expansion. Social-democratic hegemony has no other meaning.

But at the same time, imperialism pushed to center stage a new anticapitalist force, that of the peripheral nations, whose struggle has become the motive force of history. A gigantic struggle has begun, pitting the bourgeoisie against the proletariat of these nations, and the outcome will be decisive for socialism. As national liberation cannot be achieved under the leadership of the bourgeoisie, it must be carried out through the stages of development of the imperialist system, until the moment when the proletariat succeeds in taking over the leadership and when the achievement of national liberation creates the new problems of the socialist transition. It is thus that socialism makes its way, a way which cannot be predicted in advance.

The result of this situation is that the analysis of the contradictions of contemporary capitalism must from the first take the entire world system as its field of inquiry. Nothing will come out of the hundred-thousandth reading of Capital that can help us understand these contradictions. Indefinite dwelling on the preeminence of the analysis of capitalist exploitation at its sources, in the relations of capitalist production, will help us fill elementary texts and a few academic Marxological theses, but will not move us forward at all. Any Marxist who believes that analyzing the contradictions on a world scale is a decorative exercise, any Marxist who, as a consequence, considers the anti-imperialist struggle as a supplement, not to say an act of charity, lacks the means to act to transform reality. In that case, is he or she really a Marxist?

But to state that the analysis of accumulation on a world scale should be made on the world scale and not on the basis of the periphery alone is to express a wish that will remain unfulfilled so long as there is no radical shift away from the nondialectical, West-centered view that sees transformations in the periphery as deriving from those in the center. Given that 99 percent of the analyses of accumulation ignore the world picture and focus exclusively on the centers—as 99 percent of the analyses of the transition to capitalism ignore the mercantilist periphery—and given that these analyses are not only incomplete but based on a fundamental error, we must start from the other end to create the conditions for a correct overall analysis.

National liberation and socialism

1.    I will now deal with the problem from the broadest perspective, that of the Marxist debate about imperialism, and try to define the strategy for the socialist transformation on a world scale and the relations between the different political and social forces at work to different degrees and within different contexts in this direction. On this point there are two fundamentally different views. Each claims to be Marxist and claims that the other is not.

2.    The first sees imperialism as constituting an absolutely essential, qualitative break in the history of capitalism. This resulted at the end of the nineteenth century from the establishment of imperialism through the transition from classic competitive capitalism (to give it a name but without illusion as to the nature of this competition) to imperialist capitalism. Before and after imperialism, all problems are different.

Imperialism is not only, nor even primarily, an economic type of transformation inside the imperialist centers, a transition from the quantitative to the qualitative in the centralization and the concentration of capital and recognized as such by the social democrats even before revolutionaries like Lenin. Certainly, there now exist centralization, concentration, monopolies, and interpenetration of finance and industrial capital, and, concomitantly, subjection of the whole of noncapitalist societies to imperialism. But the roots of this subjection are in the past and capitalism did not await the end of the nineteenth century to take on world dimensions. Primitive accumulation itself already had a kind of world dimension before the Industrial Revolution. The manifestation of important political phenomena, and even of the colonial phenomenon, preceded imperialism in certain regions and in certain respects.

If imperialism nonetheless constituted a qualitative break, this is because the centralization-concentration of monopoly capital created the possibility of the export of the capitalist mode of production through the investment of this capital outside the centers of origin. The implantation of segments of the production process outside of and distant from the nation of origin and under different social conditions became possible. The process of the integration and the subjection of societies originally having precapitalist modes of production thus took on completely new proportions. Even if this implantation was quantitatively still sporadic, it was determining.

Later this expansion of capitalism to the world scale in the imperialist phase brought about basic transformations. This is the crucial point of the debate, that of fundamental transformations, of the place of different social classes in the center and in the periphery. We cannot understand these transformations in the relations between social classes within the center, in the periphery, and on a world scale, and the place of different social classes in the class struggle if we treat the countries separately, whether they are imperialist or dominated by imperialism. We can only understand them in the context of their world relations, in a global strategy.

Certainly the fundamental contradiction of the capitalist mode of production and thus of the world capitalist system is that between the bourgeoisie and the proletariat. But, once we have pronounced this banality, we still have to decide on a strategy. That is, on the relations between the different proletariats, the different bourgeoisies, and the other classes subjected to imperialism— especially, in the periphery, in relation to precapitalist modes of production—and how they stand in relation to one another in an overall revolutionary strategy.

With the entrance of capitalism into the imperialist phase, transformations occurred. These may be summarized as follows: The center of gravity of capitalist exploitation shifted in relation to the fact that the relative mass of surplus value centralized to the profit of the monopolies of the imperialist countries grew both in relative and absolute terms. It came more and more from the exploitation of the peoples of the periphery. It was surplus value directly created by the proletariat of the periphery. Or, and this was greater in volume, it was a surplus generated in various modes of production coming from exploiting classes, circulation via local intermediaries under particular forms, transformed into surplus value for the benefit of the monopolies by the formal subjection of these precapitalist peasant or feudal modes of production and the exploitation of large peasant masses.

This shift in the center of gravity did not result from the quantitative measure of the mass of surplus value generated in various places within the whole of the system. On the quantitative plane, the mass of surplus value continued to be generated mainly in the center. But the center of gravity, the sensitive point, shifted toward the exploitation of the periphery. Monopoly capitalism thus gave an objective basis to the social-democratic hegemony among the working classes of the West. This hegemony, visible and indisputable in the Second International, was denounced by Lenin precisely for its relation to the phenomenon of imperialism. Furthermore, the extension of capitalist imperialism to the scale of the i planet closed the road to the expansion of capitalism through bourgeois revolutions in backward countries.

The bourgeoisie in the periphery thereafter developed only in i the imperialist track and was no longer capable of leading a more or i less radical bourgeois revolution, which obviously does not mean i that capitalism is no longer developing. It is developing, but within i the imperialist framework. By contrast, the peasant movement, ; which in the center had historically been an integral part of the ! bourgeois revolution, became part of the socialist revolution. Peasant demands cannot then lead to bourgeois revolutions but must I objectively become a part of the socialist revolution on a world I scale. This does not mean that they automatically lead to it: for j that there must exist proletarian leadership and outlook. In other words, the development of capitalism in the periphery within the imperialist track and the rise of the national liberation movement are not part of capitalist and bourgeois development but part of their crisis.

To define the major camps of social forces and then to determine which are primary and which are secondary according to this thesis, it is not sufficient to recall that on the side of the socialist forces there are the proletarians of the center (even if there is social-democratic hegemony) and of the periphery and, to simplify, the exploited peasantry of the periphery; and that on the other side, in the camp of the capitalist forces, there are monopoly capital and all the dependent bourgeoisie and allied exploiting classes of the periphery. For in this class alliance on a world scale the spearhead of the forces of socialism has shifted from the Western proletariat toward the proletarian nuclei of the periphery in relation to the imperialist phenomenon. From this results the hegemony of social democracy among the Western proletariat and the possibility of a revolutionary worker-peasant alliance in the periphery.

The argument of those who constantly invoke the fundamental contradiction between the bourgeosie and the proletariat scarcely moves the discussion forward. The proletariat exists on the world scale in various places. And at any given moment of history certain sectors of the proletariat are more advanced than others.

Quotations from Marx cannot help us to explain this phenomenon because the phenomenon of imperialism came after Marx. Quotations from Lenin are perhaps a bit more helpful, since it was Lenin who first analyzed imperialism in a decisive manner. But he died in 1924; the system has continued, struggles have developed, things have changed. Lenin was above all preoccupied with the struggle in the Second International against revisionism and with the preparation of the Russian revolution. He correctly situated this in the framework of imperialism but he did not give an answer to everything that happened during his lifetime and certainly not a fortiori to everything which happened after it.

In fact, it appears that socialist revolutions have taken place only in the periphery of the system (China, Vietnam, Korea, Cambodia, Laos, Cuba). Despite the development of capitalism in the periphery and the absence of immediate prospects, it appears that the popular working and peasant masses have rarely placed themselves under the ideological domination of the bourgeoisie and of imperialism and that their revolutionary potential is therefore enormous. Thus it is highly likely that the movement will continue in the same direction. On the other hand, the working classes of the West have, up to the present, been under the sway of social-democratic or revisionist hegemony (which are more and more clearly coming to be the same ideology). This does not rule out class struggle on their part, nor battles, including political ones, which sometimes become violent. But it does deprive the latter of a socialist perspective.

However, these facts can always be disputed, because what is true one day is not necessarily true the next. And from the other side, revolutions in the name of socialism in the periphery raise a series of problems after their accomplishment. I am not talking about a peaceful, problem-free transition to communism, that is, to the abolition of social classes, commodity relations, and the I division of labor. The final goal is far away, still extremely far away.

Thus these arguments, whether they consist of quotations from i Marx or Lenin or of facts themselves, still leave the discussion i open. We must observe real struggles and analyze how they articulate and what their meaning is. Here let me forestall an additional misunderstanding: no prophecy is possible about the course of history. I can simply emphasize the dialectical relationship between the struggles in the center and those in the periphery. In such a situation, which are primary struggles? Which are secon- j dary? In other words, which struggles have a qualitative impact | on others?    j

To the extent that imperialism can transfer exploitation to the | periphery and can deepen this exploitation, it acquires the objec-! tive means to strengthen social-democratic ideology in the center, j As a consequence, imperialism is successful in dividing the working class, in depriving it of an autonomous political perspective, and of integrating its struggles into projects that it continues to control.

To the extent that the periphery offers different degrees of resistance—the highest being liberation, that is, the exit from the imperialist system—to the extent that the movement for national liberation under proletarian leadership spreads, really engaging the great mass of exploited peasants, there exists the possibility of a qualitative break. This is not socialism but only a break toward socialism, the end of imperialist exploitation but not necessarily of the development of indigenous capitalist forces. This is the meaning of the maximum level of resistance to imperialist exploitation. The minimum level is that of the dependent bourgeoisies which at a given conjuncture lead the national liberation movement and through these struggles attain de facto a new division more favorable to themselves and thereby limit the profits of monopoly capital.

To the extent that the periphery offers different degrees of resistance, then, imperialist capital is forced to transfer the contradiction to the metropoles, thus reducing the objective basis for social democracy and strengthening the tendencies toward renewed revolution. Up to the present (that is, between 1870 and 1978) the primary tendency has been for national liberation struggles—from the strongest, led by the proletariat which breaks with imperialism, to the weakest, led by the bourgeoisie which extracts concessions compensated for by readjustments in the imperialist system—to be the motive force of contemporary history. Thus, the enlarging or shrinking of the objective basis for social democracy in the center has depended, in the main, on liberation struggles for over a century now. Of course there have been ups and downs, since this resistance and these struggles have developed not in a linear fashion but through a process of victories and defeats, whether led by the proletariat or the bourgeoisie.

3. Is the national liberation movement what I claim, the motive force of history and the primary force for the creation of socialism? When, through gross oversimplification, this movement is reduced to the struggle for the national political independence of Asia and of Africa, it is tempting to conclude that this movement was in reality only a relatively brief phase of contemporary history: from 1945 to 1965-1970, perhaps.

Let us return then to the course of contemporary history. Since 1880 the fact of imperialism has controlled all important events, weighed all confrontations, and determined their outcome. Simultaneously, since 1880 the national liberation struggle has emerged and progressively grown.

In the first phase, from 1880 to 1914, the national liberation struggle was not yet the immediate motive force of history, although the revolt of the working classes in the center of the system had ceased to be so. This is why this phase was the golden age of imperialism. The working classes had already been subordinated by their imperialist bourgeoisies and, although only 1914 would indicate the catastrophic dimensions of this, the Second International appears in retrospect to have been the instrument of this subordination. The liberation movements were only beginning to establish themselves but they were not yet out of the precapitalist age. Their task was more to resist aggression than to liberate

anything. This is why during this phase interimperialist contradictions held center stage: this was the Belle Epoque, when great-power diplomacy was the immediate motive force of history. This phase ended with the First World War, the Russian revolution, the May Fourth Movement in China, Kemal Ataturk, the Egyptian Wafd, and Indian Congress Party.    i

From 1918 to 1945 center stage was no longer held exclusively j by interimperialist contradictions, although these still existed and I caused conflict between the conquerors and conquered of 1918. At I the same time, this era saw the rise of the Russian revolution, its I stagnation, and its reverses; the rise of the Chinese revolution; the I rise of liberation movements on three continents: Latin American i populism, modern independence revolts, and repressed revolu-; tions in Asia and Africa. This complex of rising forces once again i indicates the internal contradictions of the centers. The crises of I the era following the First World War and of 1930 highlight these i social contradictions. The period closed with the Second World i War, which marked the end of the rise of the Western workers’ movement, while other forces, those of the Soviet Union and those of national liberation, continued to develop.

Beginning in 1945 a third period opened, during which the predominance of national liberation was achieved. Interimperialist contradictions were attenuated by American hegemony to the point where the notion of superimperialism seemed to be confirmed. Only “seemed” because this view, anticipated by Kautsky and very much in vogue in the United States, arises from an economist reduction: the state is the passive instrument of the multinationals, which shape the world in their image (71-6). I do not share this point of view, but that is not the question. For in any event, the Western workers’ movement did not recover from the defeat of the 1930s and 1940s. As time passed, it seemed to be just as subordinated as it was before 1914. The Soviet Union, confined within the borders of its zone of influence, acted on the world scene only in relation to liberation movements. It was through the alliances it made with these movements that it acquired a world dimension. During this quarter century, national liberation was achieved in east Asia and Cuba, which undertook possible socialist transitions, while elsewhere the movement attained its first objective, political independence, without having begun such transitions.

Will the completion of this phase put an end to the national liberation movement and to its potential for socialist transformation? This is Gerard Chaliand’s position (77e-l). It seems to have been confirmed by the immediate facts over these last years, which makes it temporarily popular. And yet it is incorrect because it reduces the goal of national liberation to independence. But the latter does not resolve the contradictions of peripheral capitalism. Doubtless it creates new conditions, from which the pause arises. The transcendence of the phase of embryonic peripheral capitalism imposed by political domination (“the colonial mode of production,” as Rey calls it) by the spontaneous reproduction of dependent capitalism (the neocolonial mode of production) through the hegemony of the local bourgeoisie, via the economic mechanism of the capitalist system, modifies the nature of the objective, the methods of struggle, and the positions of the camps (10-6, 73b-l).

For these reasons Chaliand proposes that we consider the era of liberation movements to be over and that we call by its name, the internal class struggle, the era which is beginning in the third world. His error is in failing to see that this class struggle continues to operate in the framework of still incomplete national liberation. The bourgeoisies of the third world try to carry through this struggle and to retain the leadership of it, as I have argued in my analysis of the strategy they adopt to attain economic independence. The popular classes must not ignore this struggle any more than they previously ignored the goal of independence. But they must use the autonomy of their movement to take over the leadership and by means of this begin the socialist transition. This is why national liberation continues to hold center stage. History and history only—not theory and even less Marxology—will tell if this will coincide with the reemergence of a workers’ movement in the West.

4. Set within this framework, which is that of uninterrupted

revolution by stages, debates over the strategy of the new phase of national liberation take on practical importance. These are real debates within the movement and the struggle, debates whose real importance cuts through the unimportance of theories that insist on the primacy of the class struggle and conceal beneath their triviality the fact that they erase the conditions for class struggle on a world scale.

The contradictory nature of national liberation is expressed in this twofold reality. On the one hand, each partial victory for national liberation creates the conditions for the deepening of i capitalist development. On the other hand, it does not mitigate the j contradictions between the popular masses and imperialism and its allies but on the contrary aggravates them.

Is it possible that this movement will go on indefinitely, passing through successive stages without ever bringing about the qualitative break which will inaugurate the socialist transition? In this case, will the process of capitalist development become complete and the center-periphery contradiction disappear? Marx had considered the possibility that Europe, ripe for socialist revolution, might have to deal with rising capitalism from this “little corner of the world.” But he wrote this before imperialism, and thus made the twofold assumption that the European workers’ movement would continue to become radicalized and that capitalist development in Asia would be nondependent.

Since that time the hypothesis of the complete development of capitalism in the peripheries subject to imperialism has not come true. Marxism does not reason on “ifs” that are contrary to reality understood in its real movement. The new phase of imperialism which is taking shape based on the real social forces of contemporary capitalism is not going in the direction of the completion of capitalism (the goal of economic independence proclaimed by the bourgeoisies of the third world cannot be attained with the strategies they propose) but is prolonging the line of dependent, incomplete development.

Of course, if the popular forces do not act in the periphery and if

the process is thus pursued beyond this new phase, that is, if capitalism continues to survive let us say a thousand years, it will finally find the means to resolve its contradictions. In this science-fiction hypothesis, imperialism will have disappeared, having played its historic role of spreading capitalism from this “little corner of Europe” to the whole world. Imperialism would not have been the highest stage of capitalism but only a transitory modality of its deployment. But even following this hypothesis, which is without political importance, the question of communism would still exist. In a totally homogenized world where capitalism would already have suppressed nations and national inequalities, the class struggle would finally acquire that purity dreamed of by certain people—unless in this science-fiction world it was too late, unless the regime of “one-dimensional man” had nullified the laws discovered by historical materialism. If we begin a chain of reasoning like this, we must follow it to the end, leave the solid ground of real struggles between real forces operating in a no less real world for the free play of all hypotheses.

5. The current crisis provides additional evidence that the center-periphery contradiction continues to be the prime means by which the range of fundamental and secondary contradictions of the system are manifesting themselves. In fact, we see that a series of victories for national liberation movements has characterized the last phase. The most important have been those of the peoples of East Asia; the least important have been those of the oil bourgeoisies, who have obtained a new division of profits by utilizing the interimperialist contradictions of a given moment. All that has played a decisive role in the current crisis of imperialism, that is, in its need to readjust itself to this resistance by the periphery.

The consequence is obviously a resurgence of struggles in the center, whether on the ideological or the economic level, since the link between the two remains very strong. Without the Chinese cultural revolution, we would be hard pressed to understand certain things that have happened in the West. The critique of revisionism in the West began in small groups linked to anti-imperialist

struggles (Algeria, Vietnam, Palestine). Even on this level the effect is decisive.

On another level, the victorious resistance of the periphery has led to an accelerated falling rate of profit in the center, partially obscured by the mechanisms of stagflation; the transfer of the contradiction to the working classes of the center; and the attempt to implement an economic policy designed to recreate a reserve army there, at least partially. At the same time, imperialism has chosen to close ranks. The imperialist bourgeoisies of the subordinate metropoles once again are lining up under the leadership of ! the dominant American fraction in order to form a common front : to limit as much as possible the victories of national liberation j movements in the periphery and thus to mitigate the contradictions in the center. The failure of both the fourth UNCTAD conference and of the “north-south dialogue” testify to this refusal on the part of imperialism to grant concessions to the bourgeoisies of the periphery (74c, 78).

Let me restate that this analysis does not claim to be a prophecy and that weak spots can shift at any given moment. Nonetheless, I must emphasize this reality: for a century the primary tendency has been for the national liberation struggle to be the motive force of history. This means that all struggles, including those in the center, are determined in relation and in accord with this principal struggle in the capitalist system. Of course, a class struggle on this scale must not be understood as a juxtaposition of class struggles in different countries, of different modes of production, which only maintain episodic and random relations. They are organized in relation to a class alliance on a world scale and in relation to the position of different fractions of classes in this world alliance, which determines which are the vanguard elements, the bulk of the troops, the primary enemy, and so on.

6. This is one point of view, generally not accepted in the West. But there is a second, diametrically opposed vision. This is that the contradiction between the proletariat and the bourgeoisie in the center of the system continues to be the principal contradiction of

the entire system. This position also holds that the nafionalTiBera-”' tion movement is an integral part of the worldwide bourgeois revolution. It is openly predominant in the social-democratic workers’ currents as well as in those of revisionist communism and even—implicitly not to say explicitly—in the Left opposition in the West, and testifies to the ideological hegemony of social democracy. This position was taken by the Second International, and justified it in embracing imperialist ideology. One might have thought that Lenin would have eliminated it from the movement to the left of social democracy. Not at all.

The supporters of this second position will continue to be mystified about the development of capitalism in the periphery. But they do not see—since they must negate imperialism—that it is a question of dependent capitalism, which is incapable of realizing the goal of national liberation, and thus leaves intact all the potential for a socialist revolution. On the other hand, when it comes to social democratic hegemony in the West, they persist in attributing this to subjective and circumstantial factors. This is why we hold that this second view is one variant of imperialist ideology, which can take the naive form of social democracy or revisionism as well as leftwing forms.

7. The conflict between these two visions, whether open or hidden, exists everywhere and at all times. In this regard, the debate about unequal exchange has been revealing. We have seen positions gradually take shape in service of the ideological loyalties of each of the two camps. We have seen the Trotskyists chime in with the revisionists and even seen some erratic Maoists in the West join this camp.

Another example of the conflict between these two views is in the debates concerning the current crisis (74a, b). On the one side, the Maoists identify this crisis in the first instance as a crisis of imperialism, that is, of the international division of labor and of the world class alliances that control it. In this view, the origin of the crisis is first located in the defeats of imperialism in the East, defeats which have modified the objective conditions of the class

struggle in the centers as they have modified the objective framework of interimperialist contradictions. Others refuse to call the crisis a crisis of imperialism. They claim that class struggles in the center are the fundamental cause and that these struggles determine the objective framework for accumulation on a world scale.

On West-centeredness once again

1. West-centeredness is the product of capitalism and particularly of its imperialist phase; it penetrates the workers’ movement and even thought that claims to be Marxist. Its immediate manifestation is the absence of interest in non-Western societies, which inevitably leads to a serious distortion of the history of the West itself. For the West cannot be understood without the East, neither in the past during the mercantilist epoch nor today during the imperialist epoch. The benefits that Western peoples within the imperialist framework derive from the exploitation of the periphery constitute the objective basis for the penetration of West-centeredness into the workers’ movement. This enables bourgeois ideology to become that of the whole society, while it was only partially so before imperialism. These benefits are not illusory, as certain people have claimed, because the real interest of the proletariat of the centers is to free itself from capitalist exploitation. They are, within the framework of the operation of capitalism, completely real: it is imperialist exploitation on a world scale that creates full employment and the growth of real salaries in the center.

This situation will have an important impact relative to the socialist transition in the developed centers. Will the peoples of the West, if they are not forced to it by the liberation of the periphery, be disposed to renounce imperialism and face the long transition that will be necessary before the advantages of their liberation from capitalism balance the difficulties of reconversion? The least we can say is that the effect of West-centeredness is to hide this cruel reality from the peoples of the West. A moment’s thought would seem to lead to the conclusion that it is precisely there that the imperialist bourgeoisies are awaiting the Left. It is on these difficulties that eventual breakthroughs in the West are likely to founder (81).

For example, Western nations are more and more petty bourgeois nations, in that there is a concentration of middle layers whose functions can only be understood on the scale of operation of the world system, as Poulantzas has shown (8 la-1). The overdevelopment of the tertiary sector, which has become unproductive, and the possible subsequent concentration of the quartenary sector under the hypothesis of a new international division of labor relegating certain industries to the periphery, have for counterpart the concentration of the generation of surplus value in the periphery through the direct exploitation at higher rates of surplus value, formal domination over precapitalist sectors, the pillage of natural resources, and so on. Under these conditions, the reconversion that the socialist transition implies for the central societies will create considerable difficulties.

The ambiguities of popular and working-class movements in the West reveal the opportunist withdrawal in the face of these problems. We see it clearly today in relation to the battle for economic independence and a rise in the price of raw materials which third world countries are engaged in. The question is: Who will definitively maintain the superprofits of the monopolies: the working classes of the centers or the peoples (including the bourgeoisies) of the peripheries? I find it disturbing that the Western Left lines up without hesitation on the side of imperialism: their excuse for escaping their responsibility is that this battle is being led by the states and thus by the bourgeoisies of the third world. The bourgeoisie has understood perfectly well how to exploit this weakness. It has succeeded in explaining without difficulty that Western nations have a right to the natural wealth of the third world, that Western peoples should not have to finance the appetites of the sheiks and bureaucrats of the third world. In the short term, this imperialist theme has put the Right several lengths ahead, as recent revolutions in Europe have shown. And an important part of the

far left shares the attitudes of the social-democratic and dominant revisionist currents, as do the economic planners in the East European countries.

2. West-centeredness systematically distorts Marxism. Through dogmatic rigidity, it has virtually turned an instrument of revolutionary action into an academic discipline. The debate over unequal exchange has convinced me that insistence on the “preeminence of production over circulation” is nothing but an ideological excuse. For ultimately this debate has led to formulating problems in terms of relations of production, generation of surplus on a world scale, and world circulation of the surplus controlled by the capitalist relations of production on a world scale. It is in these terms that it has been established that the higher rates of surplus value in the periphery, the absolute surplus value obtained through formal domination, reduced or suppressed rents are all concealed beneath the appearance of “relative prices. ” It is a case of generation of the surplus and at the same time of the distribution that flows from the very process of its generation. The latter in its turn controls the forms of accumulation: unproductive overdevelopment at one end, the absolute law of pauperization at the other.

The anticirculationist argument thus conceals the intent to refuse to analyze the generation of surplus on a world scale and to confine this analysis to the centers. This is because it has been a priori decreed that surplus value is produced only in the centers and it would be inconvenient to find it increasingly generated in the periphery. It is not surprising to find this argument in Trotskyist writing. This is the case for Geoffrey Kay (72c-4), who is not only ignorant of the arguments in the debate but moreover naively declares his intention to prove that the misery of the third world is due not to its overexploitation by capital but to the fact that it is not exploited enough. The capitalist law of accumulation enables the rise in the living standard of the masses, and the proof is the history of the West. Additional proof is the misery of the periphery. Kay never asks himself whether the misery of the third world and the wealth of the West are related. The relative stability of salaries in

the national income of the West means that at least the rate of surplus value is constant there. Moreover, the overdevelopment of unproductive functions that do not generate surplus value but redistribute it suggests that this rate is declining there. In the periphery, on the other hand, the rate and mass of surplus value are still growing: the growth of productivity is much more rapid there than that of the returns to labor. This enormous, staggeringly clear fact, which would seem since Lenin to have become obvious, totally escapes our Marxist, whose thesis—which recalls Rostow’s in its denial that underdevelopment and development are two sides of the same coin—would be well received by the Ford Foundation.

On the other side, Charles Michalet, whose problematic is the same as mine (the world system envisaged in its totality as a framework for the generation of surplus value), writes that multinationalization “permits expanded reproduction through the shift in the site of exploitation toward zones having a higher rate of surplus value with an identical organic composition,” “is accompanied by an integrated structure of spheres of production and circulation on a world base,” or “does not mean the disappearance of the inherent laws of capitalism but rather their extension to a world scale” (7la-3).

Certainly there is much more to say about the question of how the law of value operates on the scale of the world economic system. But it seems obvious that we will not progress if we continue to repeat the abc’s: the law of value in the pure capitalist mode of production.

3. Having once and for all given up any interest in the real field of operation of capitalism, the world system, West-centered Marxists are forced to take refuge in Marxology. Theoreticism and readings of Capital take the place of analyzing reality. As Michel Beaud has pointed out, the tendency is to “derive theory from theory” (82-15). Superspecialization is contrary to Marxism but is in accord with academic tendencies. Politically, it is still revisionism, whether of the Left or Right; it is still indifferent to the problem of imperialism, viewed as the speciality of other researchers, or as an attack of third worldist fever, or as the attraction of ethnographic exoticism, or as the overflowing of a charitable spirit. Historians of this type are preoccupied with illustrating the marvelous history of the West and with proving “scientifically” that only Europe could have brought about the progress of humanity. What better proof that the ideology of the dominant class has become the ideology of society?

4. Nothing in Marx’s thought lends itself to such misuse. Marx never wanted to be taken for a prophet. Happily, he was only a man, who lived neither outside space nor outside time. But the religious spirit of others has freed his legacy from this modesty. It has been forgotten that he only laid the basis for historical materialism and discovered the essential laws of capitalism. It has been forgotten that he had no other ambition, especially not that of depriving his successors of advancing the struggle under new conditions which he scarcely tried to predict. The best of his successors, Lenin and Mao, did not so deprive themselves: for a rigid dogmatist, what could be more heterodox than the contributions of Leninism and Maoism to Marxism?

In my view, the contribution of Leninism consists above all in having applied the Marxist method to the conditions of the new imperialist epoch. This framework enabled Lenin correctly to analyze the revisionism of the Second International by relating it to its objective bases and from there to formulate the strategy for the socialist revolution in the new conditions of unequal development within the imperialist system. As to the contribution of Maoism, it consists above all in the application of the Marxist method to an analysis of the conditions of class struggle in the transitional period.

Marx was at work between 1840 and 1880, that is, at the moment when the bourgeois revolution was emerging from its original little corner of England and spreading throughout Europe. Its rise was putting an end to initial primitive accumulation and to the role the old periphery had played in it. This initial subjection by that time had already blocked and even brought about regression in Latin America, Asia, and Africa—through the genocide of the Amerindians, the slave trade, the destruction of Indian and

Egyptian industry, the opium trade imposed on China, and so on—and these continents had not yet begun to take off again under the impact of their integration as a periphery in the imperialist era. To voluntarily disregard this context, to transform phrases, often taken from drafts which Marx did not think worthy of publication, into so many “revelations” is, in reality, to betray him in the worst way: by embalming him.

II. The contradictory nature of the socialist transition

1. Soviet experience has taught us that the socialist transition does not necessarily lead to communism. The debate over the nature and laws of Soviet society is still open. I have maintained that this class society was of a new type because state centralization of capital constituted a qualitative leap. It suppressed certain basic laws of capitalism, flowing from the fragmentation of control, and particularly the dominance of the economic instance which is related to it.

Thus it established new relations between the economic base and the superstructure, which became dominant again. This is why some have thought it useful to give a name to this new class mode. The Chinese Maoists call it “state monopoly capitalism” and its ruling class the “state monopoly bourgeoisie, ” reserving the term “monopoly capitalism” pure and simple for the West. On this basis, they speak of the “restoration of capitalism.” I will return to the differences implied by these two terms.

But the Soviet experience is not the only one at issue. The political demands put forward by the tendencies that dominate the Western working class are similar: gradual movement toward the state mode or toward state monopoly capitalism (in the real sense, not in that used by the revisionist parties). Serious social democrats (in Sweden, for instance) do not try to hide this—state property must take the place of fragmented capital—nor do the Western communist parties. The Trotskyists lead objectively to the same position since as the others they make a cult of the unilateral determination by the productive forces. The self-management tendency has not yet responded to the series of fundamental questions which a socialist transition would pose in the West; it is afloat in contradictions and at times in naivetes. Finally, the experience of the third world countries seems also to show that when the bourgeoisie appears as a rising class there, it is always in the form of a state bourgeoisie.

Should we draw the conclusion from these similarities that the state mode is a possible successor to capitalism? In this case, the class struggles between exploited and exploiters would once again work in favor of a third party, a new class in formation, emerging in part from within the exploited class (party and organizational bureaucrats, technical cadres of the labor aristocracy, etc.) and in part parallel to it (new layers of technocrats).

2. Powerful objective forces are effectively at work in this way during the socialist transition. The specific contribution of Maoism to Marxism-Leninism is precisely in having developed the theory of the contradictions of the transition. This contribution has been developed within the concrete and specific conditions of China. But it also has been based on a reassessment of Soviet history. It has gotten out of the rut of the false theory of the degeneration attributed by Trotskyism to the peasant character of Russia by positively defining the conditions necessary for the worker-peasant alliance. In this way Maoism has universal applicability.

Its applicability certainly goes beyond the future experiences of transition from peripheral capitalism. For there is no doubt that the problems of the eventual transition from central capitalism will be no less serious nor fundamentally different. The same forces that work toward restoration or the emergence of the statist mode within peripheral situations will be at work within central situations: these forces originate in the continued existence of commodity relations, of the infrastructure of technical organization, and of the division of labor during the transition. Not to speak of the specific difficulties of the central transition as outlined above in relation to the destruction of imperialism. But there does not yet exist a social praxis of this transition, since the Paris Commune did not have the time to create it. Therefore, my observations will be limited to the contradictions of the peripheral transition.

Here I refer the reader to other writings and earlier discussion in this volume, notably the discussion about the meaning of independent and popular autocentered development, the strategy of putting industry in the service of agricultural development, and the “three revolutions” in the relations of production, technology, and culture. Vital questions remain to be explored, doubtless through practice first, but without putting off theoretical consideration of those problems that are maturing. Among others, the questions of autarky for small socialist countries and cooperation between socialist countries, and the question of the initiation of this cooperation between countries already advanced in their national liberation.

These questions have given rise to the expression of contradictory opinions and of equally contradictory practice, as well as to positive debates which have lead to subtler formulations. This has been the case, for example, with the discussion that put an end to the myth of the suicide of the petty bourgeoisie; discussions concerning the social organization of the rural world (cooperatives vs. the strengthening of petty commodity production) and the modalities of articulation between big and small industry in the direct service of collectivities, especially rural ones; and controversies concerning the advantages and difficulties of autarky and the “neutrality” of imported technology.

But the two essential questions which express the contradictions of the transition are the state and national questions, already discussed. The continued existence of the state during the transition testifies to the continued existence of classes, based on the continued existence of commodity relations. Of course, here we are dealing not with vestiges of old classes but above all with the new, rising class—whether we call it a bourgeoisie or something else. The anarchist tendencies of the Western Left have obviously distorted the debate over this question.

In the same way, since socialism takes form in the disintegration of the imperialist system, the national phenomenon retains all its importance during the transition. For this same reason, I have rejected the naive West-centered position which, in putting to the fore the “necessary disappearance of nations, ” objectively becomes an excuse for disregarding the effects of imperialism.

3. The contradiction of the socialist transition thus lies in the alternatives of a classless society or a new class society, either of which can emerge during the transition. A new class society or simply the restoration of capitalism? If we are talking about a new mode of production, the statist class society is highly likely to become stabilized over a long historical period, all the more so as this mode would be a progressive one since it would give a fillip to the development of the productive forces. The dominant class of this mode would thus be a rising class. If we are talking about a simple restoration, the state mode would be a transitory mode, unstable, unprogressive, and the hegemony of the dominant class would constitute the last gasp of a decadent bourgeoisie.

This fundamental debate has begun. Which of the two positions do the facts support? We know little about Soviet society, the analysis of its fundamental laws having so far been distorted by the desire to find in it a priori the expression of either of the laws of socialism (even if it is degenerate, which means little beyond the short transition), or of the laws of capitalism. For instance, the expression of the law of the tendency of the rate of profit to fall is sought. But this society seems relatively stable despite its difficulties: the impossibility of liberation, the continued backwardness of agriculture, national conflicts, and so on. Similarly, in Eastern Europe, Rumania seems to have stabilized in a state mode. But on the other hand, appearances at least do not indicate that Poland, Hungary, Czechoslovakia, or Cuba have reached a stable equilibrium. In Egypt, a third world country which has created an organizational form inspired by the same model although in a weak and dependent version, experience seems to show that the state mode—which it is true never reached its complete form here—is only a stage in the development of capitalism.

Analysis of these problems, which is necessary, will involve not only a close examination of the working of economic laws characterizing these systems but also the integration of this into a global understanding of the relations between the economic base and the superstructural, political, and ideological instances.

The social nature of Soviet society

1. In the analysis of the relations between relations and forces of production some have maintained that as the development of technology in the USSR is in all respects similar to that in the West, by the type of division of labor and of the organization which it controls, we must consider the mode of production prevailing in Soviet society to be capitalist. Theirs is a solid argument in support of this view.

Nonetheless, we need to ask two further questions. The first concerns the effects of the centralization of capital on the operation of the system. Does such centralization not erase the fragmentation characteristic of capital, along with its effects (economistic ideology)? Does it not explain the functional dominance of ideology in the USSR, as I have expressed it? The second concerns the possibility of a higher development of the productive forces on the basis of this centralization. Is the Soviet mode not new and superior in that it permits the transcendence of the limits imposed by the competition of capitals?

It is dangerous to underestimate the formidable attraction of revisionism for the western working classes and the possibility of a revisionist alliance which they would support. Is the goal of the Swedish social democrats fundamentally different?

Bukharin had envisaged this type of state monopoly capitalism (70b-5). That the Soviet Union, still very backward, has not actually tested this potential does not seem necessarily convincing to me. A new mode starts on a lower level and procedes to a higher one. If this mode permits the resolution of the center-periphery contradiction, which is inherent in capitalism, would this alone not make it a superior mode? Once again, to avoid dishonest exploitation of this hypothesis, it must be repeated that the Soviet mode is one means of partially transcending capitalism, the other being communism.

2.    Analysis of the debates about Soviet planning must be carried out within this framework. They must be related to the social nature of the USSR and the analysis of the class struggle in the USSR (80a, b).

The results of Soviet economic growth have been unequal, slower than predicted, and not in conformity with the plans. Can this be attributed to the bureaucratic deformation of a state that remains fundamentally a workers’ state, as a certain Trotskyist thesis has it? Or does it reflect the resistance of the exploited classes? I suggest that in the USSR as elsewhere it is the class struggle that determines the pace and direction of economic development. The hypothesis is that because the state bourgeoisie is not subject to the competition of capitals over which it has collective control, prices are determined by costs instead of by the laws of the market. Under these circumstances, the resistance of the workers to the intensification of work as a basis for the extortion of rising relative surplus value is easier than in the West.

The right to work, won in October, is a weapon in the class struggle, a weapon which the regime has only been partially able to circumvent through the multiplication of administrative constraints. But will it be able to go further, to suppress this right and to reestablish, by control over the unemployment rate, normal conditions for the sale of labor power? Although Yugoslavia has overcome this obstacle, it has largely nullified the effects of it by simultaneously recognizing workers’ control.

3.    This thesis concerning the transparency of relations of exploitation in the Soviet system of generalized state capital and its effects on the relations between economic base and ideological superstructure calls for more systematic thought about the functions of nationalist ideology. I am proposing that nationalism is primarily what holds this society together. In the West economic dominance reduced ideology to consumerism and science and technology to ideology. The effects of this reduction have become apparent: social crises, crises of values, crises of youth, and the like. In the USSR will nationalism forestall this crisis?

It still remains to specify what kind of nationalism we are talking about. At first, an attempt was made to create a Soviet nationalism transcending that of the Russian, Slavic, and Asiatic nationalities. Although disguised as a liberating mission on the scale of all humanity, this nationalism coincided with the Slavophile aspect of traditional ideology. Nicolas Berdiaev and Alexander Koyre had anticipated its function (80d). Gradually, this nationalism became Russified. It thus more and more conflicted with the resurgence of Turko-Muslim nationalism in Central Asia, of that of the Caucasus and of the Ukraine. The Great Russian population, no longer in the majority, was condemned demographically to become increasingly a minority: The considerable state centralization of the Soviet Union, despite its federal form, has up to now prevented the most bloody nationalist conflicts. But for how long? And how will the Russian state react to these contradictions? By granting concessions, not to say by giving up Asia and encouraging neocolonial independence there, as West-centered ideologues wish to see it? Or on the contrary, by expanding and moving outward, by external aggression, especially against China and the slavic nations of the west? We need better knowledge of the currents which cut across contemporary Soviet life.

Technocracy and labor aristocracy in the USSR and the West

1. The evolution of the USSR prompts reflection on the question of state capitalism and the objective forces at work toward a nonsocialist resolution of the contradictions of contemporary capitalism. The question is whether the state mode must necessarily take the Soviet form and thus be practically the outcome of a socialist revolution undermined by the inadequacy of the class struggle which follows it. Or state capitalism could also progressively grow out of monopoly capitalism under the impact of the gradual concentration of capital and of its fusion with the state. The thesis of superimperialism explicitly raised this possibility and even called it a necessary stage on the peaceful road of socialist development. B. Rizzi, followed by J. Burnham, has taken this thesis from Kautsky and Hilferding and combined it with the “rise of the technocrats” (80e).

2. An answer to this question needs a much more systematic analysis than that which we currently have about the relations between technocracy and the labor aristocracy of the developed capitalist countries. The social-democratic tendency in the Western workers’ movement continues in fact to be ambivalent as to the class interests it represents. There is little doubt that in the beginning this tendency reflected the gradual establishment of a labor aristocracy grafted onto imperialist exploitation and in effective control of the workers’ movement. The history of English labor and of German social democracy testifies to this. However, as the new petty bourgeoisie became established, social democracy tended to represent the alienated form of the interests of the new technocracy, the upper layer of this comfortable proletariat of white collar workers and technical cadres. The attempt of monopoly capital to make this new layer play the role which the peasants played in the previous stage, that of antiworker troops, has not always brought the expected results, especially in southern Europe and Scandinavia, in contrast to England and West Germany.

Thus a gap has formed between rightwing social democracy on the one hand, domesticated by the monopolies and subjecting the working class to the joint leadership of the technocracy and the labor aristocracy (between whom the contradictions have lessened), and on the other hand a more ambivalent movement that maintains some distance from the monopolies. At times this movement takes a social democratic form, as in Sweden, where the labor aristocracy seems to prevail and to pull the technocracy along; at times it takes a conflicted form, the movement being divided between communist parties dominated by the labor aristocracy and new style socialist parties with a technocratic membership, as in southern Europe.

3.    On this basis, can we propose a distinction between Eurocommunism, which proposes state capitalism independent of Moscow and based on the hegemony of the labor aristocracy within a bloc including national technocracy, and the more traditional social democracy, based on the compromise between monopoly capital and the technocracy and the labor aristocracy?

In other words, should we make a distinction between the new revisionism of Eurocommunism and the old revisionism inherited by social democracy from the Second International? Is Eurocommunism, still in formation and as yet poorly defined, a sign of this new tendency, or is it nothing more than a mask concealing a shift toward social democracy that is still difficult to acknowledge (81a)?

Whether we like it or not, the question of the socialist future of the developed world raises these questions. The mechanical application of the lessons of October, rejected by Luxemburg and Gramsci in their day, can less than ever satisfy those who wish to work for a socialist Europe and leave sectarian ghettoes behind. In particular, the analysis of the weak links that the countries of southern Europe could eventually be involves answering these questions. This analysis, of course, must systematically reexamine the question of the common market and of European unification.

4.    An important stage in the analysis of the system’s tendencies seems to have been reached with Robert Fossaert’s proposition of the concept of “development value” (82-1). Exchange value characterizes the stage of capitalist development based on the fragmentation of capital and the autonomy of production units. It implies that this unit, with its definite boundaries, defines the collective worker whose work is the source of the value created, as it implies that socially necessary labor time is what capital pays this collective worker. The development of the productive forces brings about the emergence of a new form of value because the productivity of labor depends from then on largely on nonmortgageable global social expenses, expenses for research and development which determine the level of science and technology developed. Socially necessary labor is, then, that which is expended in the whole of the social body and the boundaries of the area defining the collective worker are pushed outward to coincide with those of the nation and even of the world system.

Fossaert uses this concept of development value to analyze the articulation of value transfers at each of the stages of capitalist development: on the one hand in the tax-public expenditure system (where he notes that when the transfers produced by this system attain a very high level, 40 percent of the national product, taxation becomes a method of economic control and therefore control through exchange value becomes control through development value); and on the other hand in the money and credit system (where he notes that this passage is marked by the interconnection and nationalization of the credit system).

The emergence of development value reflects the contradiction between the level attained by the productive forces and the continued existence of relations of production that have become inadequate. This contradiction, already apparent, is overcome at least in part by the new mode developing in the West that Fossaert calls capitalist-statist. But development value also exists in the socialist-statist mode, which constitutes a second road (historically, the Soviet road) for the resolution of the contradiction without the abolition of classes.

This analysis seems quite fruitful. The concept of development value gives a precise response to the question of the collective worker in the sense outlined in The Law of Value and Historical Materialism: the opening up of the boundaries of the production unit. This analysis also complements that relating to expanded reproduction under advanced capitalism. I had situated in this framework the necessary introduction of a “department III” for the absorption of the surplus to correspond to the development of the productive forces without the abolition of relations of exploitation,

through the effects of monopolistic competition (cost of sale, etc.) and through state expenditures, both unproductive and productive, in relation to the needs of the development of science and technology.

But we must go further. Doesn’t the value form necessarily continue to exist, although in new guises, along with the division of labor and the state, the foundations of and the arenas for the expression of class antagonisms? Will not the new form of value that accompanies the abolition not of capital itself but of its fragmentation make the relations of exploitation transparent? If this is the case, state capitalist and state socialist modes should tend to reestablish the dominance of ideology in reproduction. The separation between state and civil society, political and economic power, characterizes the true capitalist mode alone, based as it is on the fragmentation of economic power and the economistic ideology of the generalized market.

It is no accident that democracy in the West is a concomitant of capitalism, although its extension to the working classes became possible only with imperialism—but that is no accident either. Transcendence of the fragmentation of capital through development value eliminates the separation between state and civil society, political power and economic power. That is, it eliminates democracy and reestablishes ideological absolutism, whether in the form of “one-dimensional man” in the West or that of nationalist pseudosocialist ideology in the East. This analysis, originating with the Frankfurt school, was inspired not only by Hitlerian totalitarianism and Stalinism but also by the internalized totalitarianism of advanced Western society. It is a salient reminder that the other alternative—the elimination of value, the division of labor, the state, and thus of classes—works in the opposite direction to extend and deepen civil society and thus democracy, which becomes anarchy in the etymological sense. Here we must identify the backward step taken within the Frankfurt school itself, notably by Hannah Arendt. This reduces the rich analysis of the emergence of ideological absolutism in conjunction with the evolution of the economic base down to a political schema of totalitarianism, separate from the base-superstructure dialectic. This reduction, which nullifies the problem of ideological absolutism in the advanced West, ultimately sank through successive degradations to the level of the most threadbare bourgeois ideology, as formulated in polemical discussion or by Raymond Aron and his students in France (Alain Besangon, the “new philosophers,” etc.), who adopt the most banal American politocology.

III. The “three worlds” concept and the reinstatement of the national phenomenon

1. The three worlds concept divides the countries of the world system into three groups: the first world (the two superpowers—the United States and the USSR); the second world (middle rank powers—the secondary imperialisms of Western Europe and Japan and the countries of Eastern Europe); and the third world (countries of Asia, Africa, and Latin America). This classification is intended to replace the old Soviet division into two camps: capitalist and socialist, which itself had evolved with the appearance of the nonaligned group.

The latter classification claimed to distinguish between countries in accord with both their social nature (capitalist or socialist) and their foreign policy (American or Soviet alignment). It claimed that these two aspects were indissolubly linked. Later, when the nonaligned group was created through the initiative of Tito, Nasser, and Nehru, the same logic was extended to these countries. The attempt was made to link their neutral foreign policy to the specific features of their social regimes, characterized as national democratic, the “noncapitalist road. ” The growth of the nonaligned group to include virtually all the countries of Asia and Africa (when the OAU joined as a bloc) has shown this attempt at analysis to be devoid of content.

These Soviet distinctions are incorrect. Instead, I submit that (a) so-called socialist societies are not socialist but constitute a new group of class societies based on the state mode of production; the Chinese maintain that these are state monopoly capitalist societies, while Western societies are monopoly capitalist; (b) the relations between the USSR and the popular democracies are unequal relations; the nature and modalities of their operation remain to be clarified; (c) the societies called national democracies are peripheral capitalist societies; (d) if there is a relationship between a country’s social structure considered in all its subtlety and its external policies, this relation cannot be reduced to a simple linear determination wherein a pro- or anti-Soviet attitude corresponds to a certain degree of socialism; (e) these distinctions serve to mask Soviet superpower policy and the strategies of this policy through successive periods of the cold war and detente; and (f) the alignments preferred (total or partial alignment, nonalignment considered as transitional) have constituted and continue to constitute a blocking factor in the dynamic of internal class struggles and of the antiimperialist struggle. By forcing all social and political forces to choose one camp or the other, and thus to choose between American and Soviet leadership whether they wish to or not, supporters of this position have subordinated social struggles to the imperatives of external alignments. In this sense, they have been a distorting factor in the development of struggles, reducing their potential anticapitalist scope.

2. The reclassification proposed by the Chinese, however, bends the stick too far in the other direction (75-2, 75-3). This concept is based exclusively on the national factor, reduced in this case to the shape and place of nations in the system. There are two superpowers, which alone are capable of direct and indirect action everywhere in the world. There are developed societies which are economically independent (with unequal interdependence) because they were historically created as autocentered societies (capitalist or state capitalist) but which are incapable of politically intervening on the world scale. There are underdeveloped societies, which are economically dependent, because they were historically created as subjected and extraverted peripheries and are politically and militarily weak and unstable. The classification has nothing to say about the precise social nature of these regimes, except that they are not socialist. An exception is made for China (unclassifiable or third world?), the Asian socialist countries (Korea, Vietnam, Cambodia, Laos), and possibly Cuba, which are seen as third world and socialist at the same time.

This position reinstates the national factor which the other ignored, a reinstatement both timely and amply justified everywhere by the facts. The national factor endures even during socialist construction (think of the relations between China, Vietnam, and Cambodia, for instance, or between Yugoslavia and Albania). Finally, the reclassification helps to rid us of remaining illusions about socialist states and the noncapitalist road. The reinstatement of the national factor brings precision to the formula, “the states want independence, the nations liberation, and the peoples revolution” (75-1) at the same time as this very formula establishes the limits of the national factor (the peoples want revolution).

If we perceive that states and nations are realities, not of course independent of class but not reducible to classes in a unilateral way, we can better understand the formulation. Peoples are defined as anticapitalist class blocs, these blocs being different in the center and in the periphery of the imperialist system. Nations are the historical units of antagonistic classes; they exist. Given this, what is called the national interest is nothing other than the reflection of the modalities which the world character of capitalism imposes on local hegemonic blocs, which must become integrated into the system of class opposition and alliance on a world scale. These nations operate by means of states which are more or less national and implement policy, that is, internal and international alliances.

3. But the three worlds concept does not explain reality if it is taken literally and if one reduces all reality to the national factor as reinstated by it. This would amount to substituting nations for classes, a substitution that would encourage us to forego a concrete analysis of the internal and external class conflicts and alliances by means of which the system operates, reproduces itself, and is transformed.

The USSR and the United States are indeed both superpowers and both class societies. But they do not have the same history and do not occupy symmetrical positions in the world system. The United States is an imperialist superpower which grew out of the gradual establishment of imperialism during the last century and out of the partial eclipse of secondary imperialists as world powers. It operates throughout the nonsocialist and non-Soviet world in accordance with the economic laws of imperialism (capital investment, extraction of surplus labor, etc.). The USSR was established as a new class society on the basis of a socialist revolution, after having been confined within its boundaries and then within those of its specific area of influence. Its internal mode of organization leads it to intervene elsewhere in a different way. Besides, since the internal social structures of the two superpowers are different, the reciprocal relations between these internal structures and the external interventions in which each of the superpowers is engaged are different.

Western Europe and Japan on the one hand and Eastern Europe on the other are not in analogous positions either. They differ as to internal structure (hegemonic blocs, ideologies, etc.) as well as international position (secondary imperialist heirs, small countries). And the social structures of the peripheral countries are different enough to make the nature of their states different (except if one accepts the extremist thesis that grants no autonomy to peripheral states).

The different states of the second and third worlds are not struggling for independence in the same way, nor for the same type of independence. The different nations of the third world are not struggling for liberation in the same way. As to the popular blocs of revolutionary classes, they are obviously different from one country to another. The enemies of independence, of these different types of liberation, and of different revolutions on the order of the day are not the same everywhere, nor are they organized into blocs in the same way. Thus one will be wrong nine times out of ten in asserting that the primary enemy is the same everywhere and for everyone: clearly it is not the same in Angola as in Czechoslovakia.

Thus we can see that external policy is in no way a privileged domain which is in perfect conformity with the class nature of different nations. Moreover, it is sufficient to examine how alliances are made and unmade (for example, Ethiopia and Somalia) to understand this. This said, a general principle may be formulated here. An autonomous popular bloc that leads a struggle according to its own interests can profitably make very broad internal and external alliances (e.g., Vietnam). But if these alliances are used to fill in gaps in the popular bloc, they turn the popular forces into the plaything of both internal and external reaction.

4.    The analysis of how the economic, political, and ideological network of the capitalist world operates is doubtless fairly advanced today. Unfortunately, we cannot say the same of the Soviet network. Works concerning the economic function of the division of labor within COMECON are still superficial and generally inspired by revisionist ideologues (80b). As to the critics, they are still too eager to transfer to this new reality the results of the analysis of the Western system.

5.    The Chinese thesis of social imperialism and Soviet expansionism has the advantage of proposing an integration of Soviet policy into an overall frame of reference that gives concrete definition to the new (starting in the mid 1960s) international situation. According to this, after the Second World War a new stage of imperialism arose, characterized by American hegemony over the whole of the imperialist system, the confinement of the Soviet world, and Chinese isolation. This period supposedly ended and a new phase began, in which American hegemony was challenged, primarily and fundamentally by national liberation struggles (the most important fact for the United States was the failure of its policy in Asia, in China, and in Vietnam), and secondarily by the modification of interimperialist relations between the American hegemonic element and European and Japanese subordinate elements. Within this framework, the resurgence of struggles in the weak centers (southern Europe) interacted with the rise of the national liberation movement, just as the bourgeoisies of the periphery tried to gain a second wind by extracting a new and less unfavorable division of world surplus value.

These changes in hegemony and world balance have supposedly led the Soviet Union to plan to exploit the American decline with the goal of establishing a new empire over a bigger area. In the past, the USSR was locked within the area of its direct dependencies, beyond which it had no bases, and the revisionist parties were themselves confined to their own local political lives. American imperialism exercised hegemony over a vast, organized system, thanks to the twofold support of the European and Japanese subordinate bourgeoisies (the countries of the second world) and the exploiting classes of the third world in diverse alliances.

This analysis presupposes that the Soviet Union evolved from a revolution which was socialist to begin with but which degenerated from the construction of socialism toward a class society, one which does not yet have an empire equal to its appetite. The countries of Eastern Europe, which can be classified as part of the second world due to their level of development, remain small countries. But the major problem is that the USSR does not have bases in the third world. There is no system in the third world which is solidly connected to a class alliance with the Soviet system.

The USSR has taken advantage of occasional alliances with the bourgeoisies at the head of national liberation movements at one moment or the other, intending thereby to wrest them from American hegemony and temporarily succeeding. But the case of Egypt indicated the fragility of these alliances. Thus the USSR would now try to exploit the American decline and to establish its empire by seeking more serious positions in the second and third worlds. It would seek in particular to use the possible transformation of old subordinate imperialisms into subordinate social imperialisms.

Within this framework, social imperialism pursues goals more or less analogous to those of classical imperialism: the search for external sources of exploitation to strengthen the revisionist alliance (subjection of the working class to its dominant class within the framework of the hegemony of nationalist ideology) which would supplant the social-democratic alliance. Of course, this search must take specific forms adapted to the concrete situation. For instance, the search for raw materials is perhaps secondary given the autarchic development of these within a huge country originally created by a socialist revolution. The attempt to subordinate more advanced industrialized countries capable of furnishing more effective technology would perhaps better suit the concrete Soviet situation.

In this perspective, we must also disentangle strategic goals from tactical means. The search for foreign bases may be only a tactical means in the struggle against the major competing imperialism to bring about a new and more satisfying division elsewhere. The Arab, Indian, and African worlds, “the soft underbelly” of the periphery—in contrast to Latin America, infinitely more subjected to North American hegemony, where there is conflict between the national liberation movements, the interests of hegemonic imperialism, the interests of the secondary imperialisms which exercise their domination there, and important local conflicts—can become the main arenas for the “conflict of the century” without necessarily being their real final or primary objective.

It remains to be seen if this analysis is correct, that is, if it corresponds not to plausible objectives of what the Chinese call the “new tsars” but to their real intentions. Writings like those of A. Amalrik (80d-3) even if they lack scientific value, at least serve to remind us that there are ideological currents in the USSR that see the promotion of anti-Chinese belligerency as a means to overcome the internal crisis and particularly the revolt of the oppressed Asiatic peoples of the Soviet Union. The leaders in Peking pay close attention to these facts, which are poorly understood in the West. They cannot at any price tolerate the creation of a Moscow-Washington axis against them. But experience has shown that such fears, as justified as they may be, often hinder more than they promote a cool and correct analysis of the enemy’s strategy.

Chapter 8

The Theory of Imperialism and the Contemporary Crisis

From the foregoing analysis, I can draw eight conclusions.

First conclusion: the theory of imperialism is synonymous with the theory of capital accumulation on a world scale, the articulation of various modes of extortion of surplus labor based on the specific modalities of unequal development in our era. The fundamental law that governs accumulation on a world scale is thus the expression of the law of value operating on the scale of the imperialist system as a whole. So to get to the root of the problem of imperialism, we must go back to the law of value. Indeed, in Capital, the theory of the capitalist mode of production is constructed on the basis of a precise elaboration of the law of value, which constitutes its infrastructure.

1. The law of value not only accounts for the character of the social product in the capitalist mode, that is, its commodity nature. It not only reveals the origin of profit, that is, surplus value. It also enables us to understand the laws of accumulation that control the reproduction and expansion of the capitalist mode. These laws, expressed in the equilibria and disequilibria between the two departments of capitalist production (production of means of production and production of means of consumption), place the value of labor power on an objective basis. In fact, the laws of accumulation establish the objective connection between the value of labor power and the level of development of the productive forces (90-3, 90-4).

The unity of the commodity, capital, and labor markets, that is, the coexistence of a bourgeois state, a national bourgeoisie, and a national working class implicitly and explicitly constitutes the framework necessary to give meaning to the law of value.

2.    The underlying spatial hypothesis corresponding to the analysis of Capital is that the law of value effectively operates within the framework of each of the national capitalist spaces (England, France, Germany, the United States, etc.). Actually, this hypothesis corresponds to the reality of the middle of the last century, which is what Marx analyzed. It no longer corresponds to reality. With imperialism, capital circulates and is reproduced on a world scale. Commodities are tending to become globalized, as is the working class itself. There is no longer a single national space, not even the United States, which has a framework adequate for the reproduction of the conditions of accumulation. The globalization of the productive process implies the globalization of the space within which the law of value operates.

3.    The theory of imperialism must therefore be constructed on the infrastructural basis of the theory of value operating on a world scale. In these conditions, the law of value must account for the different levels in the selling price of labor in the different segments of the imperialist system.

My argument here is (a) that commodities, because they are global, have a single world value; (b) that capital, because it is global, tends toward an average rate of return, or toward a specific range of rates structured in terms of this latter rate; (c) that the labor market remains segmented and that because of this local conditions of the class struggle allow for unequal rates of surplus value.

There are no possible alternative explanations for differences in the price of labor power. Those who deny the objective relation between the value of labor power and the development of the productive forces are forced to make of real wages an empirical category. This is either biologically determined (“subsistence”), as the Ricardians believe, and thus replaces the law of accumulation with a law of population; or it is indeterminate (“the historical and moral elements”) and thus loses all rigor, becoming a synonym for anything at all.

Therefore, if we are to establish a relationship between the value of labor power and the development of the productive forces, we must specify which productive forces we mean: sectoral, national, or global. Within any national space, the productive forces are unequally developed from one branch to the other, but labor power has the same value. Any discussion that links wages with sectoral productivity is necessarily marginalist and tautological, for one cannot compare productivity from one branch to the other. The unity of the commodity, capital, and labor markets on the one hand, and the determination of the equilibria of accumulation within this market on the other, forces us to conclude that the value of labor power is objectively related to the national (average) level of the development of the productive forces.

But given the globalization of the commodity and capital markets, as well as that of the space within which the equilibria of accumulation are realized, the value of labor power on the scale of the world system is connected to the “average” world level of development of the productive forces. National differences in the price of labor power are no longer due to different average levels of national development but to the segmentation of the working class. Thus the state-politics-class struggle elements must be introduced into the theory of imperialism.

Even on the empirical level, it does not make sense to speak of “differences in productivity.” In the same branch of production, producing identical commodities, sold on the same market at the same price, obtained by the same technology, labor has the same productivity, although wages may differ. Thus in South Korea, in the same industries as in the United States, wages are ten or twelve times less, although productivity is the same.

4. Differences in the price of labor power, which can be explained by the concrete conditions of class struggle, raise the question of the reproduction of labor power in all its ramifications. There is nothing to say that these real conditions everywhere and of

necessity will permit the reproduction of each of the segments of labor power. We forget, for instance, that Ireland had a population equal to that of England at the time of its conquest, at the start of mercantilism and the transition to capitalism. The Irish nation and people were destroyed by the same processes which fostered English expansion. There is nothing to say that in our time similar occurrences of destruction of labor power will not characterize the imperialist system.

5.    To analyze the imperialist system is to analyze a system of social formations and not the capitalist mode extended to the world. In this system all noncapitalist modes are subjected to the domination of capital and surplus labor is thus wrenched from nonproletarianized producers to be transformed into profit for capital. This formal domination affects the conditions of reproduction of nonproletarianized labor power and, again, there is nothing to say that conditions of its reproduction are assured.

6.    The price of labor power in the imperialist centers is not independent of that in the dominated peripheries, for the “average price” of labor power as a whole must correspond to its value in relation to the development of the productive forces on a world scale. The price of labor power in the center is thus indissolubly linked to the imperialist character of the system of capitalist exploitation.

7.    What happens on the level of the price of commodities (unequal exchange) thus does not result from phenomena occurring on the level of circulation but reflects on this level the conditions of the genesis and division of surplus labor (in its noncapitalist forms, in its capitalist form of surplus value, and in its immediate appearance as profit) in the imperialist system.

8.    Capitalist societies are by no means composed only of the working class and the bourgeoisie. In the dominant centers, numerous classes and layers participate in productive functions and/ or fulfill nonproductive functions. But the division of functions and occupations is not independent of the division of labor on a world scale. Who produces value, and who consumes it? This question cannot be answered without examining the imperialist system as a whole.

9.    The type of development resulting from the laws of accumulation operating on a world scale thus has an overall impact which goes beyond the question of the price of labor power. For instance, the concentration in the center of the consumption of natural resources produced in the periphery modifies the conditions for the further development of the productive forces.

10.    The superficial question of whether or not the Western working class profits from imperialism therefore leads to sterile polemicizing. An example of this type of polemic is the word game of likening the category of profit to the everyday meaning of the verb “to profit”; this tries to evade the question by redefining it.

Certainly the workers in the center of the imperialist system are exploited by capital, although a thorough analysis of the effects of the parasitism inherent in the imperialist system is far from being completed. But it is equally certain that the destruction of the imperialist system entails the end of the transfer of value generated in the periphery. This would be consistent with better living conditions for the workers in the center only if capitalist relations were overturned. This in turn would involve a completely different model of development than that derived from the laws of capitalist accumulation in general and, a fortiori, of imperialist accumulation.

Second conclusion: any crisis in the capitalist system expresses a j j malfunctioning of the law of value under the impact of the class! struggle. Crisis manifests itself through disequilibria which make j the realization of value impossible and, as a result, bring about a I fall in the rate of profit. In this way, every crisis is a crisis of the ' relations of capitalist production.

1. This general proposition is inadequate to characterize any particular crisis at any given stage in the evolution of the system. In fact, in the nineteenth century for example, because the law of value was operating on the basis of national spaces, crises were national crises, although they could be transmitted from the hegemonic center of the day (Great Britain) to other countries.

If today the basis for the operation of the law of value is the whole of the imperialist system, crises must first be understood at this level. That is, they are expressed in the impossibility of assuring the world circulation of capital and the world realization of value. Class struggle on a world scale creates this impossibility, which is why the major dimension in which the current crisis finds expression is the field of the international division of labor.

2. This conclusion does not preclude other “economic” and j “noneconomic” aspects of the global crisis: crisis in the expansion j of the multinationals and crisis in the noncompetitive sectors; unemployment and inflation; crisis in the international monetary system; ideological crisis (the “silent revolution” in lifestyle after 1968); political crisis (affirmation of “national interests” in various places); and social crises on the periphery of the system (Ethiopia, Iran, Zimbabwe, and South Africa).

Third conclusion: the theory of imperialism and of its crisis must include a theory of the state in the imperialist epoch. This theory must not be based on generalities, as it too often is. It is not enough to conceive of the state as the instrument of dominant economic interests: yesterday those of the national bourgeoisies, today those of the monopolies.

1.    Which monopolies do contemporary states represent, national or multinational and primarily American monopolies? Under these circumstances, what place do national, hegemonic, concrete class alliances have? Do not historical conditions unique to each country permanently control the composition-dislocation-recomposition of these hegemonic blocs, the membership of which varies under the direct impact of the class struggle and the accumulation of capital? On the periphery of the system are not these successive blocs visibly linked to the modalities of the international division of labor? And do they not reflect the content of the hegemonic international class alliance which ensures the global circulation of capital? The contradictions shaking these diverse hegemonic blocs under the effect of internal class struggles are manifest on the world level as contradictions between opposing states.

2.    The very process of accumulation has gradually modified the state-capital relation. In the nineteenth century, the European capitalist nation-states had already been established during the mercantilist era (England and France), or were gradually being established along with the development of industrial capitalism (Germany and Italy). At the time, the state space (national, in general) and the capitalist market (threefold market of commodities, capital, and labor power) coincided. The hegemonic class alliances were national alliances, related to the specific historical conditions of the bourgeois revolution.

British world hegemony, of course, involved transnational alliances, for instance with the dominant latifundiary classes of Latin America and the “feudal” classes of the Orient and of India. After 1815 the European countries, notably France, England’s competitor during the mercantilist era, accepted this hegemony. France established an embryonic world market (limited to certain commodities), which coexisted with fully established national markets (in the threefold guise indicated above), and organized a corresponding political and military balance (“the European balance”).

During the last three decades of the century, sharp competition (during the “great crisis” of 1875-1896) led to a new stage in the centralization and concentration of capital, a stage characterized by Lenin, following Hobson and Hilferding, as the imperialist stage. The monopolies in question were formed on the bases of already established national markets and retained this characteristic during the entire period until just after the Second World War. Beginning in 1945 the relation between the state and the monopolies again changed, as we shall see.

3. Giovanni Arrighi has provided what is probably the most finely developed analysis of the effects of these changes on state-market (here, synonymous with capital, monopolies, economy) relations (7lb-5). According to Arrighi, the fit between the national state space and the monopolies at the end of the nineteenth century explains certain crucial aspects of the social life of the entire period.

This fit first of all explains the transfer of the locus of competition among monopolies from the strictly economic arena to that of a struggle among imperialist states. From there it explains the militarist character of the period and the establishment, on two occasions, of two coalitions which matched forces in two world wars. The period as a whole (1914-1945) was like a Thirty Years’ War between Germany and the United States for the succession to declining British hegemony. This war was settled in 1945 with the definitive and accepted superiority of North American power.

The fit also explains the character of the new wave of class struggles at the beginning of the century (the 1903-1907 wave). Competition during the nineteenth century had taken place in an economic atmosphere involving a tendency for prices to drop as a result of increased productivity. The new forms of competition among monopolies for their part led to a tendency for prices to rise. Wages lost the “natural protection” resulting from the drop in prices and struggles to raise wages consequently intensified. The ambivalent attitude of the workers’ movement toward the colonial question and toward competing imperialisms (the workers’ movement tended to support its “own” national monopolies against foreign competitors) explains why this wave of economic struggles subsided before the preparations for world war.

Arrighi’s analysis explains the nature of the “retrograde” hegemonic class alliances established during the period. The competing monopolist bourgeoisies had to strengthen “national unity” through a policy of allying with those middle layers which the development of these same monopolies (e.g., peasantry, small enterprises, etc.) was destroying. From fascisms to popular fronts to the New Deal, this type of alliance was used to protect national sectors that had lost competitive power (e.g., agriculture) or had not yet acquired it (e.g., steel).

Thus we can understand the characteristics of the class struggles of the interwar period. The wave of the 1920s following the Russian revolution was the most politicized of the successive waves in the West. The workers’ movement of that era aspired to state power and the suppression of capitalist private property in favor of national appropriation. The failure of this wave and the character of the retrograde hegemonic alliances erected to combat it accounts for the seriousness of the 1930 crisis. The new wave of struggles, that of the 1930s, was from the first defensive: the movement first aspired to full employment in a capitalist economy, then it accepted the moves toward war.

Arrighi develops a striking contrast between the characteristics of the period 1880-1945 and those of the succeeding period. First, the uneontested hegemony of the United States following the Second World War fostered the reestablishment of a world market. This latter, I might add, was considerably more developed than its nineteenth-century predecessor of the era of British preimperialist hegemony, as it included a decisive proportion of commodity production (notably basic products which were all globalized) and of capital. The reestablishment of sectoral and international mobility cleared the way for the simultaneous world expansion of American monopolies and the strong economic growth of the system as a whole, in contrast to the relative stagnation of the interwar period. But there was no longer a fit between state space and economic space: the law of value had become globalized.

Second, the period immediately following the Second World War differed from that following the first: struggles were limited (practically to Italy and to France) and they appeared to be more the tail end of the previous period than the harbingers of a new wave. The epicenter of political revolution had already shifted away from Europe.

Third, strong economic growth strengthened the economic position of the working class, whose struggles were generally successful on the economic level. This reduced the flexibility of the system—all the more so as workers’ parties became central to the political life of Western Europe. Under these conditions, capital adopted a twofold strategy. On the one hand, it aimed at “refurbishing” its alliances by modernizing them, replacing old with new layers (e.g., technocracies, labor aristocracies), thus better to meet the requirements of accumulation. On the other hand, it aimed at redividing the working class on the basis of the opposition between the unskilled mass worker (often an immigrant, a minority member,

a youth, or a female) and the statutory worker. The first strategy seems to have succeeded in the United States and in northern Europe but to have encountered obstacles in France and Italy, forcing capital to attempt to revert to retrograde alliances and/or to accept a subordinate position relative to Germany in the industrial division of labor. The second strategy seems, tragically, to have had more success in the West, at least in the current stage.

The characteristics of the wave of struggles during the 1960s thus become clear: this was a depoliticized wave, with political demands being expressed by layers outside of the working class (especially in 1968). The current crisis erupted against this background. Under the circumstances, we must be concerned about the directions which a workers’ movement on the defensive might take. Could not the privileged sector of the working class, less affected by unemployment and more by inflation, adopt the same bourgeois goal of monetary stability in a world market restructured in terms of the new requirements of accumulation? There are indications that this is the case; the evolution of the German workers’ movement seems to portend such new tendencies.

4. The above analysis can be combined with the periodization of the system which I have proposed. On the level of politico-military balances, the succession from British hegemony to the opposition of the blocs to American hegemony fits in perfectly. The question still remains: Is American hegemony on the decline?

The colonial phase of the center-periphery division of labor corresponds logically to the first imperialist phase. Colonial and semicolonial dependent zones were relegated to the role of furnishers of raw materials to the industrial monopolies of the competing metropoles and of outlets for the noncompetitive industries which sustained the retrograde alliances in the metropoles. Those metropoles which enjoyed historic advantages (Great Britain and France) saw their positions coveted by those who came on the scene later and thus lacked espace vital. The interwar crisis accentuated these imperial retreats.

The neocolonial phase corresponds to the reconstruction of the world market and the expansion of the multinationals. Industrialization based on import substitution here resulted from the first wave of national liberation, which forced a renegotiation of international class alliances.

The current crisis reveals the decisive nature of the contradictions at this level. In fact, the primary obstacle to the reestablishment of the global circulation of capital lies precisely in the exhaustion of the potential for accumulation based on the division of labor which undergirded industrialization based on import substitution. Hence the convergence of the demand of the third world bourgeoisies for a new order based on export industry with the redeployment strategy of the monopolies. However, as we shall see, this convergence is fraught with contradictions, particularly in regard to the question of the state.

5. The concept of the world market reconstructed within the framework of American hegemony is not the same as Kautsky’s notion of superimperialism. The latter, in fact, ignores the state (reduced to the role of the board of directors of the monopolies). This economism reappears in the non-Marxist “radical” theses which make of the multinationals the true and only “masters of the world.” My analysis, on the contrary, starts from the contradiction between the state and the monopolies, as reflecting class contradictions within national societies both in the center and on the periphery.

Thus an analysis of the strategies of contending social forces and of the possible outcomes of the current crisis requires additional reflection about the state. For the center, we need to reflect on all the questions currently on the agenda, such as those relating to the construction of Europe and to regionalism. For the periphery, we need to reflect on the question of the content of national liberation in the current period.

Fourth conclusion: the definition of the evolving relation between the state and capital provides the appropriate framework for an analysis of the significance of the contemporary hierarchy of imperialisms and of the current question of Europe.

1.    National states are still the only supreme political units in the contemporary system. There is no supranational state. On the international level, institutions such as the International Monetary Fund do not constitute even the germ of one; they are only the extension of the system of American hegemony based on the world market during the 1945-1970 phase. On the level of Europe there is the germ of a parastate organization, but insofar as the framework within which class struggle takes place and hegemonic alliances are formed remains strictly national, we must continue to speak of imperialisms (in the plural).

In the final analysis, I believe that the imperialist hierarchy is a function of the place assigned to the productive systems of the industrial monopolies in the division of labor. On these grounds, the most powerful imperialists are the United States, Japan, and Germany (in that order). England, France, Italy, and the other states of the center are second-rank imperialists. Economic advantages inherited from colonial empires, such as inequalities in political, ideological, and military positions, are no more in this framework than are means by which secondary imperialisms can negotiate the terms of their alignment with first-rank imperialisms.

The thesis of a return to finance imperialism and of the restored supremacy of finance over industry is, in my opinion, extremely weak. This view is based on the growing international indebtedness of the third world and of the socialist world, the relative withdrawal of direct investment in the third world in favor of indebtedness, especially state indebtedness, to private financial consortia. But these developments might be conjunctural, related to the structural crisis in the international division of labor. Concrete analysis of the debts shows, in fact, that they result in part from the impact of the crisis on the third world and in part from the requirement of inserting the latter into the world circulation of capital (e.g., refloating of the balance of payments, consolidation of bourgeoisies, etc.).

2.    If a European imperialism is coming into being, it is not yet clear what relation it will have to American imperialism— competitor or ally. The construction of Europe which is taking place today serves only as a means for secondary imperialisms to mitigate their inadequacies. It remains entirely questionable whether the system will tend toward the break-up of the world market, the end of American hegemony, and the reestablishment of a state-capital fit ultimately on the level of Europe, or whether Europe and the states that comprise it will keep their current positions as relays in the unified world market system under the thumb of predominantly American monopolies.

In principle and abstractly, a crisis situation such as the system is now undergoing would lead either to an exacerbation of interimperialist contradictions or to an alignment of the weaker with the stronger. If in 1930 the crisis called up the first solution, that was because of the state-monopoly fit which characterized the period. Transnationalization accounts for the realignment currently taking place after several halfhearted assertions at autonomy at the time of the 1973 crisis.

3. The tendency to realignment raises the question of what political attitude to take toward Europe. The most commonly accepted position on the European Left is that of support for Europe, albeit for a Europe of workers rather than of monopolies. Implicit in this position is an economistic retreat before the “objective necessities of the development of the productive forces. ” The formation of a European state is, in fact, considered to be a prelude to the socialist transformation of the relations of production, now postponed indefinitely. If this stage is accepted as necessary, there could follow a second postponement based on the need to construct a planetary state in keeping with the requirements of the productive forces. This would amount to abandoning any belief in the possibility of socialist breakthroughs based on the effects of unequal development on the political conditions of the class struggle.

My position, by comparison, is that the Leninist strategy of rupture remains valid today. This strategy raises the question of “disengagement” vis-a-vis the international system, a question to which I will return.

Fifth conclusion: the question of the relations between the state and capital is also raised in the current crisis on the periphery of the system, although in different forms.

1. Contrary to what occurred in the center, the development of peripheral capitalism, far from establishing nations, destroyed them. The extraverted character of this development and its distorting effects narrowed the scope for the formation of the local market: the domination of foreign capital made the establishment of a local capital market impossible. Finally, the persistence of forms of formal domination limited the scope for the formation of a labor market.

What, then, is the state here? The administrative excrescence of the imperialist state apparatus? In part. But it is also and primarily the expression of a local hegemonic alliance linked to the imperialist alliance.

This accounts for the double fragility of peripheral states, both the fragility of the hegemonic alliance, fraught with contradictions mirroring those that pit it against the popular masses, and national fragility. The fragility of the hegemonic alliance is nothing more than the effect of the transfer to the periphery of the contradictions in the accumulation of capital on a world scale. The weakest alliances, such as those based on the predominance of a comprador bureaucracy practically without a local bourgeoisie, result in a local state that is virtually a foreign administrative excrescence and open the country to permanent outside interference. Even alliances which seem solider, such as those based on an industrial bourgeoisie and a national state, remain fragile, as the events in Iran demonstrate.

As for national fragility, integration into the imperialist system was often effected on a preexisting substratum of more or less heterogenous ethnic groups and communities. In these circumstances it was even more difficult for a national state to crystallize, as contradictions among the people could be and were exploited both by the different segments of the local hegemonic alliance and by external forces. Here we have a national liberation movement without a nation. If this latter fails correctly to resolve the contradictions among the people, it remains weak and its weakness gives power to the hegemonic blocs, however fragile, which ensure imperialist integration. When, exceptionally, the national liberation movement arises in a precapitalist nation (e.g., East Asia) this favorable conjuncture exposes the fragility of the local exploiting alliance.

2. It is necessary to understand the meaning of the current battle over the international division of labor, redeployment, and the new international economic order. In the abstract, the new order, based on accelerated industrialization in the periphery within the international division of labor, corresponds to the objective requirements of accumulation: a rise in the rate of surplus value and, from there, of profit on a world scale (74a-1).

This is only an abstraction, however, since the object of the current struggle is precisely the division of this surplus value among different segments of capital. Here the interest of dominant capital—that of the multinationals—clashed with that of the peripheral bourgeoisies. Redeployment is the strategy of the former; it presupposes weakened peripheral states. The new international economic order is the strategy of the latter; it presupposes strengthened peripheral states, capable of organizing into export cartels in order to impose a rise in the price of basic products and to exercise national control of natural resources, to retain the benefit from price rises through nationalization and fiscal policy, to control the investment of these surpluses so as to at least partially structure the productive systems to give them more autonomy, and so on.

From the beginning in 1973, the struggle between the two lines was joined. Although during the years 1973-1975 the new international economic order appeared to be the expression of a united front against imperialism, the divisive strategy adopted by the latter of supporting the right wing of the front has succeeded in dividing the third world (third and fourth worlds, “progressive” and “proimperialist” countries). If this strategy has not completely succeeded, it has at least eliminated the danger of a confrontation.

It would be a mistake, however, to stop with this last statement. The violent class struggles rocking the societies of the periphery presage the collapse of certain hegemonic blocs which maintain the current balance. Once again the events in Iran demonstrate this. There the very success of redeployment, marked by exceptional rates of growth, made the contradictions more explosive. For the working class which is forming, far from being less capable of politicized struggles, is on the contrary moved toward them almost spontaneously, notwithstanding the Western prejudice according to which the most advanced working classes would necessarily be the most revolutionary. It is of little matter under which ideological flag the masses rebel: this in large measure is a function of circumstantial and subjective conditions (the predictable consequence of the strategy of the “noncapitalist road”). What is more important is the fact that they are rebelling against the expansion of capital. A new wave of the national liberation movement, with a strong “populist” content, at least in the beginning, has already contributed to the development of the crisis of imperialism.

3. In the circumstances of this struggle, can we discern the emergence of new capitalist national states, the expression of the gradual transfer of capitalism from its origins in Europe to the whole of the planet? Here again, in the abstract, if the process of capital accumulation could be indefinitely extended, it would lead to the imposition of capitalist relations of production on all the world’s societies through the suppression of all other forms of productive relations and thus to the homogenization of the whole of the planet.

But we cannot go from the recognition of this abstract tendency to the conclusion that new capitalist centers would in fact gradually emerge. Up to the present, at each stage in the development of the imperialist system, center-periphery relations have been based on an unequal division of labor. An economic analysis of the export industries set up in certain peripheral countries and based on cheap labor and/or abundant natural resources, as well as an overall political analysis of the integration of these countries into the world system (local hegemonic alliances and dominant international alliances, the nature and role of the state, systems of ideological and political life, etc.) makes it impossible to envision the reversal of this tendency.

The opposing viewpoint always holds up “examples” of the most advanced third world countries which are in the process of industrializing (today Brazil, South Korea, Taiwan, Iran, etc.) in support of a simple theory of “stages” of development. Whether in its conventional version (that of the World Bank) or in one of its versions which use Marxist terms (cf. 70e-l), this thesis replaces an analysis in historical materialist terms (which is always holistic) with an economistic analysis reduced to the quantitative measure of industrial production.

Sixth conclusion: the analysis of imperialism in historical materialist terms cannot stop with the discernment of broad economic tendencies in the accumulation of capital but must relate these broad tendencies to the struggles of classes, nations, and states on a world scale. Thus in order to analyze these systemic contradictions at a given stage in their concrete development, as well as the concrete interrelation of these contradictions, we must place them in the framework of the real international political conjuncture of the period.

1. Our era could perhaps be interpreted as being that of the confrontation between declining capitalism and rising socialism. But we cannot be satisfied with this general and abstract proposition. Confrontation is not this direct; it is only implicit, hidden behind direct confrontations of a different type. Thus with regard to class confrontations in the center of the system, the current goal of the workers’ movement is not socialism: the goal is economic (full employment, protection of buying power eroded by inflation, etc.). Breakthroughs in the realm of social life generally occur apart from these confrontations. In the periphery, the confrontations are “silently” at work within the national liberation movement, without a clear consciousness of the goals always obtaining (thus the existence of populist forms). Overall, given these circumstances, the confrontations which occupy center stage are those between states, east and west, north and south.

2.    The East-West conflict has long been confused with a confrontation between socialism and capitalism. The Soviet version of the division into three worlds confounds the supposed social nature of regimes (socialist or capitalist) with the foreign policies of states (alignment with the USSR or the United States). Within the framework of this thesis, it has been necessary to create an “intermediate” category (“progressive regimes,” the “noncapitalist road,” “national democracy”) which is tactically useful.

3.    The Marxist method requires us to invert the terms of this argument. We must start from the real class content of these regimes. No tactical consideration justifies ignoring the basic question of the class nature of the Eastern countries and, based on this, the real goals of their international policies.

In this corrected perspective, if the USSR is not socialist, it is a power which we have to characterize. Doubtless it is a superpower, since it alone can aspire to world hegemony and/or to a division of the world with the United States, its only military competitor. We need a better understanding of the laws and requirements of its expansion. These cannot necessarily be borrowed from what we know about capitalist laws, since we are dealing with a new type of class society (i. e., the statist mode of production).

4.    The Soviet division (whether old or new, it continues to be the basis of successive theses produced to fit the conjuncture of the cold war, detente, coexistence, or hardening of the line) fulfills obvious ideological functions. It allows for the subordination of class struggles and anti-imperialist struggles to the goals of the USSR itself. It contributes to confusing, by mixing them together, “progressive forces, ” authentic popular forces, and bourgeois and neobourgeois (statist) forces conjuncturally allied to the former. By using elastic concepts (such as “socialism” loosely used, or “progressive forces,” which amounts to the liberal use of the terms “liberty” and “the rights of man”) this conceptualization of world forces subordinates strategy to mere tactics. It does not allow us to discern the primary enemy (which depends on one’s position: it is obviously not the same for the Czech working class as for Angolan peasants). It does not allow us to distinguish the moment in the evolution of the balance of power between the two superpowers. (For instance, after the defeat in Indochina, was the United States on the defensive, its capacity for direct military intervention paralyzed, as it seems to be with the Carter administration?)

5. In the confrontation between states, secondary imperialisms (those of Europe and Japan) seem currently to be realigning themselves, for the reasons indicated above. In the north-south confrontation, the variety of situations ranging from comprador bureaucracies to revolutionary peasant alliances prevent global judgments. In the strategy of the uninterrupted revolution by stages on the agenda for the periphery of the imperialist system, the important thing is that the exploited working and peasant classes be capable of autonomous expression. Then and only then will tactical internal and external alliances be subordinated to the strategic goal of the socialist transition. Failing this, popular forces will remain the plaything of local reactionary forces and of external forces.

Seventh conclusion: if we continually keep imperialism at the center of our thinking about contemporary capitalism, we will correctly identify the obstacle to socialism today. This obstacle is the difficulty with disengagement. This difficulty is even greater for the societies of the center than for those of the periphery. This, finally, is the meaning of the fact of imperialism.

1. Built on the imperialist surplus, the societies of the center, in their social composition as well as in the “advantages” gained from their access to the world’s natural resources, have difficulty conceiving of the necessity for a global restructuring. A popular antiimperialist bloc capable of overthrowing the hegemonic bloc is therefore difficult to establish. The recent experiences of Portugal and Italy serve to illustrate this difficulty. On the other hand, in the societies of the periphery, disengagement is the precondition for a development of the productive forces sufficient to meet the needs and demands of the great majority.

2.    It is clearly this basic situational difference which explains why, up to the present, the major breaches in the capitalist system have been made from the periphery of the system. This suggests a parallel with the transition from antiquity to feudalism. The Roman Empire was a system for the centralization of the surplus (tributary and slave). Further development of the productive forces required the break-up of this system of centralization, which was impeding progress in the periphery. This explains the substitution of autonomous feudal zones, established in the least advanced periphery of the empire (Celtic and Germanic Europe). Today, in the same way, the development of the periphery of the system requires the abolition of the system for the centralization of the surplus which the imperialist world market represents.

3.    This process by which capitalist relations are superceded through a break on the level of the centralization of the surplus corresponding to the most advanced productive forces obviously creates a series of new problems (the possibility of partial regressions, restorations, etc.) which socialism must confront. We have to accept this. But in the perspective of an effective transitional strategy, we must also consider an alternative outcome defined in international terms, in order to break out of the dead end of national isolation.

The alternative outcome ultimately could make possible a socialist transition starting with the weakest links in the central imperialist chain. It could also speed up the development of socialist relations in the peripheral zones that have left the system. Finally, it could ease the way for the establishment of a first anti-imperialist stage in the transition for those periphery regions which have not yet broken the chains of dependency.

The strategy of an alliance among socialist southern Europe, the Arab world, and Africa falls within this perspective (79-1, 79-2). Unfortunately, this vision is as yet little understood by most people, still less supported by them. Doubtless the forces which could be favorable to it in Europe have been primarily responsible for its failure up to the present. Currently, after the timid and ambivalent moves of the years 1970-1975, the southern European bourgeoisie chose to align with German-American Europe, thus closing the door on this possibility.

Eighth conclusion: the analysis of the imperialist system and of its crisis now calls for commentary in the nature of provisional conclusions and new questions.

1. The systematic underestimation, when it is not pure and simple omission, of the imperialist dimension of capitalism is rendering the workers’ and socialist movement impotent. This impotence is verbally compensated for by the ouvrierist position. Some claim that only the advanced working class can be the harbingers of the socialist future, forgetting the most obvious lessons of history. In fact, the three great moments in the revolutionary history of our time—the Paris Commune, the Russian revolution of 1917, and the cultural revolution in China—were not the work of advanced working classes but of working classes still in formation.

This ouvrierist position, when it is serious as with Italian operaismo, becomes leftwing in the sense of an infantile disorder. An expression of the most advanced Western working class, Italian operaismo unfortunately does not attend to the questions addressed to the working-class minority by the other social layers which constitute the majority under developed capitalism. Nor does it address the international and imperialist dimension of the problem (71c-2). The impotence of the ouvrierist position is thus manifest in its inability to grasp the nature of conflicts on a world scale. Because it reduces the confrontation between capitalism and socialism to a direct class conflict between capital and labor in the center of the system, it cannot grasp the significance and nature of the national liberation movement in the periphery and the significance and nature of the East-West contradiction and of its effects on Western society.

To ignore or underplay imperialism is, finally, to substitute for unequal development the development of capitalism by stages. It is thus to fail to grasp the significance of the historical possibility of a strategy of uninterrupted revolution by stages. It is to become confused about “capitalist development” in the periphery, forgetting its peripheral character, and forgetting that this must lead to awaiting the development of capitalism on a world scale before raising the question of socialism.

Beneath this surface error lies the reduction of Marxism to the dimensions of a workers’ ideology, when it is the revolutionary ideology of our day, the science of the revolution of the exploited and of human liberation. Of course, its discovery would have been impossible without capitalism and the workers’ movement. But Marxism has enabled us to reengage with the entire revolutionary tradition of the exploited throughout time. By this very fact, Marxism is the instrument of the complex revolution of the imperialist epoch, the science of the worker-peasant alliance.

2. Historical experience of the class struggle shows that relations of production that have become an obstacle to the development of the productive forces are destroyed by the revolt of the oppressed classes. But these revolts can serve the interests of a third class, the bourgeoisie, born partially within the peasantry and partially alongside it.

The Soviet experience once again demonstrates this historical possibility. Did not the blows of the working class against the bourgeoisie serve the interests of a new bureaucratic technical class, the dominant class of the new statist mode of production? Is this eventuality, far from being the exclusive result of conditions specific to Russia, not equally likely in the West? Are not the new layers created by the differentiation within the proletariat—labor aristocracy and technocracy—also aspiring to a statist mode, and is not social democracy a partial illustration of this tendency? And what of Eurocommunism? A still poorly defined amalgam of partially contradictory tendencies, this current already clearly contains an old social-democratic tendency (management of capital with the support of the labor aristocracy), a new Swedish-style social-democratic tendency (replacement of the bourgeoisie with the labor aristocracy and the technocracy) leading to a statist mode, and possibly a “self-management” tendency stemming from old anarcho-syndicalist sources but nonetheless expressing the workers’ revolt.

We still need to know the law of development of this new mode and its specific contradictions. Without this knowledge, it would be too easy to extrapolate to this new mode, since it is still based on class exploitation, what we know about capitalism. In particular, we need to understand better how the nation functions in this new mode of production. I have proposed several hypotheses in these different areas but am aware that the question of the nature of Soviet imperialism is as yet poorly explained.

What is the degree of “historical necessity” of the possibility of a statist mode as a successor to capitalism? Clearly, the possible evolution toward a statist mode would involve the disintegration of the world market system which has characterized the last thirty years. It would involve the strengthening of more-or-less autarchic national tendencies. Should we then interpret this contradiction as involving a possible step backward toward models (though more structured) similar to those of the interwar period? And should we interpret this tendency in the same way for the countries of the center and those of the periphery of the current system?

Current conflicts raise all these questions. It would be imprudent to ignore them and recognize only the contrary tendency toward the continuation of the regulation by the world market because this tendency corresponds to the economic needs of the monopolies, that is, the most advanced productive forces of our day. What of the question of the potential for further development, impeded by the continuation of these relations of production, particularly on the periphery? What about the effects of the class struggle in the West?

3. Put in these terms, the complex question of the confrontation between capitalism and socialism has different possible outcomes. We must differentiate between the system’s basic contradiction (today the contradiction between capital and labor) and the primary contradiction by which the latter is expressed. This primary contradiction may be between nations or states at any given moment. This raises the whole question of the degree to which the movement of revolutionary forces will control social evolution and of their potential alienation—a reflection of the still objective nature of societal laws operating like natural laws.

Under these circumstances, only a concrete analysis of the situation will enable us to characterize the period and to answer the question: Is it the winds of revolution or of war that are now blowing? There is no doubt that the implicit or explicit answer to this question will have decisive consequences for socialist strategy.

Conclusion

Revolution or Decadence?

Thoughts on the Transition

from One Mode of Production to Another

The workers’ and socialist movement has sustained itself on a vision of a series of revolutions beginning in the advanced capitalist countries. From the criticisms which Marx and Engels made of the programs of German social democracy to the conclusions derived by Bolshevism from the experience of the Russian revolution, the workers’ and socialist movement has never conceived of the transition to socialism on the world scale in any other way.

However, over the past seventy-five years the transformation of the world has taken other paths. The perspective of revolution has disappeared from the horizons of the advanced West, while socialist revolutions have been limited to the periphery of the system. These have inaugurated developments of sufficient ambiguity for some people to see them only as a stage in the expansion of capitalism to the world scale. An analysis of the system in terms of unequal development attempts to give a different answer. Beginning with the contemporary imperialist system, this analysis obliges us also to consider the nature and meaning of unequal development in previous historical stages.

The comparative history of the transition from one mode of production to another calls for posing the question of the mode of transition in general and theoretical terms. Thus, similarities between the current situation and the era of the end of the Roman Empire have led those historians who are not proponents of historical materialism to draw parallels between the two situations. On

the other hand, a certain dogmatic interpretation of Marxism has used the terminology of historical materialism to obscure thought on this theme. Thus Soviet historians speak of the “decadence of Rome,” while putting forward the “socialist revolution” as the only form of substitution of new relations of production for capitalist relations. The following comparative analysis of the form and content of the ancient and the capitalist crises in relations of production addresses this issue. Do the differences between these two crises justify treating one in terms of “decadence” and the other in terms of “revolution”?

My central argument is that a definite parallel exists between these two crises. In both cases, the system is in crisis because the centralization of the surplus it organizes is excessive, that is, is in advance of the relations of production that underlie it. Thus the development of the productive forces in the periphery of the system necessitates the break-up of the system and the substitution of a decentralized system for collecting and utilizing the surplus.

1. The most commonly accepted thesis within historical materialism is that of the succession of three modes of production: the slave mode, the feudal mode, and the capitalist mode. In this framework, the decadence of Rome would be only the expression of the transition from slavery to serfdom. It would still remain to explain why we do not speak of a “feudal revolution” as we speak of bourgeois and socialist revolutions.

I consider this formulation to be West-centered in its overgeneralization of the specific characteristics of the history of the West and its rejection of the history of other peoples in all its particularities. Choosing to derive the laws of historical materialism from universal experience, I have proposed an alternative formulation of one precapitalist mode, the tributary mode, toward which all class societies tend. The history of the West—the construction of Roman antiquity, its disintegration, the establishment of feudal Europe, and, finally, the crystallization of absolutist states in the mercantilist period—thus expresses in a particular form the same basic tendency which elsewhere is expressed in the less discontinuous construction of complete, tributary states, of which China is the strongest expression. The slave mode is not universal, as are the tributary and capitalist modes; it is particular and appears strictly in connection with the extension of commodity relations. In addition, the feudal mode is the primitive, incomplete form of the tributary mode.

This hypothesis views the establishment and subsequent disintegration of Rome as a premature attempt at tributary construction. The level of development of the productive forces did not require tributary centralization on the scale of the Roman Empire. This first abortive attempt was thus followed by a forced transition through feudal fragmentation, on the basis of which centralization was once again restored within the framework of the absolutist monarchies of the West. Only then did the mode of production in the West approach the complete tributary model. It was, furthermore, only beginning with this stage that the level of development of the productive forces in the West attained that of the complete tributary mode of imperial China; this is doubtless no coincidence.

The backwardness of the West, expressed by the abortion of Rome and by feudal fragmentation, certainly gave it its historic advantage. Indeed, the combination of specific elements of the ancient tributary mode and of barbarian communal modes characterized feudalism and gave the West its flexibility. This explains the speed with which Europe passed through the complete tributary phase, quickly surpassing the level of development of the productive forces of the West, which it overtook, and passing on to capitalism. This flexibility and speed contrasted with the relatively rigid and slow evolution of the complete tributary modes of the Orient.

2. Doubtless the Roman-Western case is not the only example of an abortive tributary construction. We can identify at least three other cases of this type, each with its own specific conditions: the Byzantine-Arab-Ottoman case, the Indian case, the Mongol case. In each of these instances, attempts to install tributary systems of centralization were too far ahead of the requirements of the development of the productive forces to be firmly established. In each case the forms of centralization were probably specific combinations of state, parafeudal, and commodity means. In the Islamic state, for instance, commodity centralization played the decisive role. Successive Indian failures must be related to the contents of Hindu ideology, which I have contrasted with Confucianism. As to the centralization of the empire of Genghis Khan, it was, as we know, extremely short-lived.

3. The contemporary imperialist system is also a system of centralizaton of the surplus on the world scale. This centralization operated on the basis of the fundamental laws of the capitalist mode and in the conditions of its domination over the precapitalist modes of the subject periphery. I have formulated the law of the accumulation of capital on the world scale as a form of expression of the law of value operating on this scale. The imperialist system for the centralization of value is characterized by the acceleration of accumulation and by the development of the productive forces in the center of the system, while in the periphery these latter are held back and deformed. Development and underdevelopment are two sides of the same coin.

Thus we can see that further development of the productive forces in the periphery requires the destruction of the imperialist system of centralization of the surplus. A necessary phase of decentralization, the establishment of the national socialist transition, must precede the reunification at a higher level of development which a planetary classless society would constitute.

This central thesis has several consequences for the theory and strategy of the socialist transition.

1. In the periphery the socialist transition is not distinct from national liberation. It has become clear that the latter is impossible under local bourgeois leadership, and thus becomes a democratic stage in the process of the uninterrupted revolution by stages led by the peasant and worker masses. This fusion of the goals of national liberation and socialism engenders in its turn a series of new problems which we must evaluate. For the emphasis shifts from one aspect to the other, due to which the real movement of society alternates between progress and regression, ambivalences and alienation, particularly in nationalist form. Here again we can make a comparison with the attitude of the barbarians toward the Roman Empire: they were ambivalent toward it, notably in their formal, even slavish, imitation of the Roman model against which they were revolting.

At the same time, the parasitical character of the central society intensifies. In Rome, imperial tribute corrupted the plebians and paralyzed their revolt. In the societies of the imperialist center, a growing portion of the population benefits from unproductive employment and from privileged positions, both concentrated there by the effects of the unequal international division of labor. Thus it is harder to envision disengagement from the imperialist system and formation of an anti-imperialist alliance capable of overturning the hegemonic alliance and inaugurating the transition to socialism.

2.    The introduction of new relations of production seems easier in the periphery than in the center of the system. In the Roman Empire, feudal relations took hold rapidly in Gaul and Germany, but only slowly in Italy and the East. It is Rome which invented colonialism, which replaced slavery. But feudal authority developed elsewhere and feudal relations never fully developed in Italy itself.

Today the feeling of latent revolt against capitalist relations is very strong in the center, but it is powerless. People want to “change their lives” but cannot even change the government. Thus progress occurs in the area of social life more than in the organization of production and the state. The silent revolution in lifestyle, the break-up of the family, the collapse of bourgeois values demonstrate this contradictory aspect of the process. In the periphery, customs and ideas are often far less advanced, but socialist states have nonetheless been established there.

3.    Vulgar Marxist tradition has effected a mechanistic reduction of the dialectic of social change. The revolution—the objective content of which is the abolition of old relations of production and the establishment of new relations, the precondition for the further development of the productive forces—is made into a natural law: the application to the social realm of the law by which quantity becomes quality. The class struggle reveals this objective necessity: only the vanguard—the party—is above the fray, makes and dominates history, is de-alienated. The political moment defining the revolution is that in which the vanguard seizes the state. Leninism itself is not entirely devoid of the positivist re-ductionism of the Marxism of the Second International.

This theory which separates the vanguard from the class is not applicable to the revolutions of the past. The bourgeois revolution did not take this form: in it the bourgeoisie coopted the struggle of the peasants against the feudal lords. The ideology which enabled them to do this, far from being a means of manipulation, was itself alienating. In this sense, there was no “bourgeois revolution”—the term itself is a product of bourgeois ideology—but only a class struggle led by the bourgeoisie or, at most, at times a peasant revolution coopted by the bourgeoisie. Even less can we speak of the “feudal revolution,” where the transition was made unconsciously.

The socialist revolution will be of a different type, presupposing de-alienated consciousness, because it will aim for the first time at the abolition of all exploitation and not at the substitution of new for old forms of exploitation. But this will be possible only if the ideology animating it becomes something other than the consciousness of the requirements of the development of the productive forces. There is nothing to say, in fact, that the statist mode of production, as a new form of relations of exploitation, is not a possible response to the requirements of this development.

Only people make their own history. Neither animals nor inanimate objects control their own evolution; they are subject to it. The concept of praxis is proper to society, as expression of the synthesis of determinism and human intervention. The dialectic relation of infrastructure and superstructure is also proper to society and has no equivalent in nature. This relation is not unilateral. The superstructure is not the reflection of the needs of the infrastructure.

If it were, society would always be alienated and I cannot see how it could become liberated.

This is why I propose to distinguish between two qualitatively different types of transition from one mode to another. When the transition is made unconsciously or by an alienated consciousness, that is, when the ideology animating classes does not allow them to master the process of change, the latter appears to be operating like a natural change, the ideology being part of nature. For this type of transition we can apply the expression “model of decadence.” On the other hand, if and only if the ideology expresses the total and real dimension of the desired change, can we speak of revolution.

4. Is the socialist revolution in which our era is engaged of the decadent or the revolutionary type? Doubtless we cannot as yet answer this question definitively. In certain of its aspects, the transformation of the modern world incontestably has a revolutionary character as defined above. The Paris Commune, the revolutions in Russia and China (and particularly the cultural revolution) have been moments of intense de-alienated social consciousness.

But are we not engaged in another type of transition? The difficulties which make the disengagement of the imperialist countries nearly inconceivable today and the negative impact of this on the peripheral countries following the socialist road (leading to possible capitalist restoration, evolutions toward a statist mode, regression, nationalist alienation, etc.) call into question the old Bolshevik model.

Some people are resigned to this and believe that our time is not one of socialist transition but of worldwide expansion of capitalism which, starting from this “little corner of Europe,” is just beginning to extend to the south and the east. At the end of this transfer, the imperialist phase will appear to have been not the last, the highest stage of capitalism, but a transitional phase toward universal capitalism. And even if one continues to believe that the Leninist theory of imperialism is true and that national liberation is a part of the socialist and not of the bourgeois revolution, would not exceptions, that is, the appearance of new capitalist centers, be possible? This theory emphasizes the restorations or the evolutions toward a statist mode in the Eastern countries. It characterizes as objective processes of capitalist expansion what were only pseudosocialist revolutions. Here Marxism appears as an alienating ideology masking the true character of these developments.

Those who hold this opinion believe that we must wait until the level of development of the productive forces at the center is capable of spreading to the entire world before the question of the abolition of classes can really be put on the agenda. Europeans should thus allow the creation of a supranational Europe so that the state superstructure can be adjusted to the productive forces. It will doubtless be necessary to await the establishment of a planetary state corresponding to the level of the productive forces on the world scale, before the objective conditions for superceding it will obtain.

Others, myself among them, see things differently. The uninterrupted revolution by stages is still on the agenda for the periphery. Restorations is the course of the socialist transition are not irrevocable. And breaks in the imperialist front are not inconceivable in the weak links of the center.

References

1. Communal formations

10. Basic works

1.    Karl Marx, Grundrisse, ed. Martin Nicolaus. New York, Random House, 1973 (especially “Forms Which Precede Capitalist Production,” pp. 471-79).

2.    Friedrich Engels, The Origin of the Family, Private Property and the State. New York, International Publishers, 1972.

3.    Lewis H. Morgan, Ancient Society. New York, New World, 1963.

4.    Frangois Pouillon et al., L’anthropologie economique. Paris, Mas-pero, 1978 (good synthesis of French Marxist economic anthropology, especially chapters 3, 4, and 5, by Frangois Pouillon, Alain Marie, and Roger Meunier, respectively).

5.    Claude Meillassoux, Terrains et theories. Paris, Anthropos, 1977. (“L’essai d’interpretation du phenomene economique dans les societes traditionelles d’auto-subsistance,” 1960, reprinted in this collection, summarizes the experience taken by the author from his Anthropolgie economique desGourode Cote d’Ivoire. The Hague, Mouton, 1960.)

6.    Pierre-Philippe Rey, Les alliances de classes. Paris, Maspero, 1973. Colonialisme, neo-colonialisme et transition au capitalisme. Paris, Maspero, 1971. “Le transfert de surtravail de la paysannerie vers le capitalisme,” L’homme et la societe (1977).

7.    Emmanuel Terray, Marxism and “Primitive” Societies. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1972.

8.    Catherine Coquery-Vidrovitch, “Research on an African Mode of Production,” in African Social Studies, ed. P. Gutkind and P. Waterman. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1976.

9.    Karl Polanyi, Primitive, Archaic and Modern Economies, ed. George Dalton. Boston, Beacon, 1971.

10.    A. V. Chayanov, The Theory of Peasant Economy. Introduction by Daniel Thorner. Homewood, 111., Free Press, 1960.

11.    Ester Boserup, The Conditions of Agricultural Growth: The Economics of Agrarian Change Under Population Pressure. Chicago, Aldine, 1965.

12.    Lawrence Krader, ed., The Ethnological Notebooks of Karl Marx. Atlantic Highlands, N.J., Humanities, 1974.

13.    C. Bennetti, J. Cartelier, and C. Berthomieu, Economie classique, economie vulgaire. Paris, Maspero, 1975.

14.    Maurice Godelier, Horizons, trajets marxistes en anthropologie. Paris, Maspero, 1973.

i 1. The idea of the domestic mode of production

1.    Marshall Sahlins, Stone Age Economics. Chicago, Aldine, 1972.

2.    Claude Meillassoux, Femmes, greniers et capitaux. Paris, Maspero, 1975.

3.    Samir Amin, I. Eynard, B. Stuckey, “Feminisme et lutte de classes,” Minuit 7 (1974).

4.    Maurice Godelier and A. Deluz, “A propos de deux textes d’anthropologie economique,” L’homme 11 (1967).

12.    Slavery in the communal formations

1.    L’esclavage en Afrique precoloniale (17 studies introduced by Claude Meillassoux). Paris, Maspero, 1975.

2.    Samir Amin, Imperialisme et sous-developpement en Afrique. Paris, Anthropos, 1977.

13.    Other readings and sources

1.    The French Africanists, especially Gerard Althabe, Marc Auge, Jean Copans, Georges Dupre, and Henri Raulin.

2.    Non-Marxist anthropology: Georges Balandier, Paul Bohannan,

George Dalton, Raymond Firth, Melville Herskovits, Claude Levi-Strauss, Lucy Mair, Bronislaw Malinowski, A. Metraux, and A. R. Radcliffe-Brown.

3.    The new school of English Marxist anthropology which is being formed. The theoretical essay by Barry Hindess and Paul Hirst (Precapitalist Modes of Production. London, Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1975) is marked by an academic structuralist-Althusserian interpretation, as are most of the works published in the English journal Economy and Society.

4.    The historians and sociologists of precolonial and contemporary African societies: Abir and Levi (Ethiopia), Edward W. Bovill (transSaharan trade), Michael Crowder (West Africa), Catherine Coquery-Vidrovitch (Central Africa), T. O. Ranger (southern Africa), Roland Oliver (East Africa), John R. Gray and David Birmingham (longdistance trade), and the sociologists: Kenneth Onwuka Dike (Niger Delta), G. Nicolas (Hausa), and Jan Vansina (Congo).

See the bibliography of Unequal Development, especially pp. 387-90. See also L’agriculture africaine et le capitalisme, texts introduced by Samir Amin, especially the studies of Founou, delaTour, and Weber.

5.    V. Gordon Childe, Man Makes Himself. New York, New American Library, 1952.

6.    On the formal domination of capital, Claude Faure, Agriculture et mode de production capitaliste. Paris, Anthropos, 1978; Pierre-Philippe Rey, “Le transfert de surtravail de la paysannerie vers le capitalisme,” L’homme et la societe (1978); and Bernard Founou, “Surexploitation de la force de travail en Afrique, considerations theoriques et etudes de cas.” Phd. diss., Paris. 1977. See the bibliography in Samir Amin, “La structure de classes du systeme imperialiste,” L’homme et la societe (1977).

2. Classical antiquity and slavery

20. Ancient Greece

1.    Umberto Melotti, Marx sul mondo antico. Milan, II Saggiatore, 1970.

2.    Jean-Pierre Vernant, Les origines de la pensee grecque. Paris, PUF, 1962.

3.    P. Vidal-Naquet and M. Austin, Economies et societes en Grece ancienne. Paris, A. Colin, 1972.

4.    Victor Ehrenberg, Greek State. New York, Norton, 1964.

5.    Moses Finley, Early Greece: The Bronze and Archaic Ages. New York, Norton, 1970.

6.    Moses Finley, The Ancient Economy. Berkeley, University of California Press, 1973.

21.    Ancient Rome

1.    Jean Gage, Les classes sociales dans I’Empire romain. Paris, Payot, 1971.

2.    Paul Petit, Histoiregeneral de I’Empire romain. Paris, Seuil, 1974.

3.    Santo Mazzarino. La fin du monde antique. Paris, Gallimard, 1973.

22.    Other readings

1.    Recherches Internationales, Formes d’exploitation du travail dans 1’antiquite classique (Soviet and Eastern European contributions) 84 (1970).

2.    Eugene Genovese, The Political Economy of Slavery. New York, Pantheon, 1966.

3. Tributary societies: the asiatic mode of production

30. The debate on the asiatic mode of production

1.    Karl Wittfogel, Oriental Despotism. New Haven, Yale University Press, 1957 (introduced to the French edition by Pierre Vidal-Naquet removed from the succeeding edition at Wittfogel’s request).

2.    Ferenc Tokei, Sur le mode de production asiatique. Budapest, Akademiai Kiado, 1966.

3.    Centre d’Etudes et de Recherches Marxistes (CERM), Sur les societes precapitalistes. Paris, Ed. Sociales, 1975. Articles by Marx, Engels, Lenin; introduction by Maurice Godelier.

4.    CERM, Sur le mode de production asiatique. Paris, Ed. Sociales, 1969. Articles by Jean Chesneaux, Maurice Godelier, Jean Suret-Canale, Pierre Boiteau, Charles Parain, Helene Autoniadis-Bibi-car, G. A. Melekechvili, Ion Banu, Catherine Coquery-Vidrovitch.

5.    CERM, Sur le feodalisme. Paris, Ed. Sociales, 1974. Articles on North Africa by Rene Galissot, Andre Nouschi, Jean Poncet, Andre Prenant, Lucette Valensi, and Charles Parain.

6.    Recherches Internationales, Les Premieres societes de classes et le mode de production asiatique 57-58 (1967).

7.    Karl Marx, Pre-Capitalist Economic Formations, ed. Eric J. Hobs-bawm. New York, International Publishers, 1965. Anonymous, Succession des formes de production et de societe dans le theorie marxiste. Paris, EDI, 1974. This book, which appeared in Italian in 1957, originally inspired Tokei and his students.

8.    Gianni Sofri, U modo di produzioneasiatico. Milan, Einaudi, 1969.

9.    Lawrence Krader, The Asiatic Mode of Production. Atlantic Highlands, N.J., Humanities, 1975.

31. Non-European tributary societies: China and India

1.    Marx et la Chine. Paris, Plon, 1976.

2.    Etienne Balaczs, La bureaucratie celeste. Paris, Gallimard, 1969.

3.    Chi Chao Ting, Le zone economiche chiave nella storia della Cina. Milan, Einaudi, 1972.

4.    Boris Valdimirstsov, La feodalite nomade. Leningrad, Stray Mon-golov, 1934; Genghis-Khan. Paris, Maisonneuve, 1943. Chantal Lemercier-Quelquejay, La paix mongole, Questions d’histoire. Paris, Flammarion, 1975.

5.    Le Thanh Khoi, Le Viet Nam, Histoire et civilisation. Paris, Minuit, 1955.

6.    Jean Chesneaux, Popular Movements and Secret Societies in China: 1840-1950. Stanford, Cal., Stanford University Press, 1972.

7.    Jacques Genet, Le monde chinois. Paris, Armand Colin, 1972.

8.    Damodar Kosambi, Culture et civilisation de I’lnde ancienne. Paris, Maspero, 1968.

9.    Louis Dumont, Homo hierarchicus. Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 1974. Claude Meillassoux, “Y-a-t-il des castes aux Indes,” in Terrains et theories. Paris, Anthropos, 1977.

32.    Byzantine, Arab, and Ottoman domains

1.    Louis Brehier, Les institutions de I’Empire byzantin. Paris, Albin Michel, 1969.

2.    Kostas Vergopoulos, he capitalisme difforme et la nouvelle question agraire. Paris, Maspero, 1977.

3.    Maurice Lombard, L’Islam dans sa premiere grandeur, Vll-XIe siecle. Paris, Flammarion, 1971.

4.    Xavier de Planhol, Les fondements geographiques de I’histoire de I’lslam. Paris, Flammarion, 1968.

5.    Claude Cahen, L’Islam des origines aux debuts de I’Empire Ottoman. Paris, Bordas, 1970.

6.    Andre Miguel, L’Islam etsa civilisation. Paris, A. Colin, 1968.

7.    Maxime Rodinson, Mohammed. New York, Random House, 1974.

8.    Samir Amin, The Arab Nation. London, ZED Press, 1978.

9.    Yves Lacoste, Ibn Khaldoun. Paris, Maspero, 1965. Ibn Khaldoun, AlMuqaddima. Paris, Hachette, 1965.

10.    Charles Issawi, ed., The Economic History of the Middle East, 1800-1914. Chicago, Chicago University Press, 1966.

11.    M. A. Cook, ed., Studies in the Economic History of the Middle East. New York, Oxford University Press, 1970.

12.    CERM, Sur le feodalisme. Paris, Ed. Sociales, 1974.

13.    Abdellatif Benachenhou, La formation du sous-developpement en Algerie. Algiers, OPU, 1976.

14.    Abdallah Laroui, Histoiredu Maghreb. Paris, Maspero, 1970.

15.    Abdallah Laroui, L’ideologic arabe contemporaine. Paris, Maspero, 1965.

16.    Mostafa Lacheraf, Algerie, nation etsociete. Paris, Maspero, 1965.

17.    Lucette Valensi, Le Maghreb avant la prise d’Alger. Paris, Flammarion, 1969.

18.    Marx et l’Algerie. Paris, Plon, 1977.

19.    Hassan Ahmad Ibrahim, Mohamad Ali fl Sudan. Khartoum, 1975.

20.    Sobhi Wahida, Fi Ugul Al Masala al Migriya. Cairo, 1950.

21.    Gamal Hamdam, Shakhsiya Migr. Cairo, 1970.

33.    Other domains and miscellaneous

1. Vittorio Lanternari, Religions of the Oppressed. London, McGib-bon and Kee, 1963.

2. Also see the bibliographies in Unequal Development and The Arab Nation.

4. European feudalism

40. Basic works

1.    Perry Anderson, Passages from Antiquity to Feudalism. New York, Schocken, 1978.

2.    CERM, Sur le feodalisme. Paris, Ed. Sociales, 1974 (contributions by Parrain, Vilar, Goblot, Hincker, Cardoso, Soboul, Lemarchand).

3.    Georges Duby, Rural Economy and Country Life in the Medieval West. Columbia, University of South Carolina Press, 1968.

4.    Georges Duby, The Early Growth of the European Economy: Worriers and Peasants from the Seventh to the Twelfth Centuries. Ithaca, N.Y., Cornell University Press, 1974.

5.    Marc Bloch, French Rural History. Berkeley, University of California Press, 1966.

6.    Marc Bloch, Feudal Society. Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 1968.

7.    Recherches Internationales, Le deuxieme servage en Europe centrale et orientale 63-64 (1970).

8.    P. Dockes et B. Rosier, “Questions aux historiens,” Cahiers 11, (1977).

9.    Lynn White, Medieval Technology and Social Change. New York, Oxford University Press, 1966.

10.    Jacques Le Goff, Le millenarisme. Paris, Flammarion, 1971.

11.    Maurice Dommanget, La Jacquerie. Paris, Maspero, 1972.

12.    EricJ. Hobsbawm, Bandits. New York, Delacorte, 1969.

13.    Georges Duby, L'an Mil. Paris, Gallinard, 1974.

5. The Mercantilist transition and the bourgeois revolution 50. Basic works

1. Perry Anderson, Lineages of the Absolutist State. London, New Left Books, 1975.

2.    Maurice Dobb et al., TheTransition from Feudalism to Capitalism. New York, Schocken, 1978. Rodney Hilton, ed., The Transition from Feudalism to Capitalism. London, New Left Books, 1967.

3.    Maurice Dobb, Studies in the Development of Capitalism. New York, International, 1967.

4.    Immanuel Wallerstein, The Modern World-System. New York, Academic Press, 1974.

5.    Fernand Braudel, The Mediterranean and the Mediterranean World in the Age of Philip II. 2 vols. New York, Harper and Row, 1972, 1974.

6.    Pierre Vilar, OretmonnaiedansThistoire. Paris, Flammarion, 1974.

7.    Witold Kula, An Economic Theoryofthe Feudal System. New York, Schocken, 1976.

8.    Frederic Mauro, L’expansion europeenne, 1600-1870; Le XVIe siecle europeen. Paris, Clio, 1964.

9.    Christopher Hill, The World Turned Upside Down. New York, Viking, 1972.

10.    Andre Gunder Frank, World Accumulation, 1492-1789. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1978.

11.    Oliver Cox, Capitalism as a System. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1964.

12.    Eric Williams, Capitalism and Slavery. New York, Russell and Russell, 1961.

13.    PierreChaunu, L’AmeriqueetlesAmeriques. Paris, A. Colin, 1964.

14.    T. S. Ashton, The Industrial Revolution, 1760-1830. New York, Oxford University Press, 1948.

15.    Pierre Dockes, L’espace dans la pensee economique. Paris, Flammarion, 1977.

16.    Philippe Joutard, Les Camisards. Paris, Gallimard, 1976-.

17.    Yves Marie Berci, Croquants et nus pieds. Paris, Gallimard, 1975.

18.    Rushton Coulborn, ed., Feudalism in History. Hamden, Conn., Shoe String, 1965.

51. The French revolution

1.    Albert Soboul, A Short History of the French Revolution. Berkeley, University of California Press, 1977.

2.    Albert Mathiez, The French Revolution. New York, Russell and Russell, 1962.

3.    Daniel Guerin, Class Struggle in the First French Republic: Bourgeois and Bras Nus 1793-1795. Atlantic City, N.J., Humanities, 1977.

4.    Florence Gauthier, La voie paysanne dans la revolution frangaise. Paris, Maspero, 1975. Du feodalisme au capitalisme, la paysannerie frangaise a la veille de la revolution, I’exemple Picard. Paris, Maspero, 1977.

5.    Albert Soboul, Problemes paysans de la revolution, 1789-1848. Paris, Maspero, 1976.

6.    EricJ. Hobsbawm, The Age of Revolution, Europe 1789-1848. New York, Mentor, 1964.

7.    Marcel Lidove, Les vendeens de 93. Paris, Seuil, 1971.

6. The national question in Europe, 1840-1914.

60. Austro-Marxists and works about European history

1.    Miklos Molmar, Marx, Engels et la politique internationale. Paris, Gallimard, 1975.

2.    Yvon Bourdet, Otto Bauer et la revolution. Paris, EDI, 1968.

3.    Georges Haupt, M. Lowy, C. Weill, Les marxistes et la question nationale, 1848-1914. Paris, Maspero, 1974 (articles by Karl Kaut-sky, Rosa Luxemburg, Karl Renner, Otto Bauer, Josef Strasser, Anton Pannekoek).

4.    Josef Strasser, Anton Pannekoek, Nation et lutte de classes. Paris, Plon, 1977.

5.    Histoiredu marxisme contemporain. 4 vols. Milan, Feltrinelli, 1976 (article by Agnelli).

6.    Solomon F. Bloom, The World of Nations: A Study of the National Implications in the Work of Karl Marx. New York, Columbia University Press, 1941.

7.    Horace B. Davis, Nationalism and Socialism. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1967.

8.    Eric J. Hobsbawm, The Age of Capital, 1848-1875. New York, Scribner, 1975.

9.    Also see the bibliographies in Pierre Souyri, Le marxisme apres Marx. Paris, Flammarion, 1970 and Kostas Papaioannou, Marxet les marxistes. Paris, Flammarion, 1972.

266 Class and Nation

61. Italian unity

1.    Antonio Gramsci, Laquestionemeridionale. Turin, Einaudi, 1947.

2.    E. Sereni, Ilcapitalismo nellecampagne 1860-1900. Turin, Einaudi, 1968.

3.    Rosario Romeo, Risorgimento e capitalismo. Bari, Laterza, 1963.

4.    Sergio Romano, Histoire de I’ltalie du Risorgimento a nos jours. Paris, Points, 1977.

5.    Nicola Zitara, L’unita d’ltalia, Nascita di una colonia. Milan, Jaca, 1970; II proletariate esterno. Milan, Jaca, 1972.

6.    E. Capecelatro and A. Carlo, Contro la questione meridionale. Rome, Savelli, 1972.

7.    Benedetto Croce, Histoire de I’Europe au XIXe siecle. Paris, Galli-mard, 1973.

62. Other aspects of the national question in the developed centers

1.    Yannick Guin, Histoire de la Bretagne de 1789 a nos jours. Paris, Maspero, 1977.

2.    Marcel Lidove, Les vendeens de 93. Paris, Seuil, 1972.

3.    Maurice Goldring, L’lrlande, ideologie d’une revolution nationaliste. Paris, Ed. Sociales, 1975.

4.    Pierre Vilar, Catalogne et regionalisme en Espagne. Paris, Flam-marion, 1969.

5.    Gerald Brenan, The Spanish Labyrinth. New York, Cambridge University Press, 1960.

6.    Elise Marienstras, Les mythes fondateurs de la nation americaine. Paris, Maspero, 1975.

7.    F. Masnata and C. Masnata, Pouvoir, societe et politique aux Etats Unis. Paris, Payot, 1970.

8.    R. Ertel, G. Fabre, and E. Marienstras, En marge, les minorites aux Etats Unis. Paris, Maspero, 1971.

7. Imperialism and national liberation

70. Imperialism: general theory and basic concepts

a) Brief review of the writings of Marx and Engels on colonial societies

1. Umberto Melotti, Marx e il Terzo mondo. Milan, II Saggiatore, 1971.

2.    Shlomo Avineri, Karl Marx on Colonialism and Modernization. New York, Anchor, 1969.

3.    Also see the bibliography in Unequal Development.

b)    Basic works, sources, and popular presentations

1.    J. A. Hobson, The Evolution of Modern Capitalism. London, Walter Scott, 1894.

2.    Rudolph Hilferding, Finance Capital. London, Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1978.

3.    V. I. Lenin, Imperialism, the Highest Stage of Capitalism. New York, International, 1969.

4.    Rosa Luxemburg, The Accumulation of Capital. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1968.

5.    Nikolai Bukharin, Imperialism and the Accumulation of Capital. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1972.

6.    Jacques Valier, Sur I’imperialisme. Paris, Maspero, 1975.

7.    S. J. Rosen and J. R. Kurth, Testing Theories of Economic Imperialism. Toronto, 1974. Also the major works of the English Trotskyists Tom Kemp, Michael Barrat-Brown, R. Owen, R. Sutcliffe, Geoffrey Kay, Michael Kidron; for instance, R. Owen and R. Sutcliffe, eds., Studies in theTheory of Imperialism. London and New York, Longman, 1972 and Michael Barrat-Brown, The Economics of Imperialism. Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1974.

c)    The workers’ movement and the colonial question

1.    Josef Stalin, Marxism and the National and Colonial Question. London, Martin Lawrence, n.d. In Selected Works. Davis, Cal., Cardinal, 1971.

2.    Georges Haupt et al., La lie Internationale et I’Orient. Paris, Cujas, 1967.

3.    E. Colotti Pischel and C. Robertazzi, L’InternationaleCommuniste et les problemes coloniaux 1919-35. The Hague, Mouton, 1968.

4.    Manifestes, theses et resolutions des quatre premiers congres de I’ln-temationalecommuniste, 1919-23. Paris, Maspero, 1975. LePremier Congres des peuplesd’Orient, Bakou 1920. Paris, Maspero, 1971.

5.    Helene Carrere d’Encausse and Stuart Schram, Marxism and Asia. London, Allen Lane, 1969..

6.    Gregoire Madjarian, La question coloniale et la politique du P.C.F. 1944-47. Paris, Maspero, 1977.

d)    For a summary of my position see: Samir Amin, “A propos de la critique,” L’homme et la societe 39-40 (1976). “La strategic de la revolution socialiste dans le Tiers Monde,” in Connaissancedu Tiers Monde. Paris, Plon, 1977.

e)    other viewpoints

1.    Bill Warren, “Imperialism and Capitalist Industrialization,” New Left Review 81 (September-October 1973).

2.    Mario Tronti, Ouvriers et Capital. Paris, Bourgeois, 1977. Antonio Negri, Laclasseouvrierecontrel’etat. Paris, Galilee, 1978.

71. The world system and imperialism today

a)    General works

1.    Harry Magdoff, The Age of Imperialism. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1969.

2.    Paul Sweezy, Modern Capitalism and Other Essays. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1972.

3.    C. A. Michalet, Le capitalisme mondial. Paris, PUF, 1976.

4.    Paul Baran, The Political Economy of Growth. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1957.

5.    Paul Baran and Paul Sweezy, Monopoly Capital. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1966.

6.    Michael Kidron, Western Capitalism Since the War. London, Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1968.

7.    Ernest Mandel, Le troisieme age du capital. 3 vols. Paris, Plon, 1978.

8.    Fritz Sternberg, Capitalism and Socialism on Trial. Westport, Conn., Greenwood, 1968.

9.    David Horowitz, From Yalta to Vietnam. New York, Penguin, 1970.

10.    Amin, Faire, Hussein, and Massiah, La crise de I’imperialisme. Paris, Minuit, 1976.

11.    Alexander Gerschenkron, Economic Backwardness in Historical Perspective. Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press, 1962.

b)    The debate on the multinationals; the theory of superimperialism (the modern economist viewpoint)

1. Michael Hudson, Superimperialism: The Economic Strategy of the

American Empire. New York, Center for Study of Development and Social Change, 1968.

2.    Stephen Hymer, “The Multinational Corporation and the Law of Uneven Development,” In Economics and the World Order, ed. J. N. Bagwathi. Homewood, 111., Free Press, 1974.

3.    R. Vernon, Les entreprises multinationales. Paris, Calmann-Levy, 1974.

4.    Christian Palloix, L’economic capitaliste mondiale. Paris, Maspero,

1972.

5.    Giovanni Arrighi, La geometria de I’imperialismo. Milan, Feltrinelli, 1978; “The Class Struggle in 20th-Century Western Europe,” mimeographed paper. Uppsala, 1978.

72. The unequal international division of labor, unequal exchange, and dependency theories of underdevelopment

a)    The debate on unequal exchange

1.    Arghiri Emmanuel, Unequal Exchange. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1972.

2.    Arghiri Emmanuel, E. Somaini, and M. Salvati, Un debat sur Vechange inegal. Paris, Maspero, 1975.

3.    Oscar Braun, Comercio intemacional e imperialismo. Buenos Aires, SigloXXI, 1973.

4.    Christian Palloix, Problemes de la croissance en economic ouverte. Paris, Maspero, 1969.

5.    Samir Amin, L’echange inegale et la loi de la valuer. Paris, Anthropos,

1973.

b)    The debate on dependency

1.    Andre Gunder Frank, Capitalism and Underdevelopment in Latin America. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1967. Latin America: Underdevelopment or Revolution? New York, Monthly Review Press, 1969. Lumpenbourgeosie, Lumpendevelopment. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1972.

2.    Fernando H. Cardoso and B. Faletto, Dependency and Development in Latin America. Berkeley, Cal., University of California Press, 1978. Ruy Mauro Marini, Subdesarrollo y revolucion. Mexico, Siglo Veintiuno Editores, 1969.

3. Samir Amin, Unequal Development. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1976.

c) Capitalist accumulation and underdevelopment

1.    Carlo Benetti, L’accumulation dans les pays capitalistes sous-developpes. Paris, Anthropos, 1974.

2.    Paul Sweezy, The Theory of Capitalist Development. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1942.

3.    Tamas Szentes, The Political Economy of Underdevelopment. Budapest, 1971.

4.    Geoffrey Kay, Development and Underdevelopment, a Marxist Analysis. London, Macmillan, 1975. See my critique in The Insurgent Sociologist, University of Oregon, Spring 1977.

5.    Hosea Jaffe, Processo capitalista e teoria dell’ accumulazione. Milan, Jaca, 1973.

6.    Andre Gunder Frank, “Desequilibres des echanges multinationaux de marchandises et developpement economique inegal; limitation de l’etendue du marche interne par la division du travail et par les relations de production,” in S. Amin and A. G. Frank, L’accumula-tion dependante. Paris, Anthropos, 1978.

73. Capitalism and peasant exploitation

a) Theses relative to formal domination in general and the exploitation of the peasants by capital.

1.    Karl Marx, Un chapitre inedit du Capital. Paris, Plon, 1971. This is now in English as the Appendix in the new Pelican Marx Library edition of Capital.

2.    Claude Faure, Agriculture et mode de production capitaliste. Paris, Anthropos, 1978.

3.    Gervais, Servolin, and Weil, Une France sans pay sans. Paris, Seuil, 1965.

4.    Bernard Lambert, Les paysans dans la lutte des classes. Paris, Seuil, 1970.

5.    Cahiers d’Economie Politique 4, Petite agriculture et capitalisme (1976).

b) Theses relating to formal domination on the periphery of the imperialist system and in general.

1.    P.-P. Rey, “Le transfert de surtravail de la paysannerie vers le capitalisme,” L’homme et la societe (1978).

2.    Bernard Founou, “Surexploitation de la force de travail en Afrique, considerations theoriques et etudes de cas.” Phd. diss., Paris, 1977.

3.    Bruno Lautier, “La soumission formelle du travail au capital.” Phd. diss., Vincennes, 1973.

74. Debates on the crisis of contemporary capitalism and the new international economic order

a)    For my analysis of the crisis and similar views see

1.    Samir Amin, “Une crise structurelle,” in Amin, Faire, Hussein, and Massiah, La crise de I’imperialisme. Paris, Minuit, 1975. Samir Amin, “Developpement autocentre, automnomie collective et nou-vel ordre economique international,” in L'Occident et desarroi. Paris, Dunod, 1978.

2.    A. Faire arid J. P. Sebord, Le nouveau desequilibre mondial. Paris, Grasset, 1973.

3.    A. Farhi, Y. Fitt, and J. P. Vigier, La crise de I’imperialisme et la troisieme guerre mondiale. Paris, Maspero, 1976.

4.    Cahiers Yenan 2, Face a la crise economique (1977).

5.    Rikard Stajner, La crise. Belgrade, QAS, 1976.

b)    Other viewpoints

1.    Wladimir Andreff, Profits et structures du capitalisme mondial. Paris, Calmann-Levy, 1976.

2.    La crise mondiale du capitalisme. Vincennes, Colloque de l’ACSES, 1975.

3.    J. M. Chevalier, Le nouvel enjeu petrolier. Paris, Calmann-Levy,

1973.

c)    The new international economic order

1. Samir Amin, Les perspectives de la localisation internationale des activites industrielles. Paris, GRESI, 1976; After Nairobi, UNCTAD, and the New Economic Order. Colombo, Marga Q.J., 1976; Amin, Frank, Jaffe, Quale 1984? Milan, Jaca, 1975.

2.    The Club of Rome and its critics

a.    D. H. Meadows et al., Limits to Growth. New York, Universe,

1974.

b.    Jan Tinbergen (coordinator), RIO, Reshaping the International Order. New York, Dutton, 1976.

c.    Wassily Leontief, 1999, L’expertise deW. Leontief. Paris, Dunod, 1977.

d.    Amilcar O. Herrera et ah, Un monde pour tous. Paris, PUF, 1977.

e.    J. Klatzmann, Nourrir dix milliards d'hommes. Paris, PUF, 1977.

3.    See also Michel Chatelus, Strategies pour le Moyen-Orient. Paris, Calmann-Levy, 1974 and J. Annerstedt and R. Gustavsson, Towards a New International Economic Division of Labor. Stockholm, 1975.

75.    Chinese theories about imperialism today

1.    L’imperialisme aujourd’hui. Paris, E 100, 1976.

2.    See “A Proposal Concerning the General Line of the International Communist Movement,” and “Apologists of Neocolonialism,” in The Polemic on the General Line of the International Communist Movement. Peking, Foreign Languages Press, 1965; reprint ed. London, Red Star Press, 1976. “Chairman Mao’s Theory of the Three Worlds,” Renmin Ribao, January 11, 1977.

3.    “La theorie et la pratique de la revolution,” Zeri i Populit (Tirana) July 7, 1977.

76.    The historical formation of underdevelopment a) The Asian domain

1.    Frederick Clairmonte, Economic Liberalism and Underdevelopment. New York, Asia Publishing House, 1960.

2.    Charles Bettelheim, LTnde-independante. Paris, Maspero, 1971.

3.    Daniel Thorner, Peasant Unrest in South East Asia. New York, Asia Publishing House, 1968.

4.    Erich H. Jacoby, Man and Land. New York, Knopf, 1971.

5.    Daniel Thorner and Alice Thorner, Land and Labour in India. New York, Asia Publishing House, 1962.

6.    Kathleen Gough and Hari P. Sharma, eds., Imperialism and Revolution in South Asia. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1973.

7.    Rene Dumont, Paysanneries aux abois. Paris, Seuil, 1973.

b)    The Arab and Ottoman domain

1.    Charles Issawi, “Egypt since 1800: A Study in Lopsided Development,” Journal of Economic History 21, no. 1 (March 1961).

2.    Dorren Warriner, Land Reform and Development in the Middle East. Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1962.

3.    Mahmoud Hussein, Class Conflict in Egypt, 1945-1970. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1974.

4.    Hassan Riad, L’Egypte nasserienne. Paris, Minuit, 1964.

5.    Samir Amin, The Mahgeb in the Modern World. Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1970.

6.    Samir Amin, The Arab Nation. London, ZED Press, 1978.

7.    Kostas Vergopoulos, Le capitalisme difforme et la nouvelle question agraire. Paris, Maspero, 1977.

c)    The African domain

1.    Peter Gutkind and Immanuel Wallerstein, eds., The Political Economy of Contemporary Africa. Beverly Hills, Cal., Sage, 1975.

2.    Giovanni Arrighi and John Saul, Essays on the Political Economy of Africa. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1973.

3.    Diverse authors, Studies on South African Imperialism. Uppsala, Southern Africa Research Group, Peace and Conflict Research, 1977.

4.    Rene Lefort, L’Afrique du Sud, Histoire d’une crise. Paris, Maspero, 1977.

5.    Boubacar Barry, Le royaume du Waalo. Paris, Maspero, 1972.

6.    Samir Amin, Neocolonialism in West Africa. Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1973.

7.    Samir Amin and Catherine Coquery-Vidrovitch, Histoire econo-miquedu Congo, 1880-1968. Paris, Anthropos, 1969.

8.    B. Ameillon, La Guinee, bilan d’une independence. Paris, Maspero, 1964.

9.    Catherine Coquery-Vidrovitch, Le Congo au temps des conpagnies concessionnaires, 1890-1930. The Hague, Mouton, 1973.

10. R. Merlier, Le Congo de la colonisation beige a I’independance. Paris, Maspero, 1965.

11.    Samir Amin, Imperialisme et sous-developpement en Afrique. Paris, Anthropos, 1975.

12.    Harold Wolpe, “Capitalism and cheap labour power in South Africa,” Economy and Society 1, no. 4 (1972): 425-56.

13.    Rene Dumont, False Start in Africa. New York, Praeger, 1969. Paysanneries aux abois (Le Senegal). Paris, Seuil, 1972.

14.    Woungly Massaga, La revolution au Congo. Paris, Maspero, 1974.

15.    Yves Benot, Ideologie des independances africaines. Paris, Maspero,

1975.

d)    The American domain

1.    Fernando H. Cardoso, Politique et developpement dans les societes dependantes. Paris, Anthropos, 1971.

2.    Fernando H. Cardoso, Sociologie du developpement en Amerique latine. Paris, Anthropos, 1971.

3.    Celso Furtado, Economic Development of Latin America. New York and London, Cambridge University Press, 1977.

4.    Jesus Silva Herzog, La revolution mexicaine. Paris, Maspero, 1968.

5.    Various authors, Aspectos teorico-metodologicos de industrialisacion y desarrolio de America Latina. Caracas, Nueva Ciencia, 1977.

e)    Miscellaneous and general works

1.    Michel Gutelman, Structures et reformes agraires. Paris, Maspero, 1975.

2.    Robert I. Rhodes, ed., Imperialism and Underdevelopment. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1970.

3.    Rene Dumont, Lands Alive. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1965. Hungry Future. New York, Praeger, 1969. Developpement et socialismes. Paris, Seuil, 1969. L’utopie ou la mort. Paris, Seuil,

1973.

77. National liberation and national questions in the contemporary

third world

a) The East Asian domain

1.    M. Bastid, M. C. Bergere, and J. Chesneaux, La Chine. 4 vols. Paris, Hatier, 1976.

2.    Le Thanh Khoi, Le Viet Nam, Histoire et civilisation. Paris, Minuit, 1955.

3.    Le Chau, Le Viet Nam socialiste, une economie de transition. Paris, Maspero, 1966.

4.    Nguyen Kien, Le Sud Viet Nam depuis Dien Bien Phu. Paris, Maspero, 1963.

5.    Pierre Rousset, Le parti communiste vietnamien. Paris, Maspero, 1975.

6.    Samir Amin, "The Lesson of Cambodia," in Imperialism and Unequal Development. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1977.

b)    The South and Southeast Asia domain

1.    Kathleen Gough and Hari P. Sharma, eds., Imperialism and Revolution in South Asia. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1973.

2.    Robin Blackburn, Explosion in a Subcontinent. Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1975.

3.    Biplad Dasgupta, The Naxalite Movement. New York, International Publications Service, 1975.

4.    Visakha Kumari Jayawardena, The Rise of the Labor Movement in Ceylon. Durham, N.C., Duke University Press, 1972.

5.    Tariq Ali, Pakistan, Military Dictatorship or Popular Power? London, Jonathan Cape, 1970. B. H. Levy, BanglaDesh, Nationalisme dans la revolution. Paris, Maspero, 1973.

6.    Frequent articles by Tariq Ali, Amiya Bagdi, Paresh Chattopadhyay, Hamza Alavi, Feroz Ahmed, Ram Krishna Mukherjee, and others in The Socialist Register and New Left Review (London).

c)    The Arab domain

1.    Hassan Riad, L’Egypte nasserienne. Paris, Minuit, 1964.

2.    Mahmoud Hussein, Class Conflict in Egypt: 1945-1970. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1974.

3.    Samir Amin, The Maghreb in the Modern World. Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1970.

4.    Fred Halliday, Arabia Without Sultans. Harmondsworth, Penguin,

1974.

5.    Samir Amin, The Arab Nation. London, ZED Press, 1978.

6.    Mohamed Harbi, Aux origines du F.L.N.. Paris, Bourgeois, 1975.

d)    The African domain

1. Jean Suret-Canale, L'Afrique noire. 3 vols. Paris, Ed. Sociales, 1961.

2.    Michael Crowder, West Africa Under Colonial Rule. Evanston, 111., Northwestern University Press, 1968.

3.    Benoit Verhaegen, Rebellions au Congo. 2 vols. Brussels, CRISP, 1969.

4.    Richard Gibson, African Liberation Movement: Contemporary Struggles Against White Minority Rule. New York and London, Oxford University Press, 1972.

5.    CEDETIM, Angola: la lutte continue. Paris, Maspero, 1977.

6.    Rene Lefort, L’Afrique du Sud, Histoire d’une crise. Paris, Maspero, 1977.

7.    Diverse authors, Studies on South African Imperialism. 2 vols. Uppsala, Southern Africa Research Group, Peace and Conflict Research, 1977.

8.    Samir Amin, The Future of Southern Africa. Dar es Salam, Tanzanian Publishing House, forthcoming.

9.    Anonymous, Nationalities and Class Struggle in Ethiopia. New York, Challenge, 1971.

10.    Yash Tandon, “Whose Capital and Whose State?” African Review 7, no. 3(1978).

11.    Issa Shivji, Class Struggles in Tanzania. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1976.

e) Other works

1.    Gerard Chaliand, Revolution in the Third World. New York, Viking, 1977.

2.    Eric Wolf, Peasant Wars of the Twentieth Century. New York, Harper and Row, 1969.

78. The north-south debate

1.    Samir Amin, “CNUCED III,” Un Bilan, Bulletin of Peace Proposals, Oslo, 1972.

2.    Samir Amin, “UNCTAD IV and the New International Economic Order,” Africa Development, 1974.

3.    Samir Amin, “After Nairobi,” Africa Development, 1976.

4.    Samir Amin “The New World Economic Order: Reactions of the Developed World,” in International Financing of Economic Development. Belgrade, 1978.

5.    Samir Amin, “Developpement autocentre, autonomie collective et

Ordre economique international nouveau,” in L’Occident en de-sarroi. Paris, Dunod, 1978.

6. Cheryl Payer, The Debt Trap: The I.M.F. and the Third World. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1974.

79. Europe-African relations

1.    Samir Amin, Perspectives de la localisation internationale des activity industrielles, un point devueafro-arabe. Paris, GRESI, 1976; “L’association eurafricaine, quelques aspects du probleme,” Euraf-rica, 1975; “A propos de 1’Eurafrique” in Imperialisme et sous-developpement en Afrique. Paris, Anthropos, 1976.

2.    Kwame Amoa, “Les relations economiques internationales et le probleme du sous-developpement: la C.E.E. et l’Afrique,” in Amoa and Braun, Echanges intemationaux et sous-developpement. Paris, Anthropos, 1974

8. Capitalism and socialism: the socialist transition

80. USSR and China: state capitalism or socialism?

a)    The Soviet debates

1.    Nikolai Bukharin, Economics of the Transformation Period. Atlantic City, N.J., Humanities, 1971.

2.    Nickolai Bukharin, Le socialisme dans un seul pays. Paris, Plon,

1974.

3.    Bukharin, Kamenev, Preobrajensky, and Trotsky, La question pay-sanneen U.R.S.S. Paris, Maspero, 1973. Bukharin, Preobrajensky, and Trotsky, Le debat sovietique sur la loi de la valeur. Paris, Maspero, 1972.

4.    Eugeny Preobrajensky, New Economics. New York and London, Oxford University Press, 1965.

5.    A. Erlich, The Soviet Industrialization Debate, 1924-1928. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1960.

b)    Planning in the Eastern countries

1. CES, Les problemes de la plantation socialiste. Paris, EDI, 1968.

2.    Erik Egnell and Michel Peissik, U.R.S.S., L'entreprise face a I’Etat. Paris, Seuil, 1974.

3.    Marie Lavigne, Le Comecon. Paris, Cujas, 1973. The Socialist Economics of the Soviet Union and Europe. White Plains, N.Y., M.E. Sharpe, 1974.

4.    Wlodzimierz Brus, The Economics and Politics of Socialism. New York and London, Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1973.

5.    B. Mine, L’economie politique dusocialisme. Paris, Maspero, 1974.

6.    Branko Horvat, An Essay on Yugoslav Society. White Plains, N. Y., M.E. Sharpe, 1969.

7.    H. Denis and M. Lavigne, Le probleme des prix en Union So-vietique. Paris, Cujas, 1965.

8.    Andrea Boltho, Foreign Trade Criteria in Socialist Economies. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1971.

9.    Tibor Kiss, The International Division of Labor in Open Economies, with Special Regard to the CMEA. New York, International Publications Service, 1971.

10. Rene Dumont, Is Cuba Socialist? New York, Viking, 1974. Sovkhozes, Kholkhozes et la problematique communiste. Paris, Seuil, 1964.

c) The Maoist critique

1.    Charles Bettelheim, Economic Calculation and Forms of Property. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1976.

2.    Charles Bettelheim, Class Struggles in the USSR. 2 vols. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1976, 1978.

3.    Charles Bettelheim, Cultural Revolution and Industrial Organization in China. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1975.

4.    Charles Bettelheim and Paul Sweezy, On the Transition to Socialism. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1971.

5.    Pierre Amon, “Revolution culturelle et dialectique du centre et de la Peripherie,” in Sociologieet Revolution. Paris, Plon, 1974.

6.    Robert Linhart, Lenine, lespaysans, Taylor. Paris, Seuil, 1975.

7.    Carmen Claudin Urondo; Lenine et la revolution culturelle. The Hague, Mouton, 1974.

8.    Marcel Liebman, Leninism Under Lenin. London, Jonathan Cape,

1975.

9.    Sigrid Grosskopf, L’alliance ouvriereet paysanneen U.R.S.S. 192128. Paris, Maspero, 1976.

10.    Alain Bouc, Mao ou la revolution approfondie. Paris, Seuil, 1975. La Chine a la mort de Mao. Paris, Seuil, 1976. La rectification. Paris, Federop, 1977.

11.    Catherine Quiminal, La politique exterieure de la Chine. Paris, Maspero, 1975.

12.    E. Poulain, Le mode d’industrialisation socialiste en Chine. Paris, Maspero, 1977.

13.    Charles Bettelheim, China Since Mao. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1978.

d)    The viewpoint of Russian ideology and the internal critique in Eastern Europe

1.    Roy Medvedev, Let History Judge: The Origins and Consequences of Stalinism. New York, Knopf, 1971.

2.    Roy Medvedev, Khrushchev, The Years in Power. New York, Columbia University Press, 1976.

3.    A. Amalrik, L’Union Sovietique survivra-t-elle en 1984? Paris, LGF, 1977.

4.    Alexandre Koyre, La philosophie et le probleme national en Russie au debut duXIXe siecle. Paris, Gallimard, 1976.

5.    Nicolas Berdiaev, Les sources et le sens du communisme russe. Paris, Gallimard, 1963.

6.    Alain Besangon, Les origines intellectuelles du Leninisme. Paris, Calmann-Levy, 1977.

7.    K. Modzelevski and J. Kuron, Lettre ouverte au Parti ouvrier polonais. Paris, Maspero, 1969.

8.    Samizdat, Line opposition socialiste en Union Sovietique aujourd’hui. Paris, Maspero, 1975.

9.    Marc Rakovski, Le marxisme face aux pays de I’Est. Rome, Savelli, 1977.

e)    Other views on “bureaucracy”

1.    B. Rizzi, La bureaucratisation du monde. Paris, 1939.

2.    James Burnham, The Managerial Revolution. Westport, Conn., Greenwood, 1972.

1. Corne/ius Castoriadis, L’experience du mouvement ouvrier, 2 vols. Paris, Plon, 1974. La societe bureaucratique, 2 vols. Paris, Plon,

1975. L'institution imaginaire de la societe. Paris, Seuil, 1975.

4. Also see the contributions of the Frankfurt school (Horkheimer,

Habermas, Adorno, Marcuse, etc.), and the bibliography in Martin Jay, The Dialectical Imagination: A History of the Frankfurt School and the Institute of Social Research, 1923-1950. Boston, Little Brown, 1973.

81. The contemporary European workers’ movement

a)    Social structure, ideology, contemporary Europe

1.    Nicos Poulantzas, Classes in Contemporary Capitalism. New York, Schocken, 1978.

2.    Serge Christophe Kolm, La transition socialiste. Paris, Cerf, 1977.

3.    IIManifesto. Paris, Seuil, 1971.

4.    Mario Tronti, Ouvriers et capital. Paris, Bourgeois, 1977.

5.    YvesBenot, L’autreItalie 1968-76. Paris, Maspero, 1977.

6.    PUP, Usciredalla crisio dalcapitalismo in crisi. Rome, PUP, 1975.

7.    Cahiers d’etudes socialistes, L’integration europeenne et le mouve-ment ouvrier. Paris, EDI, 1964.

8.    Fernando Claudin, Eurocommunism and Socialism. New York, Schocken, 1978.

9.    Henri Weber, Le PCI aux sources de I’eurocommunisme. Paris, Plon, 1976.

10.    CEDETIM, L’experience portugaise. Paris, Maspero, 1977.

11.    James Weinstein, The Decline of Socialism in America, 1912-1925. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1967.

12.    Daniel Lindenberg, Le marxisme introuvable. Paris, Calmann-Levy, 1975.

13.    Fernando Claudin, The Communist Movement: From Comintern to Cominform. New York, Monthly Review Press, 1976.

b)    The self-management tendency and its critics; leftwing communism

1.    Claude Berger, Marx, l’association, I’anti-Lenine. Paris, Payot, 1974.

2.    Diverse authors, Les marxistes contre l’autogestion. Paris, Seuil, 1973.

3.    Yvon Bourdet, La delivrancedePromethee. Paris, Anthropos, 1970.

4.    Yvon Bourdet, Pour 1’autogestion. Paris, Anthropos, 1973.

5.    Daniel Guerin, Pour un marxisme libertaire. Paris, Laffont, 1969.

6.    Michel Charzat, Georges Sorel et la revolution au XXe siecle. Paris, Hachette, 1977.

82. General questions about modes of production, base, and ideology

1.    Robert Fossaert, Lasociete. Paris, Seuil, 1977.

2.    Perry Anderson, Considerations on Western Marxism. New York, Schocken, 1976.

3.    Pierre Souyri, Le marxisme apres Marx. Paris, Flammarion, 1970.

4.    Kostas Papaioannou, Marxet les marxistes. Paris, Flammarion, 1970.

5.    Institut Feltrinelli, Le marxisme contemporain. Paris, Plon, 1976.

6.    Antoine Pelletier and J. P. Goblot, Materialisme historique et his-toire des civilisations. Paris, Ed. Sociales, 1969.

7.    G. Dhoquois, Pour I’histoire. Paris, Anthropos, 1971.

8.    F. Jakubowsky, Les superstructures ideologiques dans la conception materialiste de I’histoire. Paris, EDI, 1972.

9.    M. Reubel, Marx critique du marxisme. Paris, Payot, 1974.

10.    A. Lipietz, L’espace du capital. Paris, Maspero, 1977.

11.    Abraham Leon, La conception materialiste de la question juive. Paris, EDI, 1968.

12.    Lewis Mumford, The City In History: Its Origins, Its Transformations, and its Prospects. New York, Harcourt Brace Jovanovitch, 1961.

13.    Lewis Mumford, Technics and Civilization. New York, Harcourt Brace Jovanovitch, 1963.

14.    Martin Jay, The Dialectical Imagination: A History of the Frankfurt School and the Institute of Social Research, 1923-1950. Boston, Little Brown, 1973.

15.    Beaud, Bellon, Francois, Lirelecapitalisme. Paris, Anthropos, 1976.

9. Analysis of the author’s principal works

90. This book refers, at times explicitly and often implicitly, to ideas

developed in the following works:

1.    Unequal Development (UD). New York, Monthly Review Press, 1976.

2.    Imperialism and Unequal Development (IUD). New York, Monthly Review Press, 1977.

3.    L’echange inegal et la loi de la valeur (EU). Paris, Anthropos, 1973. Included in Imperialism and Unequal Development as part IV.

4.    The Law of Value and Historical Materialism (LV). New York, Monthly Review Press, 1978.

5.    The Arab Nation (AN). ZED Press, 1978.

6.    La Crise de I’imperialisme (Cl) in collaboration with Faire, Hussein and Massiah. Paris, Minuit, 1976.

7.    Imperialisme et sous-developpement en Afrique (ISA). Paris, Anthro-pos, 1977.

So as not to encumber the text, I have refrained from too frequent references to these works; a synoptic analysis of their ideas follows:

1.    Modes of production, social formation, base and superstructure,

ethnic groups and nations: UD, chapter 1.

2.    Precapitalist societies and the transition to capitalism: in general,

UD, chapter 1; the Arab case: AN.

3.    The basic laws of capitalism:

a)    Accumulation: UD, chapter 2, EU (dynamic equilibrium of departments I and II, wages and productivity, rate of profit, etc.)

b)    The functions of money in accumulation: UD, chapter 2; LV, chapter 3.

c)    Cycle and conjuncture: UD, chapter 2.

d)    External equilibrium: UD, chapter 2, LV, chapter 3.

4.    The law of value:

a)    Nature, articulation of the class struggle, problems of the “transformation” of values into prices: LV, chapters 1, 2, appendix.

b)    Money, state, and rate of interest: LV, chapter 3; EU; UD, chapter 2.

c)    Ground rent and the interrelation of agriculture and industry: IUD, chapter 2; LV, chapter 4.

d)    Mining rent in the world system: LV, chapter 6.

e)    The imperialist system, unequal exchange, international trade, and the unequal international division of labor: UD, chapter 3; IUD, chapter 6; EU; LV, chapter 5; ISA, introduction.

5.    The formation of the world system and imperialism:

a)    The historical establishment of peripheral capitalist formations: UD, chapter 5; ISA, parts I and II.

b)    General characteristics of peripheral formations: UD, chapter 4; IUD, chapters 7, 9, 10.

c)    Imperialism, the class struggle on the world scale; the pro- and anti-imperialist tendencies within Marxism: LV, conclusion.

d)    Questions of national liberation: IA, part III, IUD, chapter 8.

6.    The current crisis of imperialism: Cl; IUD, chapter 5.

7.    Capitalism and socialism, USSR and China; economism and

Marxism: UD, chapter 5; IUD, chapters 1, 3, 4.

Index

Accumulation, 53, 185

center-periphery relations and, 118, 132-34, 170-73, 204 homogenization and, 31-35 imperialism and, 225-30, 233, 252 money and, 24 peasant struggles and, 94, 97 state and, 21, 28, 127-28 Africa (Black), 91, 101, 167, 224 national liberation in, 181 state in, 177-78

Agriculture, 5, 41-42, 49, 81, 133 in Italy, 115, 119-21 in periphery, 136, 137, 139, 142 144-48, 160-61 Albania, 146, 220 Albigensian heresy, 53 Alexander the Great, 77 Amalrik, A., 224 America

capitalist development in, 84, 96 mercantilist period and, 90, 91, 101, 127 migration to, 93

Anarchism (anarcho-syndicalism), 15, 186, 209, 246

Anderson, Perry, 8, 50, 66, 82, 87, 89 Anglicanism, 80, 89 Angola, 222

Anthropology, 5, 9, 36-45, 67, 168 Arab world, 14, 224,251-52 tributary mode in, 64, 69, 77 mercantilism in, 179, 187

Arendt, Hannah, 217 Argentina, 137, 181 Aron, Raymond, 218 Arrighi, Giovanni, 231-33 “Asiatic” mode of production, 53 false characterization of, 9, 12, 45, 47, 48

tributary mode and, 58, 61-63, 102 Assyria, 77

Ataturk, Kemal, 72, 73, 137, 196 Austro-Hungarian Emprire, 106 Austro-Marxists, 106, 112, 122 Australia, 73, 91, 93

Babeuf, Gracchus, 75 Babylonia, 77

Bakhunin, Michel, 108, 109 Banu, Ion, 69

Barbarian world, 17, 19, 253

communal mode and, 44-45, 76 feudal development and, 62 Balkans, 111, 116 Bauer, Otto, 106, 111 Beaud, Michel, 205 Belgium (Flanders), 89, 128 Berdiaev, Nicolas, 213 Besangon, Alain, 218 Bodin, Jean, 83 Bohemia, 79 Bolshevism, 249 Bonapartism, 25 Boserup, Ester, 41 Bourgeois revolution, 66

capitalist development and, 72-76, 85-86, 254

class struggle and, 73-74, 96-97 imperialism and limits to, 192 national question and, 173-81 state and, 72-74

unequal development during, 9299, 113-14

Bourgeoisie, 49, 182, 199 in Brittany, 122-25 class struggle and, 54-55, 191 in Italy, 115-16, 119, 121 mercantile period and, 82, 86 national formation and, 106-07 world income and, 150-52 Brazil, 137, 181, 241 Bretton Woods system, 26 Brittany, 122-26 Buddhism, 52 Bukharin, Nikolai, 211 Buonarrotti, Filippo Michele, 75 Burma, 146, 179 Burnham, J., 214 Byzantium, 77, 80, 251

Cambodia, 146, 168, 179, 193, 220 Canada, 128

Capecelatro, E., 114, 117, 118, 120 Capitalism

accumulation on world scale and, 225-30, 233, 252 bourgeois revolutions and, 72-76, 85-86, 254

class struggle and, 52-55, 65, 82, 85-89, 92-94, 149-50, 188, 232-33

crisis of, 229-30, 250-52 European emergence of, 6-7, 9, 15-16, 62-66, 171, 184-85 imperialism and limits to, 167, 174, 189-91, 193-98 mercantile, 18, 19, 81-93 socialist transition and, 182-83, 207-08

state and, 39, 214-18 as world system, 2-3, 16-18, 2122, 186, 187

Capitalist mode of production, 40, 49, 53, 84, 102

center-periphery relations and, 67, 10-11, 16-18, 107 homogenization and, 30-35 imperialism and, 228-29 limits to, as world system, 157-58 Marx’s analysis of, 132-33, 20607, 226

stages of development and, 4-11, 14, 71-76 state and, 24-25

Cardoso, Fernando Henrique, 168 Carlo, Antonio, 114, 117, 118, 120 Catholicism, 79-80 Center (capitalist countries)

capitalist system and, 6-7, 10-11, 16-18

competition between, 25-28, 232 class struggle in, 149-50, 188, 22829

homogenization and, 30-35 imperialist hegemony and, 202-04, 232-37, 242-43 national question and, 104-12 “regionalism” and, 113-29 working class in, 152-54,162, 164, 191, 193, 195, 196, 198, 20203,214-15,229,232-33,245 Center-periphery relations, 235 accumulation and, 170-73 capitalist mode and, 6-7, 10-11, 16-18, 107

class structure of imperialism and, 149-73

imperialism and, 189-205, 243-44 international division of labor and,

131-49, 240-43,253 in mercantile period, 84-85, 88-91 national question and, 173-81 regionalism and, 129-30 three worlds concept and, 218-19 Chaliand, Gerard, 197 Charles V, 89

Chartism, 96, 105, 110, 187 Chayanov, A. V., 40 Chesneaux, Jean, 53, 63

Chile, 181 China, 72, 146, 196

cultural revolution in, 245, 255 socialist, 16, 38, 168, 179, 193, 199, 220

Soviet Union analyzed by, 207, 208, 219, 222-24 as tributary society, 6, 14, 17,48, 59, 64, 67, 69-70, 99 Christianity, 52, 53, 61, 79-80 Circulation process, 44-45, 185-86, 204

Class(es), 2, 3, 42, 220

bourgeois and proletarian line on, 28-30

in center, 228-29 center-periphery relations and, 190— 92

imperialism and structure of, 149— 73

socialist transition and, 183, 209-10 stages of development and, 5, 13 state and, 220, 230-31, 235 Class struggle, 8, 14, 176, 208

bourgeois and proletariat, 92, 192— 93, 200-01

bourgeois revolution and, 73-74, 96-97

bourgeoisie and, 54-55, 191 in capitalist center, 149-50, 188, 232-33

for communal and tributary modes, 52-55, 65

historical development and, 2, 1011, 13-14, 23

imperialism and, 163-66, 168, 229-30

during mercantile period, 82, 8589, 92-94

national formation and, 105-12 national liberation movements and, 197-98

productive forces and, 125-26 socialist revolution and, 253-54 Soviet development and, 212, 24243

COMECON, 222

Commodity production

globalization of, 163, 226, 233 and mass-market in periphery, 132, 137

precapitalist, 57, 60, 84 Communal formations, 36-45 Communal mode of production, 4-5, 9, 12

and absence of class struggle, 52-53 property relations and, 49-50 two paths of development and, 5859

Communism, 4, 5

capitalist development and, 7, 9 socialist revolutions and, 193-94, 199, 207

Communist parties (West), 207, 215 Communist Party (U.S.), 129

Comparative advantage theory, 146 Confucianism, 52, 53, 67, 70, 252 Congo, 176, 179

Coquery-Vidrovitch, Catherine, 167 Cox, Oliver, 66, 83, 88 Crisis, 22, 24

ancient and capitalist, compared, 250-52

contradictions of relations of production and, 229-30 and imperialism, 27-28, 167-68, 187-88, 201-02, 238-40 socialist transition and, 182-83 state and, 230-32 Croce, Benedetto, 114 Cromwell, Oliver, 85, 86, 95, 105 Cuba, 137, 146, 193, 197,210, 220 Czechoslavkia, 210, 222

Democracy, 25, 29, 215 Denmark, 105 Development value, 215-17 Dhoquois, Guy, 4 Division of labor

capitalist development and international, 84, 102 imperialism and unequal, 26-28, 131-49, 230-31, 239-41 sexual, 40

Dobb, Maurice, 51, 96 Domestic mode of production, 39-43 Domination, See Exploitation Dumont, Louis, 67

Economic base (infrastructure), 3, 15, 36-37, 48, 254 Egypt, 6, 59, 137, 223

contemporary development in, 143-44, 179,210-11 mercantile, 116, 187 tributary mode and, 17, 77 Engels, Friedrich, 22, 55, 82, 183,

249

anthropology and, 36-37, 41, 45 national question and, 106-07,109, 179-80

England (Great Britain), 16, 25 capitalist formation in, 72, 79, 105, 110, 170-71

imperialist hierarchy and, 236 in mercantile period, 84, 89-92, 231-32

Irish question and, 96, 105, 110, 126-27, 228

English revolution, 72, 73, 85, 86, 95 Ethiopia, 42, 179, 222, 230 Ethnic groups, 19-20, 128-29, 153, 175-77

Eurocommunism, 215, 246 Europe, 14, 48, 221

bourgeois revolutions in, 92-99, 112-14

capitalist development in, 6-7, 9, 15-16, 62-66, 171, 184-85 feudalism and, 17-18, 58-60, 76-81, 100-02

imperialist development and, 236— 37, 243

mercantile period and, 82-91 national formation and, 105-12 European Common Market, 26, 120 Exchange, See Market relations Exchange value

capitalist mode and, 53 development value and, 216-17 tributary mode and, 51

Exploitation

determining level of, 157, 161 domination and, 42 production relations and, 100-01 women's oppression and, 38-41

Feudalism, 3, 5, 8, 44, 53

capitalist development and, 17-19, 81-88, 133, 184 cities of, 64-65

Marxist analysis of, 46-47, 168 peasant struggles and, 92 slavery and, 58-61 tributary mode and, 60-64, 69-70, 76-87,99-102,251.

Flanders (Belgium), 89, 128 Fossaert, Robert, 215, 216 France, 16, 25, 97, 234

Brittany’s development and, 122-26

capitalist development in, 79, 84, 89, 92, 105, 108, 110 imperialist hierarchy and, 236 Franqois I, 16, 25, 97, 234 Frank, Andre Gunder, 66, 83, 88, 168, 170-72 Frankfurt school, 217

Gallicanism, 80, 89 General Agreement on Tarriffs and Trade (GATT), 26 Germany

ancient or barbarian, 19, 61, 62 capitalist development in, 79, 80, 91,96, 115

imperialist hierarchy and, 236 modern, 16, 72, 232, 234 unification of, 72, 73, 106 Gerontocracy, 43

Godelier, Maurice, 37, 38,48, 62, 63, 69

Gramsci, Antonio, 114, 117-19, 121, 215

Greece, 58-60, 77, 116 Ground rent, 116, 118, 119, 162 Guerin, Daniel, 86, 98 Guevaraism, 181

Guilds, 64, 65, 86 Gum, Yannick, 122, 124

Hanseatic League, 79-81 Hegel, G. W. F., 75 Hilferding, Rudolf, 214, 231 Hilton, Rodney, 46, 51, 64, 83 Hinduism, 52, 67, 251 Historical materialism, 6, 166, 199, 250

anthropology and, 36-43 political economy and, 22-23, 28 universal history and, 3-4, 15 History, 1-4

nations with and without, 107, 109 praxis and, 254-55 See also Universal history Hittites, 77

Hobsbawm, Eric, 94, 119 Hobson, H. A., 231 Holland, 79, 89-90, 105 Homogenization, 3, 6, 11 imperialism and, 199, 240 tributary mode and, 78, 126 unequal accumulation and, 30-35 Hoyakawa, Jiro, 68 .

Hungary, 79, 91, 96, 115, 210

Idealism, 15, 50 Ideology, 4, 27, 202 class and, 29—30, 37-38 Soviet Union and, 211-13 state capitalist mode and, 217-18 transition to capitalism and, 93-94, 254

tributary mode and, 52, 79 Imperialism, 6, 44, 55, 75, 114, 236 capitalist crisis and, 27-28,

187-88, 201-02 capitalist mode and, 228-29 center hegemony and, 202-04, 232-37, 242-43 center-periphery relations and, 189-205, 243-44 class structure of contemporary, 149-73

globalization of law of value and, 225-30, 233, 252

hierarchy of, 236-37 international division of labor and, 26-28, 131-49, 230-31, 239-41

Marxist analysis of, 179-80, 189-95, 198-201,249-50, 253-56

national liberation movements and, 189-202

national question and, 173-81 phases of, 137, 140-43 Soviet social, 222-24 state and, 230-35

Import substitution strategy, 137, 235 India, 6, 176, 196

tributary mode and, 59, 61, 67,96, 109,251-52 Indonesia, 179

Industrial Revolution, 95-96, 114 Industrialization in Italy, 115-17

of periphery, 136-41, 143-48, 239 See also Productive forces; Technology

Infrastructure, See Economic base Institute for Italian Reconstruction, 117

International Monetary Fund, 27, 236 Iran, 179, 230, 238, 241 Iraq, 57

Ireland, 96, 105, 110, 126-27, 228 Italy, 16, 234, 243

capitalist development in, 66, 72, 80,81,89,91, 187 imperialist hierarchy and, 236 unequal development and, 114-22 unification of, 72, 73, 106

Jaffe, Hosea, 170 Japan, 9, 72,91,92,96,218, 221 feudalism in, 57, 61, 64-66 imperialist hierarchy and, 236, 243 Meiji revolution and, 72, 73

Kautsky, Karl, 22, 33, 40, 106, 111, 112, 169, 196,214,235 Kay, Geoffrey, 204

Khan, Genghis, 252 Kinship, 37, 42, 49, 52 Korea (socialist), 146, 179, 193, 220 Koyre, Alexander, 110, 213

Labor (labor power)

law of value and, 40, 226-28 productive forces and, 41-42 unequal exchange and peripheral, 134-35

Labor force, 25, 60, 226-27 Language, 33, 42, 70, 78, 111, 175, Laos, 193, 220

Latin America, 167-68, 179, 224 Lautier, Bruno, 41 Lenin, V. I., 40, 71,96, 106, 132, 179, 183, 185

imperialism analyzed by, 190, 192, 193,201,205,206,231 national formations and, 106, 108-09, 112 Leninism, 254 Levellers, 95 Lipietz, Alain, 41 Louis Philippe, 25

Luxemburg, Rosa, 106, 111-12, 179, 185, 188, 215

Madagascar, 179 MaoTse-tung, 183, 206 Maoism (Maoists), 38, 52, 201, 206-08, 219, 222-24 Marie, Alain, 37, 38, 42 Market relations, 174

center-periphery relations and, 134-35, 174

tributary mode and, 51-52, 56-57, 80

U.S. hegemony and world, 235 Marx, Karl, 8, 34, 52, 183, 193, 249 anthropology and, 39, 40, 45 capitalist mode analyzed by,

132-33,206-07, 226 on exchange, 56

feudalism analyzed by, 46-47, 55, 71

and historical materialism, 4, 11-13

mercantile transition analyzed by, 82, 83, 94

national question and, 106-10,126, 179-80, 198 Marxism, 132

Austro-, 106, 112, 122 bourgeois revolution and, 75, 106 European ethnocentrism and peripheral analysis of, 6, 9, 166-69, 184-85, 188-89, 204-07, 245-46, 249 feudalism analyzed by, 46-47, 168 imperialism analyzed by, 179-80, 189-93, 298-301, 249-50, 253-56

state and, 230-32 vulgar, 38, 58, 155-56 Meiji revolution, 72, 73 Meillassoux, Claude, 42-43, 45, 67, 168

Mercantile capitalism, 18, 19, 81-93 Meridionalists, 118, 119 Merrington, John, 64 Mesopotamia, 77 Mexican revolution, 72, 109 Michalet, Charles, 205 Mode(s) of production, 3, 11, 164, 250,

class and, 2, 29 as unifying principle, 50-51 Mohammed Ali, 116, 187 Monarchies, 63, 65, 66, 69, 82, 88 Mongols, 251

Monopolies (transnational firms), 201 imperialist break and, 172-73, 191 periphery and, 138-40, 162, 164 state and, 230-32, 235 Montesquieu, Baron, 47, 53 Morocco, 179 Murat, Joachim, 121

Nasser, Gamal Abdel, 218 Nasserism, 72, 181 Nation(s), 2, 29, 30

accumulation and, 127-28 ethnic groups and, 19-20 three worlds concept and, 218-24

National liberation movements, 2, 27, 130, 173

contradictory nature of, 184-89 imperialism and, 136-37, 167-68, 238-39

national unity and, 176-79 peripheral social progress and, 141, 144-49

socialism and, 180, 189-202, 252-56

three worlds concept and, 220-23 National question, 3, 28-30, 103 center and, 104-12 Marx and Engels on, 106-10, 126, 179-80, 198

in periphery, 183-81, 209-10 Nationalism, 27, 35, 85, 212-13 Nehru, Jawaharla, 218 Neoclassical economic theory, 41, 56 New England model, 57, 91, 96, 118 New Zealand, 7 Nigeria, 176

Nkrumah, Kwame, 176, 178

Organization of African Unity (OAU), 176, 218

Ottoman Empire, 77, 89, 91, 106, 116,251 Ouvrierists, 245

Pakistan, 176 Palestine, 181 Palmerston, H. J. T., 108 Pannekoek, Anton, 106, 112 Pan-Slavic Congress, 108 Paris Commune, 104, 105, 109, 187, 209, 245, 255 Peasantry, 42-43, 53

alliance with workers, 166-67, 192, 208, 246

in Brittany, 122-25 class struggle and, 54-55, 75, 92-99, 167, 170 in Italy, 115, 119 mercantile period and, 86 national revolutions and, 107-09 in periphery, 157-58, 191-94 Peripheral national bourgeoisie

center-periphery relations and, 135, 136-37, 175, 177, 192-95, 197-99

income of, 150-52 national capitalist development and, 138-42, 174 Periphery

capitalist development and, 6-7, 10-11, 16-18, 184-88 class structure in, 150 crisis and, 238-41 homogenization and, 30-35, 199, 240

national question and, 173-81, 209-10

state and, 139, 174-78,238 Peru, 181

Petty bourgeoisie, 152, 154-55, 160, 203

Phoenicia, 77

Poland, 79,85,90, 111-12,210 Polevoi, N. A., 110 Political economy, 22-23, 28 Politics, 21, 38-40, 43 See also Class struggle Portugal, 81, 90, 91, 98, 105, 124, 243 Pouillon, Francois, 42 Poulantzas, Nicos, 203 Precapitalist societies class and, 12-13

commodity production and, 56-57, 60, 84

Marxist analysis of, 179-80 peasant revolts and, 92 Productive forces, 4, 53, 182

capitalist development and, 6, 120 class struggle and, 125-26 as motive force of history, 13-14 peripheral development and, 135, 170, 225

productivity of labor and, 41-42 rate of surplus value and, 132 and relations ofproduction, 48-50, 54, 60, 100-01,216, 246,250 Soviet development and, 211 See also Industrialization; Technology

Productivity

globalized working class and, 227 productive forces and, 41-42 value transfer and, 159-66 Profits, 132, 134, 150, 157, 200 Proletariat, 100, 191 in Brittany, 124-25 capitalist development and, 95-98, 133

in Italy, 119-20 socialist revolution and, 192-93 working class and, 152-54 Property, 49-50, 58-59 Protectionism, 115, 117-18, 120 Prussia, 90, 96, 115

Qarmat communism, 53 Quebec nationalism, 128

Raw materials, 140, 143, 146, 147 Regionalism, 113-30, 235 Relations of production, 18, 84 crisis and, 229-30 and productive forces, 48-50, 54, 60, 100-01, 216, 246, 250 Religion, 29-30, 61 feudalism and, 79-80 tributary mode and, 52, 53 Revolution

bourgeois and peasant, 72-75 imperialism and, 196-97, 220-24 Marxist theory of, 249-50, 253-54 Rey, P.-P., 53, 166, 167, 197 Rhodes, Cecil, 55, 127, 188 Ricardo, David, 23, 75 Rizzi, B., 214 Romano, Sergio, 114 Rome (Roman Empire), 17, 58-60, 101, 243 crisis of, 249-53 feudalism and, 76-79, 87 Romeo, Rosario, 114, 119 Rostow, W. W., 205 Rumania, 96, 210 Russia, 72, 79, 101, 112

mercantile period and, 90, 91, 115 Russian revolution, 86, 104, 108, 187, 196,215, 245,249,255

Scandinavia, 79

Second International, 34, 179, 254 Eurocommunism and, 215 imperialist hegemony and, 192, 193, 195, 201, 206

Self-management, 182, 186, 208, 246 Sereni, E., 114, 118 Serfdom, 11-12, 58, 65, 66, 81, 84, 102

Shiism, 53 Siberia, 81, 93, 101 Slavery, 5, 10-12,251

ancient society and, 43-44, 77 capitalist development and, 84 production relations and, 100-02 tributary mode and, 58-61, 99 Soboul, Albert, 94, 97 Social democracy, 26-27, 172, 188, 246

monopoly capitalism and, 191-94,

201

Soviet socialism and, 211 state capitalism and, 214-15 See also Second International Social formation, 2, 3, 21-28, 228 Socialism, 66, 173, 182 accumulation and, 32 contradiction of, 207-18 de-alienated consciousness and, 254-55

imperialist system and, 131, 137 national liberation and, 180, 189-202, 252-56 peripheral social progress and, 146, 148

state mode and, 218-19 utopian, 11, 13, 15 Socialist parties, 111 Sociology, 29 Somalia, 222 South Africa, 230 South Korea, 227, 241 Soviet Union (USSR), 7, 16, 35, 146 anti-imperialist movement and, 196-97

contradictions of socialism and, 207-18

as new type class society, 219, 222-24, 242,246 three worlds concept and, 218-19, 222-23

See also Russia Spain, 16, 66, 127

capitalist development and, 77, 81, 84, 90,91, 105, 187 Sraffa, Pierro, 23, 165 Sri Lanka, 179

Stage(s) of development, 187, 245 capitalist mode and, 4—11, 14, 71-76

center-periphery relations and,

133-34

necessity of, 4-8 Stalin, Josef, 106, 179 State, 2, 5,43, 217

accumulation and, 21, 28, 127-28 bourgeois revolution and, 72-74 capitalist development and, 24-25, 84-88, 116-17 class and, 220, 230-31,235 money regulation and, 24-26 national formations and, 19, 42, 107

periphery and, 139, 174-78, 238 productive forces and, 42, 43 regionalism and, 129-30 social formation and, 21-28 socialist transformation and, 209 tributary mode and, 61-62, 65, 76 Statist mode of production, 10, 11, 38, 254

evolution toward, 246-47 socialist and capitalist, 207-08, 213-24

Strasser, Josef, 106 Strasser, Otto, 33, 106, 111, 112 Structuralism, 13, 15, 37, 50 Subimperialism, 143-44 Sudan, 42, 143-44 Sunnite Islam, 53 Superimperialism, 214, 235 Superstructure, 3, 10, 254 tributary mode and, 52-53 Surplus, 5, 69

agricultural, 42

ancient and capitalist crisis and, 250, 252

Italy’s development and, 116-18 mode of production and, 50-51 state and class formation and, 48-50

Surplus labor, 5

Marxist analysis of, 165-69 in periphery, 158-64 Surplus value

imperialism and peripheral, 158-61, 191-92, 225-26,239 Marxist analysis of, 165-68, 203-05

productive forces and, 132 Sweden, 90, 105, 207, 211 Sweezy, Paul, 8, 57, 60 Switzerland, 128

Taiwan, 241

Takahashi, Kohachiro, 51 Taoism, 53

Technology, 32-33, 100, 214, 216 feudalism and, 81, 84 peripheral dependence and, 138-40

Soviet development and, 211-13 See also Industrialization; Productive forces Thailand, 179

Third International, 179, 180 Third world, See Periphery “Three worlds” concept, 218-24 Tito, Marshal, 218 Tokei, Ferenc, 48, 58, 62, 63, 69, 184 Transition period(s), 4, 14, 141-42 crisis and, 249-52 lack of law for, 18, 86-87 to capitalism, 7-9, 12, 63, 65-66, 71-102

to socialism, 74,182,188, 207-11, 252-53, 255-56

Tributary mode of production, 8, 9, 10,49, 55

capitalist development and, 4-6, 65-68, 99-101

characteristics of, 50-53, 250-51 class-state dominance in, 17 feudalism and, 60-64, 69-70, 76-87, 99-102, 251 Trotsky, Leon, 106, 109, 179 Turkey, 72, 73, 116, 137

Ukraine, 81, 93 UN Conference on Trade and

Development (UNCTAD),

148, 200

UN Food and Agricultural Organization, 160 Unemployment

in periphery, 138, 149-50,

153-54, 163, 174 state regulation of, 25, 27 Soviet mode and, 212 Unequal development, 14-15, 110 in ancient and feudal world, 76-81 in bourgeois revolution, 92-99, 113-14

centers and, 115-30 European development and, 7, 63, 82-91

revolutionary development and, 249-50

universal history and, 2, 3, 15-19 . Unequal exchange, 168

center-periphery relations and, 134 Marxist analysis of, 44-45, 204 social structure and, 172-73 United States, 16, 72, 187

capitalist development in, 57, 91, 96, 105, 118, 171 “three worlds” concept and, 218, 221-24

unequal development and, 128-29 S world hegemony by, 232-37, c 1    242-43

% Universal history

s'i historical materialism and, 3—4, 15 ! periodization and, 102-03 fr, | unequal development and, 2, 3,

§ 1    15-19

cdJse value -

m | homogenization and, 31-32 ££ | tributary mode and, 51, 52, 56

Value, law of

exchange and, 56 imperialism and globalization of, 225-30, 233, 252 precapitalist production and, 57 value transfer and, 165, 169 vulgar Marxist computation of,

156-57

See also Suplus value; Use value Value transfer, 159-65, 169-70, 216 Vergopoulos, Kostas, 168 Vietnam, 146, 168, 179, 193, 220, 222

Vilar, Pierre, 83

Wafd, 137, 196 Wages

imperialism and, 226-28 mercantile transition and, 83 in periphery, 132, 138 Wallerstein, Immanuel, 66, 80, 83-84, 88-89 Weber, Max, 11, 13, 64 Wolpe, H„ 167 Women, 38-41 Workers’ movement, 241

imperialism and, 193, 195, 196,

.    198, 202-03, 245

labor aristocracy and, 214-15 ouvrierist position and, 245-46 state competition and, 232-33 See also Second International Working class

divisions within, 26, 151-54, 226, 227, 233-34, 246 globalization of, 226 in periphery and center, 151-54, 162, 164, 191, 229 revolutionary strategy for, 234, 237 technocracy and, 214 Worker-peasant alliance, 166-67, 192, 208, 246

World Bank, 27, 241 Yugoslavia, 212, 220 Zimbabwe, 230

Zitara, Nicola, 114, 117, 118, 120